Today s Lecture 1/28/10

Similar documents
What are Truth-Tables and What Are They For?

9.1 Intro to Predicate Logic Practice with symbolizations. Today s Lecture 3/30/10

PART III - Symbolic Logic Chapter 7 - Sentential Propositions

Logic: A Brief Introduction

A. Problem set #3 it has been posted and is due Tuesday, 15 November

Chapter 8 - Sentential Truth Tables and Argument Forms

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC FOR METAPHYSICIANS

INTERMEDIATE LOGIC Glossary of key terms

Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic

LOGIC ANTHONY KAPOLKA FYF 101-9/3/2010

Logicola Truth Evaluation Exercises

Logic & Proofs. Chapter 3 Content. Sentential Logic Semantics. Contents: Studying this chapter will enable you to:

Lecture 3 Arguments Jim Pryor What is an Argument? Jim Pryor Vocabulary Describing Arguments

Workbook Unit 3: Symbolizations

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

Logic for Computer Science - Week 1 Introduction to Informal Logic

Chapter 9- Sentential Proofs

A Romp through the Foothills of Logic: Session 2

Philosophy 220. Truth Functional Properties Expressed in terms of Consistency

PHILOSOPHY 102 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC PRACTICE EXAM 1. W# Section (10 or 11) 4. T F The statements that compose a disjunction are called conjuncts.

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

Study Guides. Chapter 1 - Basic Training

7.1. Unit. Terms and Propositions. Nature of propositions. Types of proposition. Classification of propositions

Symbolic Logic. 8.1 Modern Logic and Its Symbolic Language

Part II: How to Evaluate Deductive Arguments

Chapter 3: More Deductive Reasoning (Symbolic Logic)

An Introduction to. Formal Logic. Second edition. Peter Smith, February 27, 2019

KRISHNA KANTA HANDIQUI STATE OPEN UNIVERSITY Patgaon, Ranigate, Guwahati SEMESTER: 1 PHILOSOPHY PAPER : 1 LOGIC: 1 BLOCK: 2

Situations in Which Disjunctive Syllogism Can Lead from True Premises to a False Conclusion

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 2. Background Material for the Exercise on Inference Indicators

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

A Primer on Logic Part 1: Preliminaries and Vocabulary. Jason Zarri. 1. An Easy $10.00? a 3 c 2. (i) (ii) (iii) (iv)

Rosen, Discrete Mathematics and Its Applications, 6th edition Extra Examples

PHIL 115: Philosophical Anthropology. I. Propositional Forms (in Stoic Logic) Lecture #4: Stoic Logic

Also, in Argument #1 (Lecture 11, Slide 11), the inference from steps 2 and 3 to 4 is stated as:

HANDBOOK. IV. Argument Construction Determine the Ultimate Conclusion Construct the Chain of Reasoning Communicate the Argument 13

9 Methods of Deduction

An alternative understanding of interpretations: Incompatibility Semantics

Transition to Quantified Predicate Logic

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

4.1 A problem with semantic demonstrations of validity

Chapter 3: Basic Propositional Logic. Based on Harry Gensler s book For CS2209A/B By Dr. Charles Ling;

Chapter 6, Tutorial 1 Predicate Logic Introduction

2.1 Review. 2.2 Inference and justifications

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

15. Russell on definite descriptions

In Defense of The Wide-Scope Instrumental Principle. Simon Rippon

In more precise language, we have both conditional statements and bi-conditional statements.

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

3. Negations Not: contradicting content Contradictory propositions Overview Connectives

Artificial Intelligence: Valid Arguments and Proof Systems. Prof. Deepak Khemani. Department of Computer Science and Engineering

3.5_djj_004_Notes.notebook. November 03, 2009

CHAPTER ONE STATEMENTS, CONNECTIVES AND EQUIVALENCES

Logic Book Part 1! by Skylar Ruloff!

Geometry 2.3.notebook October 02, 2015

LGCS 199DR: Independent Study in Pragmatics

What would count as Ibn Sīnā (11th century Persia) having first order logic?

A romp through the foothills of logic Session 3

Lecture 4: Deductive Validity

3.3. Negations as premises Overview

Overview of Today s Lecture

Conditionals II: no truth conditions?

Exposition of Symbolic Logic with Kalish-Montague derivations

Announcements & Such

Is the law of excluded middle a law of logic?

Unit. Categorical Syllogism. What is a syllogism? Types of Syllogism

A Liar Paradox. Richard G. Heck, Jr. Brown University

Natural Deduction for Sentence Logic

b) The meaning of "child" would need to be taken in the sense of age, as most people would find the idea of a young child going to jail as wrong.

2.3. Failed proofs and counterexamples

The antecendent always a expresses a sufficient condition for the consequent

Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body

Day 3. Wednesday May 23, Learn the basic building blocks of proofs (specifically, direct proofs)

BASIC CONCEPTS OF LOGIC

Illustrating Deduction. A Didactic Sequence for Secondary School

Complications for Categorical Syllogisms. PHIL 121: Methods of Reasoning February 27, 2013 Instructor:Karin Howe Binghamton University

To better understand VALIDITY, we now turn to the topic of logical form.

Homework: read in the book pgs and do "You Try It" (to use Submit); Read for lecture. C. Anthony Anderson

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

1.5. Argument Forms: Proving Invalidity

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

Faith indeed tells what the senses do not tell, but not the contrary of what they see. It is above them and not contrary to them.

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

GENERAL NOTES ON THIS CLASS

Philosophical Perspectives, 14, Action and Freedom, 2000 TRANSFER PRINCIPLES AND MORAL RESPONSIBILITY. Eleonore Stump Saint Louis University

Responses to the sorites paradox

Chapter 2. A Little Logic

Identity and Plurals

Deduction. Of all the modes of reasoning, deductive arguments have the strongest relationship between the premises

ELEMENTS OF LOGIC. 1.1 What is Logic? Arguments and Propositions

BASIC CONCEPTS OF LOGIC

Moore on External Relations

Testing semantic sequents with truth tables

Tutorial A02: Validity and Soundness By: Jonathan Chan

1 Clarion Logic Notes Chapter 4

Instructor s Manual 1

Logic: A Brief Introduction. Ronald L. Hall, Stetson University

Basic Concepts and Skills!

What is a logical argument? What is deductive reasoning? Fundamentals of Academic Writing

Philosophy 12 Study Guide #4 Ch. 2, Sections IV.iii VI

Transcription:

Chapter 7.1! Symbolizing English Arguments! 5 Important Logical Operators!The Main Logical Operator Today s Lecture 1/28/10

Quiz State from memory (closed book and notes) the five famous valid forms and their names. --be sure your name is on your paper

Announcements Homework -- Ex 7.1 pgs. 298-299 Part A and B (All) Quiz on Tuesday (Feb 2nd) --state from memory each logical operator, its translation, and its corresponding type of compound statement. See the table on p. 279. (Example: ~ not negation) Book Issues Adding the Course

Validity v. Invalidity Again An argument is valid if and only if it s impossible for all of the premises to be true while the conclusion is false. An argument is invalid if and only if it is possible for all of the premises to be true while the conclusion is false.

Validity v. Invalidity Again --Our task shortly is to study a particular mechanical method for determining whether an argument is either valid or invalid. --It will be the method of Truth Tables.

--But before we can employ this mechanical method, it's essential that we be able to represent English arguments using a symbolic notation. --To do this we need to learn all that is involved with translating English statements into symbols.

Atomic v. Compound Statements An atomic statement is one that does not have any other statement as a component. Examples!Grass is green.!the library is adjacent to Sierra Tower.!Tennis is challenging.

Atomic v. Compound Statements A compound statement is one that has at least one atomic statement as a component. Examples! It is false that grass is red.! The library is adjacent to Sierra Tower and I am hungry.! If tennis is challenging, then tennis players have a reason to practice.

Atomic Statements: Symbolize Atomic Statements with a single upper case letter. B: Brass is a mixed metal. C: Cathy called in sick. N: Nadal wins trophies T: Thought is mysterious.

Compound Statements Symbolize Compound Statements by first symbolizing their Atomic Constituents, and then their logical words. (logical words: it s not the case that, and, or, if, then, if and only if, and their stylistic variants) (We will just symbolize the Atomic Constituents for now) Example: It is false that grass is red. It is false that G.

Compound Statements More examples of partially translated compound Statements: The library is adjacent to Sierra Tower and I am hungry -- L and I If tennis is challenging, then tennis players have a reason to practice -- If T, then P

Symbolizing the Logical Words Operator ~ Name tilde Translates not Compound Type negation dot and conjunction v vee or disjunction " arrow if, then conditional! double-arrow If and only if biconditional

~ NEGATIONS

Symbolizing Negations Grass is not red (R: Grass is red) is symbolized as this is our scheme of ~ R abbreviation It is not the case that grass is red ~ R It is false that grass is red ~ R

Negations of Compound Statements It is false that Dallas wins and Phoenix wins is symbolized as ~ (D P) (D: Dallas wins P: Phoenix wins) It s not true that if Dallas wins, then Phoenix wins ~ (D " P) The following is false: either Dallas wins or Phoenix wins. ~ (D # P)

Parentheses are Important It is false that Dallas wins and Phoenix wins ~ (D P) -- this a negation (this says that it s not the case that both of them win; it leaves us agnostic as to who actually wins; maybe both of them don t win) If we didn t use parentheses we would get ~ D P -- this is a conjunction, not a negation (this says that Dallas does not win and Phoenix wins)

Parentheses are Important It s not the case that if Dallas wins then Phoenix wins. ~(D " P) -- this is a negation (this says that Dallas winning does not entail Phoenix winning) If we didn t use parentheses we would get: ~D " P -- this is a conditional, not a negation (this says if Dallas doesn t win, then Phoenix wins)

Main Logical Operator The most important step in knowing where to place parentheses is finding the main logical operator (i.e. main connective) in the English statement. This lets you know what kind of compound statement it is, be it a negation or conditional, or disjunction, etc.

Main Logical Operator The main logical operator is, roughly, the operator that governs (or connects) the entire statement. Finding the main operator depends upon your ability to see what the statement is saying. This just takes practice. More will be said concerning main operators and parentheses later.

Back to Negations Again, all of these are examples of negations: ~ (D P) ~(D "P) ~(D # P) The ~ is the main logical operator

CONJUNCTIONS

Symbolizing Conjunctions Grass is purple and life is good. (G: grass is purple; L: life is good) G L

Stylistic Variants of and! Grass is purple but life is good.! Grass is purple; however life is good.! Grass is purple yet life is good.! Although grass is purple, life is good.! While grass is purple, life is good.! Grass is purple; nevertheless life is good. Still, G L

Not all uses of 'and' are conjunctions Not all uses of the English term 'and convey a conjunction. If they did, then we would be able to translate the statements in question into conjunctions and capture the essential meaning of the English statement. But we are unable to do this in all cases. For example

Not all uses of 'and' are conjunctions! Sometimes and indicates temporal order! Sometimes and indicates a relationship -Sarah cracked the safe and took the money. -You made a joke and I laughed. -Dave and Val are married. - Dave and Val moved the couch.

These are all Conjunctions P Q P ~(Q # R) (P " Q) (Q " P) The is the main operator ~P [Q # (R " S) ] [Q " (P # R)] S (P # Q) (R " S) The is the main operator

# DISJUNCTIONS

Symbolizing Disjunctions 1. Grass is green or pizza is edible. (G: Grass is green; P: pizza is edible) G # P 2. Alfred will not pass tomorrow or Alfred will study tonight (P: Alfred will pass tomorrow; S: Alfred will study tonight) ~P # S

Stylistic Variants of or Alfred will not pass tomorrow and/or Alfred will study tonight. Alfred will not pass tomorrow or Alfred will study tonight (or both). Alfred will not pass tomorrow unless Alfred will study tonight. Still ~P # S

Inclusive OR either P or Q (or both) Sometimes when people make a disjunctive claim, they intend the or to be read inclusively. e.g. If you want to live under my roof, either you get a job or you go to college. **The parent will not be bothered if you do both. Exclusive OR either P or Q (but not both) Sometimes when people make a disjunctive claim, they intend the or to be read exclusively. e.g. You may have the soup or you may have the salad. **The waitress will be bothered if you say both.

Logicians Treat or as Inclusive We will treat or as inclusive in the absence of a context that suggests an exclusive reading. There is, however, a way of translating an exclusive or which is, again, P or Q (but not both) Consider: You may have the soup or you may have the salad, but not both. Q: How would you translate this?

Exclusive OR You may have soup or you may have salad, but not both. (S: you may have soup; L: you may have salad) (S # L) ~(S L)

'Neither-Nor' is Not a Disjunction! Neither Simon nor Garfunkel is sad. S: Simon is sad. G: Garfunkel is sad. Two Equivalent Readings 1. ~ (S # G) 2. ~S ~G

These are all Disjunctions P # Q P # ~(Q R) (P " Q) # (Q P) The # is the main operator ~P #[Q (R " S) ] [Q " (P # R)] # S (P # Q) #(R " S) The # is the main operator

" CONDITIONALS

Symbolizing Conditionals If Lisa is identical to an immaterial soul, then Lisa is essentially invisible. L: Lisa is identical to an immaterial soul I: Lisa is essentially invisible L " I If Lisa is identical to a material body, then Lisa is not essentially invisible. M: Lisa is identical to a material body I: Lisa is essentially invisible M " ~I

Some Stylistic variants of 'if-then' If Gizmo is a cat, then Gizmo is a mammal! Gizmo is a cat only if Gizmo is a mammal.! Assuming that Gizmo is a cat, Gizmo is a mammal.! Gizmo is a mammal if Gizmo is a cat G: Gizmo is a cat; M: Gizmo is a mammal G " M (Note: there are other stylistic variants. See p. 286)

A note on only if The term Only if (unlike if ) introduces a consequent; the antecedent precedes the only if Remember ANTECEDENT only if CONSEQUENT The term only if intuitively (naturally) introduces a necessary condition (or a requirement). Since the consequent of a conditional is a necessary condition for the antecedent, it s a bit easier to see how only if introduces a consequent.

Sufficient and Necessary Conditions Sufficient Conditions " P " Q is claiming that the occurrence of P is sufficient condition for Q. " A sufficient condition is a condition that guarantees that a statement is true (or that a phenomenon will occur). Necessary Conditions " P " Q is also claiming that the occurrence of Q is a necessary condition for P. " A necessary condition is a condition that, if lacking, guarantees that a statement is false (or that a phenomenon will not occur).

Some Examples --If Alex knows he has hands, then Alex believes he has hands. Knowing something is sufficient for believing it. --Alex knows he has hands only if Alex has good reason to believe he has hands. Having good reason to believe something is a necessary condition on having knowledge of it. --Given that one has a conscious pain, one is aware of the pain. Being conscious of pain is sufficient for being aware of pain. --You can legally drink only if you are at least 21. Being at least 21 is a necessary condition on being able to legally drink.

These are all Conditionals P " Q P " ~(Q # R) (P " Q) " (Q " P) ~P "[Q # (R " S) ] [Q (P # R)] " S (P Q) " (R " S) The " is the main operator The " is the main operator

Unless can be translated by the " as well as the # Depending on the intent of the speaker, 'Alfred will not pass tomorrow unless Alfred will study tonight' could read: If Alfred will study tonight, then it s false that he won t pass tomorrow (i.e. he will pass) S" ~~P (or S " P). This corresponds to the exclusive reading of 'or' in that the intent is not to say that Alfred could very well study and not pass. For if he studies tonight, he will pass tomorrow.

Unless can be translated by the " as well as the # 'Alfred will not pass tomorrow unless Alfred will study tonight' could read: If Alfred will not study tonight, then Alfred will not pass tomorrow ~S " ~P This corresponds to the inclusive reading of 'or' in that it leaves open the possibility that he could study and not pass. The conditional just says that if he doesn't study tonight, he won't pass. It doesn't automatically follow from this that if he does study, he will pass.

Unless can be translated by the " as well as the # Since we are sticking with an inclusive reading of or (and unless), p unless q (where p and q stand for any statement, compound or atomic) should be symbolized as: ~q " p

! Biconditionals

Symbolizing Biconditionals Leslie is in her 30 s if and only if Leslie is between the ages of 30-39. L: Leslie is in her 30 s A: Leslie is between the ages of 30-39 L! A

Symbolizing Biconditionals Jon is a bachelor if and only if Jon is not married and Jon is a male. B: Jon is a bachelor M: Jon is a male R: Jon is married Q: How would you symbolize this?

Symbolizing Biconditionals Jon is a bachelor if and only if Jon is not married and Jon is a male. B: Jon is a bachelor M: Jon is a male R: Jon is married B! (~R M)

Stylistic variant of if and only if Leslie is in her 30 s just in case Leslie is between the ages of 30-39. L: Leslie is in her 30 s A: Leslie is between the ages of 30-39 M! A

These are all Biconditionals P! Q P! ~(Q R) (P " Q)! (Q P) ~P! [Q (R " S) ] [Q " (P # R)]! S (P # Q)! (R " S)