Basic Concepts and Distinctions 1 Logic Keith Burgess-Jackson 14 August 2017

Similar documents
Aquinas s Third Way Keith Burgess-Jackson 24 September 2017

IDHEF Chapter 2 Why Should Anyone Believe Anything At All?

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

HOW TO ANALYZE AN ARGUMENT

1.5 Deductive and Inductive Arguments

A Brief Introduction to Key Terms

Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

2.3. Failed proofs and counterexamples

What Is a Normative Ethical Theory? Keith Burgess-Jackson 26 December 2017

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014

Is Epistemic Probability Pascalian?

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

A Primer on Logic Part 1: Preliminaries and Vocabulary. Jason Zarri. 1. An Easy $10.00? a 3 c 2. (i) (ii) (iii) (iv)

Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe.

Courses providing assessment data PHL 202. Semester/Year

WHY SHOULD ANYONE BELIEVE ANYTHING AT ALL?

Chapter 1 - Basic Training

1.6 Validity and Truth

PHI Introduction Lecture 4. An Overview of the Two Branches of Logic

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER VI CONDITIONS OF IMMEDIATE INFERENCE

1/12. The A Paralogisms

A s a contracts professional, from

INTERMEDIATE LOGIC Glossary of key terms

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

An Introduction to. Formal Logic. Second edition. Peter Smith, February 27, 2019

The Appeal to Reason. Introductory Logic pt. 1

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

THE FORM OF REDUCTIO AD ABSURDUM J. M. LEE. A recent discussion of this topic by Donald Scherer in [6], pp , begins thus:

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

A R G U M E N T S I N A C T I O N

Study Guides. Chapter 1 - Basic Training

Introducing Our New Faculty

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC FOR METAPHYSICIANS

Theological Voluntarism: Objections and Replies Keith Burgess-Jackson 7 January 2017

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

1.5. Argument Forms: Proving Invalidity

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

Early Russell on Philosophical Grammar

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Powerful Arguments: Logical Argument Mapping

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Philosophy Courses-1

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY FALL 2014 COURSE DESCRIPTIONS

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

ARGUMENTS. Arguments. arguments

ELEMENTS OF LOGIC. 1.1 What is Logic? Arguments and Propositions

Action in Special Contexts

A Solution to the Gettier Problem Keota Fields. the three traditional conditions for knowledge, have been discussed extensively in the

Please visit our website for other great titles:

PHILOSOPHY 102 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC PRACTICE EXAM 1. W# Section (10 or 11) 4. T F The statements that compose a disjunction are called conjuncts.

Phil 3304 Introduction to Logic Dr. David Naugle. Identifying Arguments i

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Overview of Today s Lecture

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

Theories of propositions

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

1.2. What is said: propositions

Should We Assess the Basic Premises of an Argument for Truth or Acceptability?

Scanlon on Double Effect

Ibuanyidanda (Complementary Reflection), African Philosophy and General Issues in Philosophy

Argumentation Module: Philosophy Lesson 7 What do we mean by argument? (Two meanings for the word.) A quarrel or a dispute, expressing a difference

Lecture 3 Arguments Jim Pryor What is an Argument? Jim Pryor Vocabulary Describing Arguments

PHILOSOPHY EOLOGY. Volume 8 N der 3 UNIVERSITY QUARTERLY MARQUETTE

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Philosophy Courses-1


PHI 244. Environmental Ethics. Introduction. Argument Worksheet. Argument Worksheet. Welcome to PHI 244, Environmental Ethics. About Stephen.

MCQ IN TRADITIONAL LOGIC. 1. Logic is the science of A) Thought. B) Beauty. C) Mind. D) Goodness

Part II: How to Evaluate Deductive Arguments

Necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pp. i-ix, 379. ISBN $35.00.

A. Problem set #3 it has been posted and is due Tuesday, 15 November

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Haberdashers Aske s Boys School

Supplementary Section 6S.7

PHIL 176: Death (Spring, 2007)

Chapter 6. Fate. (F) Fatalism is the belief that whatever happens is unavoidable. (55)

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

On Interpretation. Section 1. Aristotle Translated by E. M. Edghill. Part 1

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1

SECTION 2 BASIC CONCEPTS

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Logic for Computer Science - Week 1 Introduction to Informal Logic

Academic argument does not mean conflict or competition; an argument is a set of reasons which support, or lead to, a conclusion.

Instructor s Manual 1

2016 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

Moore on External Relations

2017 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

Predicate logic. Miguel Palomino Dpto. Sistemas Informáticos y Computación (UCM) Madrid Spain

Chadwick Prize Winner: Christian Michel THE LIAR PARADOX OUTSIDE-IN

1/5. The Critique of Theology

Future Contingents, Non-Contradiction and the Law of Excluded Middle Muddle

(Some More) Vagueness

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

But we may go further: not only Jones, but no actual man, enters into my statement. This becomes obvious when the statement is false, since then

What are Truth-Tables and What Are They For?

1. Lukasiewicz s Logic

THE LARGER LOGICAL PICTURE

Deduction. Of all the modes of reasoning, deductive arguments have the strongest relationship between the premises

Logic Book Part 1! by Skylar Ruloff!

Transcription:

Basic Concepts and Distinctions 1 Logic Keith Burgess-Jackson 14 August 2017 Terms in boldface type are defined somewhere in this handout. 1. Logic is the science of implication, or of valid inference (based on such implication). 2 2. Logical implication (also known as entailment ) is a particular relation (one of many) between propositions (or propositional forms). It is not to be confused with material implication, so the adjectives logical and material are necessary (unless the context makes it clear which type of implication is intended). One proposition logically implies ( entails ) a second proposition when it is logically impossible for the first to be true while the second is false. Example: x is (exactly) six feet tall logically implies x is at least six feet tall, for it is logically impossible for x to be (exactly) six feet tall without x being at least six feet tall. Note that the second of these propositions does not logically imply the first, for x may be at least six feet tall without x being (exactly) six feet tall. Some pairs of proposition logically imply each other for example, x is (exactly) six feet tall and x is 72 inches tall. Henceforth, impossible will mean logically impossible ; possible will mean logically possible ; and necessary will mean logically necessary. 3 3. Inference (or reasoning) is the psychological process by which one proposition (known as the conclusion) is derived from, or arrived at on the basis of, one or more other propositions (known as the premises). The word inference may be used to refer to the process itself (i.e., the act of inferring) or to the product of the process (i.e., the thing inferred). For example, suppose I infer from the fact that there are dark clouds approaching that it will rain soon. I have performed an act of inference (or reasoning). My inference (conclusion) is that it will rain soon. Suppose I infer from the fact that Donald J. Trump is the 45th president of the United States that there have been 44 other presidents (even if I can t name 1 I thank my colleague Dan Giberman for helpful comments on an earlier version of this handout. 2 Morris R. Cohen and Ernest Nagel, An Introduction to Logic (New York and Burlingame: Harcourt, Brace & World, 1962 [first published in 1934 as Book I of An Introduction to Logic and Scientific Method]), 13. By implication, Cohen and Nagel mean logical implication, not material implication. See the Appendix of this handout for alternative definitions of logic. The English word logic derives from the Greek word logos, which means word or reason. 3 The reason for this stipulation is that there are different types of possibility (and hence different types of impossibility and necessity). A given act, for example, may be psychologically (or morally) possible, impossible, or necessary. A given event may be physically possible, impossible, or necessary. Since our concern in this course is logical possibility, impossibility, and necessity, rather than some other kind, there is no need to keep using the adjective logical. 1

them). I have performed an act of inference (or reasoning). My inference (conclusion) is that there have been 44 presidents other than Donald J. Trump. 4. Every inference (using the word now to refer to the process rather than to the product of the process) can be expressed as, or transformed into, an argument, and every argument is the expression, or statement, of an inference. The purpose of an argument is to persuade or convince someone to believe something (the conclusion) by providing reasons, evidence, or grounds for it. (These reasons, evidence, or grounds constitute the premises.) Thus, an argument consists of two or more propositions, one of which, the conclusion, is claimed (by the arguer) to follow from the other or others, the premises. The act or process of arguing is known as argumentation. 4 5. Every argument, by definition, involves a claim (by the arguer) that its conclusion follows from its premises. Some claims are stronger than others: a. If one s claim is that the conclusion cannot be false, given the truth of the premises, then one s argument is deductive. (Another way to put this is that, in a deductive argument, the arguer claims that the premises logically imply, or entail, the conclusion.) b. If one s claim is merely that the conclusion is unlikely to be false, given the truth of the premises, then one s argument is inductive. (The arguer in this case does not claim that the premises logically imply, or entail, the conclusion.) Deduction is to necessity as induction is to probability. What follows is a deductive argument (for almost certainly the arguer would claim that the premises logically imply the conclusion): All mammals are animals. All dogs are mammals. Therefore, All dogs are animals. 5 Here, by way of contrast, is an inductive argument (for almost certainly the arguer would not claim that the premises logically imply the conclusion): Most professors are atheists. Jones is a professor. 4 I will focus on arguments rather than inferences in the remainder of this handout, but much of what I say about arguments can also be said about inferences. 5 Another example: Every mammal has a heart; all horses are mammals; therefore, every horse has a heart. (From Wesley C. Salmon, Logic, 3d ed. [Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1984], 14.) 2

Therefore, Jones is an atheist. 6 The focus of this course is deduction. Our concern, in other words, will be arguments in which the arguer claims that the premises logically imply, or entail, the conclusion. 6. Every deductive argument (and therefore every inference expressed by a deductive argument) is either valid or invalid, depending on whether the claim of logical implication made by the arguer is true. If the premises do in fact logically imply the conclusion, then the arguer s claim is true and the argument is valid. If the premises do not in fact logically imply the conclusion, then the arguer s claim is false and the argument is invalid. Note that whether an argument is deductive or inductive depends on the strength of the claim being made by the arguer. Whether a deductive argument is valid or invalid depends on the truth of the claim being made by the arguer. It is important not to conflate these points. Strictly speaking, only deductive arguments are valid or invalid. We may, if we like, say that all inductive arguments are invalid, but this is misleading, for it implies (or might be taken to imply) that there is something wrong with inductive arguments. There is nothing wrong with inductive arguments. 7 Some inductive arguments are cogent, in the sense that (a) they have true premises and (b) their premises make their conclusions probable. Example: Most dogs have a tail of at least one inch in length; Shelbie is a dog; therefore, Shelbie has a tail of at least one inch in length. Perhaps it s best to say that the terms valid and invalid don t apply to inductive arguments, i.e., that inductive arguments are neither valid nor invalid. They belong in category 3 of the following taxonomy: 8 6 Another example: Every horse that has ever been observed has had a heart; therefore, every horse has a heart. (From Salmon, Logic, 3d ed., 14.) 7 Without some type of inductive reasoning, we would have no grounds for predicting that night will continue to follow day, that the seasons will continue to occur in their customary sequence, or that sugar will continue to taste sweet. All such knowledge of the future, and much else as well, depends upon the power of inductive arguments to support conclusions that go beyond the data presented in their premises (Salmon, Logic, 3d ed., 18). 8 A taxonomy is a classification scheme. The taxonomy in the text is both jointly exhaustive and mutually exclusive (because of how the categories are defined). To say that it is jointly exhaustive is to say that every argument goes in at least one of its three categories. To say that it is mutually exclusive is to say that no argument goes in more than one of its three categories. It follows that every argument goes in exactly one of its three categories. Every argument, in other words, is either (1) a valid (i.e., truth-preserving) deductive argument, (2) an invalid (i.e., non-truth-preserving) deductive argument, or (3) an argument that is neither valid nor invalid. Category 3 could, of course, be subdivided, for it contains all inductive arguments, some of which are cogent (such as the one in the text) and some of which are not cogent (e.g., Eighty-five percent of the readers of the New York Times oppose capital punishment; therefore, 85% of Americans oppose capital punishment ). 3

Valid 1 Arguments Not Valid Invalid Not Invalid 2 3 7. Ideally, one would like one s argument to have both of the following properties: necessity and informativeness. That is, one would like one s conclusion (a) to follow necessarily from (i.e., to be entailed by) one s premises and (b) to go beyond one s premises in terms of the amount of information it conveys. Unfortunately, no argument can have both of these properties. To get necessity, one must forgo informativeness. To get informativeness, one must forgo necessity. Let us see why. In a (valid) deductive argument, the conclusion may convey either the same amount of information as the conjunction of the premises or less information than the conjunction of the premises, but it may not convey more information than the conjunction of the premises. Consider the following classic argument: All men (i.e., human beings) are mortal. Socrates is a man (i.e., a human being). Therefore, Socrates is mortal. The conclusion, which is about a particular human being (namely, Socrates), conveys less information than the conjunction of the premises. (The first premise alone conveys information about many human beings.) Now consider a typical inductive argument: On nine of the past 10 occasions in which weather conditions were as they are now, it rained within six hours. Therefore, It will rain within six hours. The conclusion conveys more information than the premise. The premise is about the past; the conclusion is about the future. We might say that deduction purchases necessity at the cost of informativeness, whereas induction purchases informativeness at the cost of necessity. 9 Both types of argument, however, are capable of conferring knowledge: a. The knowledge conferred by a valid deductive argument consists in making explicit (in the conclusion) what is implicit (in the premises). 9 See Wesley C. Salmon, The Foundations of Scientific Inference (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1967), 8. 4

b. The knowledge conferred by a cogent inductive argument consists in extending (in the conclusion) what is already known (in the premises). We may think of the choice between necessity and informativeness as the tragedy of logic, because in one of its senses the word tragedy means a sad event or a calamity. 10 The calamity is that we can t have everything that we want or need. 11 8. Propositions are bearers of truth value. In this course, we shall assume that there are two (and only two) truth values: true and false. 12 Here are two Laws of Thought: 13 a. Every proposition is either true or false, i.e., the truth values true and false are jointly exhaustive (this is known as the Law of Excluded Middle or, more precisely, the Law of Bivalence); and b. No proposition is both true and false, i.e., the truth values true and false are mutually exclusive (this is known as the Law of Noncontradiction). 14 Sentences, unlike propositions, are linguistic entities, which means that they are in particular languages, such as English, German, Swahili, or Latin. Propositions, which are in no particular language, are what indicative (declarative) sentences express, assert, or signify. 15 Two different indicative (declarative) sentences (e.g., John loves Mary and Mary is loved by John [both of which are in English], or It is raining and Il pleut [the former of which is in English, the latter of which is in French]) can express, assert, or signify the same proposition. This is called synonymy. 16 A given indicative (declarative) sentence (e.g., Jones is happy ) can express, assert, or signify different propositions, depending on such things as (a) when it is uttered (Jones may be happy at one time but not at another) and (b) what its terms (e.g., Jones ) refer to (Adam Jones may be happy while Andruw Jones is not). This is called ambiguity. 10 The Oxford American Dictionary and Language Guide (1999), 1068. 11 You may have heard the term tragic choice. Suppose two or more people need life-saving medicine, but that I, a physician, have only enough medicine for one of them. Obviously, I would like to save all the needy people, and would do so if I could, but the situation constrains me. I must make a tragic choice. 12 In what is called a many-valued logic, there are more than two truth values. 13 Strictly speaking, these are logical implications or entailments of the Laws of Thought, but we will ignore that complication here. 14 While every proposition is either true or false and no proposition is both true and false, it doesn t follow that we always know which truth value a given proposition has. Take the proposition that Abraham Lincoln thought about his son Robert five seconds before he (Abraham) was shot. This proposition is either true or false and it is not both true and false, but we will probably never know its truth value. (Query: What would constitute evidence for its truth? What would constitute evidence for its falsity?) 15 Sentence is to proposition as numeral is to number. 16 Some people refer to it as synonymity. 5

9. A valid argument is a deductive argument that has the following (desirable) property: it is logically impossible for its premises to be true while its conclusion is false. (If it is logically possible for a given deductive argument s premises to be true while its conclusion is false, then the argument is invalid.) Valid arguments are truth-preserving: a. If the premises of a valid argument are true, then its conclusion must be true. b. If the conclusion of a valid argument is false, then at least one of its premises must be false. Note that there can be a valid argument with false premises as well as an invalid argument with true premises. An example of the former is: Texas is east of the Mississippi River. FALSE. Therefore, Something is east of the Mississippi River. An example of the latter is: Something is east of the Mississippi River. TRUE. Therefore, Texas is east of the Mississippi River. Note also that, while all valid arguments are deductive, not all deductive arguments are valid. What makes an argument deductive (as we saw earlier) is the strength of the claim being made by the arguer. What makes a deductive argument valid (we are now seeing) is the truth of the claim being made by the arguer. This course, as I said, is concerned exclusively with deduction. If you wish to study induction, you should take Fundamentals of Reasoning (PHIL 1301). 17 10. Validity (a property of some, but not all, deductive arguments) is valuable (i.e., worthy of being valued, not merely capable of being valued) for the sake of what it preserves, namely, truth. It is not valuable for its own sake. 18 Truth (i.e., true belief) is valuable because it is essential to knowledge. (One can t know falsehoods, though one can believe falsehoods.) Knowledge is valuable because it is a 17 The two courses may be taken in any order; neither of them is a prerequisite for the other. Some people disparage Fundamentals of Reasoning (which at some universities is known as Critical Thinking or Informal Logic) as baby logic. That s like saying that abnormal psychology is baby psychology or that microeconomics is baby economics. The two types of logic are different but equal. I recommend that both courses be taken by every student. 18 In other words, validity is extrinsically or instrumentally valuable, not intrinsically valuable. Validity is a means to an end, not an end in itself. In this respect, validity is like money and unlike, say, friendship, knowledge, pleasure, or beauty. 6

component of the good life. As the Greek philosopher Socrates put it (according to his disciple Plato), The unexamined life is not worth living. 19 11. Any argument that has a valid form is a valid argument. 20 If one s aim is to produce valid arguments, therefore, it is in one s interest to know as many valid argument forms as possible, so that one may make use of them. We will examine (i.e., you will learn) 58 valid argument forms in this course: 40 in propositional logic and 18 in predicate logic. See the handout entitled Valid Argument Forms for details. 12. The form of an argument is its skeleton the part that remains after its flesh has been removed. For example, the form of the argument No dogs are cats; therefore, no cats are dogs is No Ø are Ψ; therefore, no Ψ are Ø. Another argument with the same form is No animals are dogs; therefore, no dogs are animals. This shows that there can be two or more arguments of (with) the same form. (We might say that each of them instantiates the form.) Since validity has to do solely with the form of an argument (and not with its content, matter, or substance), if two arguments have the same specific form, 21 then either (a) both arguments are valid or (b) both arguments are invalid. 22 13. A sound argument is a valid argument all of whose premises are true. 23 It follows from this definition that: a. All sound arguments have true conclusions. (Note the difference between x following from a definition and x being, or being part of, a definition.) 24 19 See Plato s Apology. 20 It might be thought that any argument that has an invalid form is an invalid argument, but this is not the case. There are valid arguments that have an invalid form. For example, the valid argument If birds fly, then pigs swim; birds fly; therefore, pigs swim has, as one of its forms, p; q; therefore, r, which is invalid. 21 We define the specific form of a given argument as that argument form from which the argument results by substituting a different simple statement for each distinct statement variable (Irving M. Copi, Symbolic Logic, 5 th ed. [New York: Macmillan Publishing Company, 1979], 21 [italics in original]). The specific form of the argument set out in the previous footnote is If p, then q; p; therefore, q. The form p; q; therefore, r is a form of the argument, but not its specific form. 22 This is the basis of what is known as refutation by logical analogy. If one s aim is to refute a particular argument (call it A ), one may do so by thinking up a second argument (call it B ) that (1) has the same specific form as A but (2) has true premises and a false conclusion. The fact that B has true premises and a false conclusion shows that it is invalid, for, by definition, no valid argument has true premises and a false conclusion; the fact that B has the same specific form as A shows that A, like B, is invalid. Do not confuse refutation with rebuttal. To refute is to prove the invalidity of a given argument. Refutation is a success term. One can attempt to refute an argument but fail to do so, just as one can attempt to refute an argument and succeed in doing so. Rebut, by contrast, is not a success term. To rebut is to push back against something with no implication that the pushing succeeds (or fails, for that matter). Refutation may be thought of as successful rebuttal. 23 We might put this as an equation: S = V + T. 24 Suppose I put the following true-false statement on an examination: By definition, all 7

b. Any argument that is invalid is unsound. c. Any argument that has a false premise (even one) is unsound. A given argument may be invalid and have a false premise. Such an argument has two defects: one formal or structural (invalidity) and the other material or substantive (a false premise). Here is an example of a doubly defective argument: Keith s automobile is green. Therefore, Everything is green. As a matter of fact, Keith s automobile is not green; but even if it were, it would not follow that everything is green. 25 (This is known as a non sequitur i.e., a nonfollower.) Another example is provided by the philosopher Judith Jarvis Thomson: Fetuses have a right to life. Abortion kills fetuses. Therefore, Abortion is wrong. Thomson says the first premise is false, but even if it (together with the second premise) were true, the conclusion (she says) would not follow. Here, in the form of a taxonomy (of deductive arguments), is a summary of this section: All Premises True Not All Premises True Valid Sound Unsound Invalid Unsound Unsound See the handouts entitled Argument Analysis and Understanding Validity for details. 14. Validity and soundness are all or nothing, not matters of degree. sound arguments have true conclusions. The statement is false. While it s true that all sound arguments have true conclusions, it s not true by definition. The definition of sound argument makes no reference to the conclusion of the argument, much less to the conclusion being true. The definition of sound argument makes reference to two things: (1) validity; and (2) the truth of the premises. When you put these two components of the definition together, it follows that all sound arguments have true conclusions. 25 If one s aim is to criticize (i.e., find fault with) another person s argument, one should identify all its defects, formal as well as material. Conversely, if one is making an argument, one should ensure not only that one s conclusion follows from one s premises (i.e., that it has a truth-preserving form), but that one s premises are (in fact) true. 8

(Figuratively speaking, they are digital, not analog.) A given deductive argument is either valid or invalid, sound or unsound. It makes no sense to say, of a deductive argument, that it is almost valid or almost sound, or that one deductive argument is more valid or more sound than another. If a given deductive argument has 1,000,000 premises and 999,999 of them are true (the remaining premise being false), then the argument is unsound, just as it would be if all 1,000,000 premises were false. Here, then, is our final taxonomy of arguments: Arguments Deductive Valid Sound Unsound 1 2 Invalid 3 Inductive 4 The taxonomy is jointly exhaustive in that every argument goes in at least one of its four categories. Every argument, in other words, is either (1) sound (i.e., a valid deductive argument with true premises), (2) unsound (i.e., a valid deductive argument with at least one false premise), (3) invalid (i.e., a deductive argument that is not truth-preserving), or (4) inductive (i.e., an argument that is not deductive). The taxonomy is mutually exclusive in that no argument goes in more than one of its four categories (i.e., every argument goes in at most one of its four categories). It follows that every argument goes in exactly one of the taxonomy s four categories. 15. Specialists in logic are known as logicians. 26 Logicians, as such, have no expertise in determining which propositions are true and which false unless the propositions in question are true or false simply by virtue of their form (such as God exists or God does not exist, which is true by virtue of its form, and God exists and God does not exist, which is false by virtue of its form). 27 Logicians are, however, expert in determining which arguments (argument forms) are valid, for logic, as we saw at the outset, is the science of implication (i.e., valid inference). 28 26 Specialists in magic are known as magicians which is not to say that logic has anything to do with magic! 27 Propositions that are true by virtue of their form are called tautologies. Propositions that are false by virtue of their form are called self-contradictions. We will have more to say about tautologies and self-contradictions in due course. 28 People who are not expert in a given field should defer to those who are. If you are not a logician, then you should defer to logicians on matters that are within the scope of their expertise, just as, if you are not a biologist, then you should defer to biologists on matters that are within the scope of their expertise. Expertise does not necessarily transfer from one field to another, so the fact that a particular individual is expert in field X does not mean that he or she is expert in field Y. Many people, sadly, are expert in nothing. (A person of this sort is said to be a jack of all trades, master of none. ) Some people, happily, are expert in more than one field. I have a friend (Robert Bob Schopp, who teaches at the University of Nebraska) who has three advanced degrees: a Ph.D. in psychology, a Ph.D. in philosophy, and a J.D. (law). He works at the intersection of these fields on topics such as 9

APPENDIX: DEFINITIONS OF LOGIC The general science of inference. [T]he branch of philosophy that examines the correctness of rational inference, the ways we think, and the limitations of such inferences. Loosely speaking, logic is the process of correct reasoning, and something is logical when it makes sense. Philosophers often reserve this word for things having to do with various theories of correct reasoning. The scope of the term logic has varied widely from writer to writer through the centuries. But these varying scopes seem all to enclose a common part: the logic which is commonly described, vaguely, as the science of necessary inference. Logic is the study of principles of reasoning. It is concerned not with how people actually reason, but rather with how people ought to reason if they wish to ensure the truth of their results. Logic is the study of the methods and principles used to distinguish good (correct) from bad (incorrect) reasoning. Logic deals with arguments and inferences. One of its main purposes is to Simon Blackburn, The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy, 2d ed. revised, Oxford Paperback Reference (New York: Oxford University Press, 2008), 212. Gregory Pence, A Dictionary of Common Philosophical Terms (New York: McGraw-Hill, 2000), 31. Robert M. Martin, The Philosopher s Dictionary, 3d ed. (Orchard Park, NY: Broadview Press, 2002), 182. Willard Van Orman Quine, Elementary Logic, rev. ed. (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1980), 1. Warren Goldfarb, Deductive Logic (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 2003), xiii. Irving M. Copi, Introduction to Logic, 7 th ed. (New York: Macmillan Publishing Company, 1986), 3. Wesley C. Salmon, Logic, 3d ed. (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, insanity and automatism (both of which are criminal defenses). People who are expert in more than one field especially people, such as Bob, who are expert in multiple fields are known as polymaths. Aristotle (384-322 BCE), Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646-1716), and Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) were polymaths. 10

provide methods for distinguishing those that are logically correct from those that are not. Logical inference leads from premises statements assumed or believed for whatever reason to conclusions which can be shown on purely logical grounds to be true if the premises are true. Techniques to this end are a primary business of logic.... [L]ogic is the autonomous science of the objective though formal conditions of valid inference. Logic is the science of valid inference. Logic is the science of the weight of evidence in all fields. 1984), 1. W. V. Quine, Methods of Logic, 4 th ed. (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1982), 53 (italics in original). Morris R. Cohen and Ernest Nagel, An Introduction to Logic (New York and Burlingame: Harcourt, Brace & World, 1962 [first published in 1934 as Book I of An Introduction to Logic and Scientific Method]), viii, viii, viii, 5, 8, 12, 13, 20, 21, 110, 182, 185-6 (italics in original). Logic may be said to be concerned with the question of the adequacy or probative value of different kinds of evidence. Traditionally, however, it has devoted itself in the main to the study of what constitutes proof, that is, complete or conclusive evidence. Logic as a distinctive science is concerned... with the relation of implication between propositions. Thus the specific task of logic is the study of the conditions under which one proposition necessarily follows and may therefore be deduced from one or more others, regardless of whether the latter are in fact true. It is the object of logical study to consider more detailed rules for distinguishing valid from invalid forms of argument. 11

Logic may... be... defined as the science of implication, or of valid inference (based on such implication). The essential purpose of logic is attained if we can analyze the various forms of inference and arrive at a systematic way of discriminating the valid from the invalid forms. Logic may be conceived as ruling out what is absolutely impossible, and thus determining the field of what in the absence of empirical knowledge is abstractly possible. [T]he fundamental task of logic is the study of those objective relations between propositions which condition the validity of the inference by which we pass from premises to conclusions. [L]ogic studies the relations between sets of propositions in virtue of which some limitation is placed upon the possible truth or falsity of one set by the possible truth or falsity of another set. [L]ogic may be regarded as the study of the most general, the most pervasive characters of both whatever is and whatever may be. Logic may be defined as the organized body of knowledge, or science, that evaluates arguments. [T]he subject matter of symbolic logic is merely logic the principles which govern the validity of inference. It is quite common for people to concentrate on the individual statements Patrick J. Hurley, A Concise Introduction to Logic, 11 th ed. (Boston: Wadsworth, 2012), 1. Clarence Irving Lewis and Cooper Harold Langford, Symbolic Logic, 2d ed. (New York: Dover Publications, 1959), 3 (italics in original). Stan Baronett, Logic, 3d ed. (New York: Oxford University Press, 12

in an argument and investigate whether they are true or false. Since people want to know things, the actual truth or falsity of statements is important; but it is not the only important question. Equally important is the question Assuming the premises are true, do they support the conclusion? This question offers a glimpse of the role of logic, which is the study of reasoning, and the evaluation of arguments. Logic is the study of reasoning. Logic may be broadly defined as the study of methods for determining whether or not a conclusion has been correctly drawn from a set of assumptions. Logic in general is the science and art of right thinking. The study of the validity of different kinds of inference. [T]he science of reasoning, proof, thinking, or inference. Logic is concerned with the principles of valid inference.... Logic is concerned with what makes reasoning good and what makes arguments valid. 2016), 3. Daniel Bonevac, Simple Logic (New York: Oxford University Press, 1999), 2. Joseph Bessie and Stuart Glennan, Elements of Deductive Inference: An Introduction to Symbolic Logic (Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Publishing Company, 2000), 1. Raymond J. McCall, Basic Logic: The Fundamental Principles of Formal Deductive Reasoning, 2d ed., College Outline Series (New York: Barnes & Noble, 1952), xvii. Boruch A. Brody, Logical Terms, Glossary of, in The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Paul Edwards (New York: Macmillan Publishing Company, 1967), 5:57-77, at 67. The Oxford American Dictionary and Language Guide (New York: Oxford University Press, 1999), 583. William Kneale and Martha Kneale, The Development of Logic (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1962; paperback ed., 1984), 1. Tom Tymoczko and Jim Henle, Sweet Reason: A Field Guide to Modern Logic (New York: W. H. Freeman and Company, 1995), 1. 13

The province of logic must be restricted to that portion of our knowledge which consists of inferences from truths previously known; whether those antecedent data be general propositions, or particular observations and perceptions. Logic is not the science of Belief, but the science of Proof, or Evidence. In so far as belief professes to be founded on proof, the office of logic is to supply a test for ascertaining whether or not the belief is well grounded. With the claims which any proposition has to belief on the evidence of consciousness, that is, without evidence in the proper sense of the word, logic has nothing to do. Logical implication is the well-defined core of implication, and the techniques governing it are the central business of logic. John Stuart Mill, A System of Logic Ratiocinative and Inductive: Being a Connected View of the Principles of Evidence and the Methods of Scientific Investigation, Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, vol. VII (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1974 [first published in 1843]), 9. W. V. Quine and J. S. Ullian, The Web of Belief, 2d ed. (New York: Random House, 1978), 40, 41. Implication is what makes our system of beliefs cohere. If we see that a sentence is implied by sentences that we believe true, we are obliged to believe it true as well, or else change our minds about one or another of the sentences that jointly implied it. If we see that the negation of some sentence is implied by sentences that we believe true, we are obliged to disbelieve that sentence or else change our minds about one of the others. Implication is thus the very texture of our web of belief, and logic is the theory that traces it. 14