HOW TO ANALYZE AN ARGUMENT

Similar documents
Philosophy 1100: Ethics

MCQ IN TRADITIONAL LOGIC. 1. Logic is the science of A) Thought. B) Beauty. C) Mind. D) Goodness

Lecture 3 Arguments Jim Pryor What is an Argument? Jim Pryor Vocabulary Describing Arguments

Relevance. Premises are relevant to the conclusion when the truth of the premises provide some evidence that the conclusion is true

Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

Revisiting the Socrates Example

Appendix: The Logic Behind the Inferential Test

Tutorial A03: Patterns of Valid Arguments By: Jonathan Chan

PHIL2642 CRITICAL THINKING USYD NOTES PART 1: LECTURE NOTES

Logic: A Brief Introduction. Ronald L. Hall, Stetson University

Logic for Computer Science - Week 1 Introduction to Informal Logic

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Philosophy 12 Study Guide #4 Ch. 2, Sections IV.iii VI

MPS 17 The Structure of Persuasion Logos: reasoning, reasons, good reasons not necessarily about formal logic

CHAPTER THREE Philosophical Argument

Lecture 2.1 INTRO TO LOGIC/ ARGUMENTS. Recognize an argument when you see one (in media, articles, people s claims).

PHILOSOPHY 102 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC PRACTICE EXAM 1. W# Section (10 or 11) 4. T F The statements that compose a disjunction are called conjuncts.

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

Pastor-teacher Don Hargrove Faith Bible Church September 8, 2011

Argumentation Module: Philosophy Lesson 7 What do we mean by argument? (Two meanings for the word.) A quarrel or a dispute, expressing a difference

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

1.6 Validity and Truth

LOGIC LECTURE #3: DEDUCTION AND INDUCTION. Source: A Concise Introduction to Logic, 11 th Ed. (Patrick Hurley, 2012)

Chapter 1. Introduction. 1.1 Deductive and Plausible Reasoning Strong Syllogism

Introduction to Philosophy

A R G U M E N T S I N A C T I O N

Logical (formal) fallacies

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

Study Guides. Chapter 1 - Basic Training

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

Announcements. CS243: Discrete Structures. First Order Logic, Rules of Inference. Review of Last Lecture. Translating English into First-Order Logic

What is an argument? PHIL 110. Is this an argument? Is this an argument? What about this? And what about this?

1. To arrive at the truth we have to reason correctly. 2. Logic is the study of correct reasoning. B. DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE ARGUMENTS

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 2. Background Material for the Exercise on Inference Indicators

Introducing Our New Faculty

Chapter 1. What is Philosophy? Thinking Philosophically About Life

Philosophical Arguments

A Primer on Logic Part 1: Preliminaries and Vocabulary. Jason Zarri. 1. An Easy $10.00? a 3 c 2. (i) (ii) (iii) (iv)

L4: Reasoning. Dani Navarro

Announcements. CS311H: Discrete Mathematics. First Order Logic, Rules of Inference. Satisfiability, Validity in FOL. Example.

Chapter 8 - Sentential Truth Tables and Argument Forms

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

Module 5. Knowledge Representation and Logic (Propositional Logic) Version 2 CSE IIT, Kharagpur

Deductive Forms: Elementary Logic By R.A. Neidorf READ ONLINE

Unit. Categorical Syllogism. What is a syllogism? Types of Syllogism

Three Kinds of Arguments

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

CRITICAL THINKING (CT) MODEL PART 1 GENERAL CONCEPTS

Session 10 INDUCTIVE REASONONING IN THE SCIENCES & EVERYDAY LIFE( PART 1)

1/19/2011. Concept. Analysis

Persuasive Argument Relies heavily on appeals to emotion, to the subconscious, even to bias and prejudice. Characterized by figurative language,

Argument and Persuasion. Stating Opinions and Proposals

Introduction to Logic

2016 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

Logic Book Part 1! by Skylar Ruloff!

Artificial Intelligence: Valid Arguments and Proof Systems. Prof. Deepak Khemani. Department of Computer Science and Engineering

ELEMENTS OF LOGIC. 1.1 What is Logic? Arguments and Propositions

Logic: inductive. Draft: April 29, Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of premises P1,

Critical Thinking is:

Powerful Arguments: Logical Argument Mapping

Chapter 9- Sentential Proofs

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1

A short introduction to formal logic

Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe.

Introduction to Logic

Thinking and Reasoning

Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of

Academic argument does not mean conflict or competition; an argument is a set of reasons which support, or lead to, a conclusion.

Also, in Argument #1 (Lecture 11, Slide 11), the inference from steps 2 and 3 to 4 is stated as:

Critical Thinking 5.7 Validity in inductive, conductive, and abductive arguments

I. Claim: a concise summary, stated or implied, of an argument s main idea, or point. Many arguments will present multiple claims.

VERITAS EVANGELICAL SEMINARY

Statements, Arguments, Validity. Philosophy and Logic Unit 1, Sections 1.1, 1.2

1 Logical Form and Sentential Logic

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

The antecendent always a expresses a sufficient condition for the consequent

Basic Concepts and Distinctions 1 Logic Keith Burgess-Jackson 14 August 2017

LOGIC ANTHONY KAPOLKA FYF 101-9/3/2010

Learning from Mistakes Karl Popper and Thomas Kuhn

Instructor s Manual 1

Overview of Today s Lecture

Faith indeed tells what the senses do not tell, but not the contrary of what they see. It is above them and not contrary to them.

4.1 A problem with semantic demonstrations of validity

But we may go further: not only Jones, but no actual man, enters into my statement. This becomes obvious when the statement is false, since then

T. Parent. I shall explain these steps in turn. Let s consider the following passage to illustrate the process:

Chapter 2 Analyzing Arguments

HANDBOOK. IV. Argument Construction Determine the Ultimate Conclusion Construct the Chain of Reasoning Communicate the Argument 13

Aristotle ( ) His scientific thinking, his physics.

Scientific Method and Research Ethics Questions, Answers, and Evidence. Dr. C. D. McCoy

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 5

MODUS PONENS AND MODUS TOLLENS: THEIR VALIDITY/INVALIDITY IN NATURAL LANGUAGE ARGUMENTS

Part II: How to Evaluate Deductive Arguments

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

1.5 Deductive and Inductive Arguments

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

Module 9- Inductive and Deductive Reasoning

Inductive Logic. Induction is the process of drawing a general conclusion from incomplete evidence.

Transcription:

What does it mean to provide an argument for a statement? To provide an argument for a statement is an activity we carry out both in our everyday lives and within the sciences. We provide arguments for statements if we want to convince someone of their truth. We provide arguments in order to justify a belief that we take to be true; and we provide arguments in order to get to know the consequences of actions and events, i.e. in order to examine the consequences following from certain basic assumptions. We use arguments in many different contexts we find ourselves in, for instance if we want to show how general laws apply to singular cases, if we want to explain the phenomena of nature, or if we want to give a mathematical proof. 1 Providing arguments for statements is an activity that is undertaken for a rhetorical purpose, namely for the purpose of finding out whether the statement is true or for the purpose of convincing another person of the truth of this statement. We come across arguments both in spoken and written language, in what people say and in what they have written. When we provide arguments for the truth of a statement, we make use of a language (spoken or written). If we want to convince a person of the truth of a statement by argument, then we better use a language that both we and the person we address speak and understand. What is an argument? An argument is a sequence of propositions. However, not every sequence of propositions is an argument. A sequence of propositions is an argument if and only if the last proposition of the sequence, the conclusion of the argument, is related to the preceding propositions, the premises of the argument, in a certain way. Deductive and inductive arguments We distinguish between deductive arguments on the one hand and inductive arguments on the other. The distinction concerns the way in which the premises of an argument are related to its conclusion. 1 Quoted after Axel Bühler, Einführung in die Logik. Argumentation und Folgerung. Freiburg/München 1992, p. 11/2. 1

Deductive arguments An argument is deductive if and only if its conclusion is logically deducible from the conjunction of its premises. The conjunction of the premises is the connection of these premises by and. (There are arguments with only one premise. The logic of such arguments does not differ from the logic of more complex arguments, i.e. those that have more than one premise.) What does it mean to say that a conclusion is logically deducible from a conjunction of premises? A conclusion is logically deducible from a conjunction of premises if and only if the truth of all premises (i.e. the truth of the conjunction of premises) guarantees the truth of the conclusion. A deductive argument consists of a conjunction of premises and a conclusion, such that if the premises are all true, then the conclusion is necessarily true. Here is an example of a deductive argument: All humans are mortal. Socrates is human. Socrates is mortal. (1. premise) (2. premise) (Conclusion) We have to distinguish between the logical correctness or validity of a deductive argument on the one hand and the truth of its premises and its conclusion on the other. Logical correctness or validity is a property of a deductive argument and concerns the inferential relationship between a conjunction of premises and a conclusion: the inference from the premises to the conclusion is valid. Truth on the other hand is a property of a proposition. The example given above is an example of a valid argument of which all premises are true. Examples of logical forms of deductive arguments: (Pn = Premise number, C = Conclusion) Syllogism Barbara P1: All humans are mortal. P2: Socrates is human. p C: Socrates is mortal. Transitivity of Implication P1: All cats are mammals. P2: All mammals are animals. P3: All animals are creatures of God. C: All cats are creatures of God. Modus Ponens P1: If it rains, then the ground is wet. P2: It rains. l C: The ground is wet. Modus Tollens P1: If it rains, then the ground is wet. P2: The ground is not wet. l C: It does not rain. This is just a small selection of examples of logical forms of deductive arguments. As the premises of these arguments are true, these are all valid arguments. 2

Inductive Arguments Inductive arguments, unlike deductive arguments, provide conclusions whose content exceeds that of their premises. To do this, inductive arguments must sacrifice the necessity of deductive arguments. even though we cannot guarantee that the conclusion of an inductive argument is true if the premises are true, still, the premises of a correct inductive argument do support or lend weight to the conclusion. among correct inductive arguments there are degrees of strength or support. The premises of a correct inductive argument may render the conclusion extremely probable, moderately probable, or probable to some extent. Consequently, the premises of a correct inductive argument, if true, constitute reasons, of some degree of strength, for accepting the conclusion. The degree of support of the conclusion by the premises of an inductive argument can be increased or decreased by additional evidence in the form of additional premises. it is a general characteristic of inductive arguments, that additional evidence may be relevant to the degree to which the conclusion is supported. 2 An example of an inductive argument: By far the simplest type of an inductive argument is induction by enumeration. In arguments of this type, a conclusion about all of the members of the class is drawn from premises that refer to observed members of that class. Suppose we have a barrel of coffee beans. After mixing them up, we remove a sample of beans, taking parts of the sample from different parts of the barrel. Upon examination, the beans in the sample are all found to be grade A. We then conclude that all of the beans in the barrel are grade A. 3 P: All beans in the observed sample from the barrel B are grade A. K: All beans in the barrel B are grade A. 2 Quoted from Wesley C. Salmon, Logic. 3 rd ed. Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey 1984 (Prentice-Hall), p. 88. 3 Quoted from Wesley C. Salmon, Logic. 3 rd ed. Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey 1984 (Prentice-Hall), p. 89. 3

Fallacies Deductive Fallacies Some sequences of propositions rhetorically pretend to provide a deductive argument for the truth of a certain proposition (by using conjunctions like therefore, because, as, if... then for example) but fail to do so because the proposition that is supposed to be the conclusion is not logically deducible from the propositions that are supposed to function as premises. Such sequences of propositions are deductive fallacies. Here are a few examples of logical forms of deductive fallacies: Affirming the Consequent P1: If it rains, then the ground is wet. P2: The ground is wet. p K: It rains. Denying the Antecedent P1: If I am in Oslo, then I am in Norway. P2: I am not in Oslo. l K: I am not in Norway. None of these sequences of sentences provides an argument as the conjunction of the so-called premises can be true even though the so-called conclusion is false. Both If it rains, then the ground is wet and The ground is wet can be true even though it does not rain (there can be another reason for the ground being wet). And even if If I am in Oslo, then I am in Norway, and I am not in Oslo are both true, it is fully possible that I am in Norway; I can be in Bergen for example. These sequences of sentences are pseudo-arguments or fallacies; their rhetoric somehow tries to imitate the rhetoric of real arguments. Inductive Fallacies There are certain premises that can render inductive arguments either absolutely or practically worthless. We shall refer to these errors as inductive fallacies. If an inductive argument is fallacious, its premises do not support its conclusion. 4 Here is an example for an inductive fallacy: Insufficient statistics P1: All swans observed in Europe are white. K: All swans are white. What makes the argument fallacious is the fact that there are black swans in Australia. The observational basis for the conclusion is insufficient. The inductive generalization has been made before enough data had been accumulated. 4 Quoted from Wesley C. Salmon, Logic. 3 rd ed. Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey 1984 (Prentice-Hall), p. 88. 4

How to Justify a Proposition by way of Deduction How do we have to proceed in order to justify a proposition p deductively, that is in order to show that p is true? We have to provide a deductive argument for the truth of p. In order to do so we have to proceed in two steps: First, we have to indicate a sequence of propositions from which the proposition p is logically deducible. Second, we have to show that all the propositions of this sequence are true. How to Test Sequences of Propositions that Claim to Provide a Deductive Argument What do we have to do in order to test whether a sequence of propositions actually provides a valid deductive argument for a certain proposition, i.e. in order to find out whether the sequence of propositions convinces us of the truth of a certain proposition? The first step is to test whether the sequence of propositions provides an argument or whether it is no more than a fallacy. If it provides a valid inference from the premises to the conclusion, if it is logically correct, then it does indeed provide an argument, then the proposition which is meant to be the conclusion follows logically from the propositions that are meant to function as premises. In order to go for this first step, we have to analyze the logical form of the sequence of sentences. Often, it is not easy to recognize the logical form of a deductive argument brought forth in a text spoken or written in a natural language. The art of analyzing arguments presented in a natural language is above all the art of recognizing a certain logical form in a sequence of sentences. The second step is to test whether the premises of the deductive argument actually are true. If these premises are true, the conjunction of these premises is true, and then the conclusion is true as well. In most cases we cannot decide whether a proposition that functions as a premise in an argument is true or false by a simple analysis of its logical form; we must instead check whether the proposition corresponds to the facts in the real world or not. First step The first step of an analysis of the logical form of a sequence of sentences claiming to provide a deductive argument leads to one of two possible results: Either the sequence of sentences does indeed provide a deductive argument, the inference from the premises to the conclusion is logically correct or valid; or the sequence of sentences does not provide a deductive argument, it is a pseudoargument. In the first case we can go right from the first to the second step of the analysis of the argument. In the second case there are two possibilities of how to proceed: Either we leave it there and stay with the diagnosis of a fallacy. We simply conclude that the sequence of sentences claiming to provide an argument does not provide any valid 5

inference to the proposition that was meant to be its conclusion. Or we try (bearing in mind the principle of charity) to transform the fallacy into a valid deductive argument, for example by adding further propositions as premises. If we succeed to provide a valid inference from the premises to the conclusion, we must continue with the second step. Second Step The test of the truth value of the premises of an argument again leads to one of two possible results: Either all the premises actually are true and therefore the conjunction of these premises is true as well. Or not all of the premises are true (at least one of these premises is false); in this case the conjunction of the premises is false. In the first case we can infer the truth of the conclusion. In the second case we have to admit that the argument (despite its logical correctness!) is not suited to convince us of the truth of its conclusion. Please note: A logically correct or valid deductive argument of which some premises are false does not allow for any inference concerning the truth value of its conclusion. The following three arguments are examples of logically correct arguments (syllogismes of the form Barbara : All A are B, this C is an A. Thus this C is a B.) (1) All humans are immortal. Socrates is human. Socrates is immortal. (2) All humans are wise. Alle primates are human. Alle primates are wise. (3) All senators are old. All over 80 are senators. Alle over 80 are old. Here the first premise is false, the other true, but the conclusion is false. Here both the premises as well as the conclusion are false. Here both premises are false, while the conclusion is true. Always keep in mind the distinction between the logical correctness or validity of a deductive argument on the one hand and the truth of the propositions which function as its premises on the other. Common language does not always make this distinction. Make the distinction a part of your own use of language! 5 5 Further reading: Wesley C. Salmon, Logic. 3 rd ed. Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey 1984. The logic of induction is a complicated matter. Those interested in the debate may start with Nelson Goodman s Riddle of Induction ; see Nelson Goodman, Fact, Fiction, and Forecast. Cambridge/mass. And London/England, 1 st edition 1979 (Harvard University Press), chapter III. 6