ESSAY REVIEWS CANONIZING CAVENDISH

Similar documents
LOCKE STUDIES Vol ISSN: X

Comments on Leibniz and Pantheism by Robert Adams for The Twelfth Annual NYU Conference on Issues in Modern Philosophy: God

Hume s An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding

The British Empiricism

Reason and Freedom Margaret Cavendish on the Order and Disorder of Nature

Summary of Sensorama: A Phenomenalist Analysis of Spacetime and Its Contents

Primary and Secondary Qualities. John Locke s distinction between primary and secondary qualities of bodies has

Address 307 Valley Street Purdue University, Department of Philosophy

Lecture 25 Hume on Causation

Journal of Philosophy, Inc.

Syllabus. Primary Sources, 2 edition. Hackett, Various supplementary handouts, available in class and on the course website.

Syllabus. Primary Sources, 2 edition. Hackett, Various supplementary handouts, available in class and on the course website.

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 110, No. 3. (Jul., 2001), pp

out in his Three Dialogues and Principles of Human Knowledge, gives an argument specifically

On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title being )

Nagel, T. The View from Nowhere. New York: Oxford University Press, 1986.

Lend me your eyes; I can change what you see! ~~Mumford & Sons

An Article for Encyclopedia of American Philosophy on: Robert Cummings Neville. Wesley J. Wildman Boston University December 1, 2005

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought

Chapter 16 George Berkeley s Immaterialism and Subjective Idealism

Instructor Information Larry M. Jorgensen Office: Ladd Hall, room Office Hours: Mon-Thu, 1-2 p.m.

Properties and Predications

Dualism: What s at stake?

George Berkeley. The Principles of Human Knowledge. Review

Margaret Cavendish on the Relation between God and World

New Chapter: Epistemology: The Theory and Nature of Knowledge

Midwest Studies in Philosophy, XXVI (2002) Presence and Likeness in Arnauld s Critique of Malebranche NANCY KENDRICK

Descartes: A Guide for the Perplexed

A History Of Philosophy, Vol. 5: Modern Philosophy - The British Philosophers From Hobbes To Hume By Frederick Copleston

First Treatise <Chapter 1. On the Eternity of Things>

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

1/10. Primary and Secondary Qualities and the Ideas of Substance

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Naturalism and is Opponents

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

History of Modern Philosophy

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action

Metaphysics. Gary Banham

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Fall 2014 Russell Marcus

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

Leibniz on mind-body causation and Pre-Established Harmony. 1 Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra Oriel College, Oxford

5AANA003 MODERN PHILOSOPHY II: LOCKE AND BERKELEY

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 4b Free Will/Self

Mind s Eye Idea Object

Prepared by: John Culp (626) , ext. 5243, Duke 241 Office Hours: MW 2:00-4:00 PM Other times by appointment

Reading Questions for Phil , Fall 2013 (Daniel)

What does it mean if we assume the world is in principle intelligible?

1/10. Descartes Laws of Nature

CONTENTS. CHAPTER 1. CHAPTER II. THE PROBLEM OF DESCARTES, -

THE CHALLENGES FOR EARLY MODERN PHILOSOPHY: EDITORIAL INTRODUCTION 1. Steffen Ducheyne

PL 406 HISTORY OF MODERN PHILOSOPHY Fall 2009

1/7. Metaphysics. Course Leader: Dr. Gary Banham. Room Tel. Ext.: 3036

WEEK 1: CARTESIAN SCEPTICISM AND THE COGITO

Mind and Body. Is mental really material?"

Was Berkeley a Rational Empiricist? In this short essay I will argue for the conclusion that, although Berkeley ought to be

EMPIRICISM & EMPIRICAL PHILOSOPHY

Qué es la filosofía? What is philosophy? Philosophy

Holtzman Spring Philosophy and the Integration of Knowledge

Marcel Sarot Utrecht University Utrecht, The Netherlands NL-3508 TC. Introduction

HUME S EPISTEMOLOGICAL COMPATIBILISM

3. Knowledge and Justification

Berkeley, Three dialogues between Hylas and Philonous focus on p. 86 (chapter 9) to the end (p. 93).

Excerpt from J. Garvey, The Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books (Continuum, 2007): Immanuel Kant s Critique of Pure Reason

Thomas Reid, An Inquiry into the Human Mind on the Principles of Common Sense (1764)

Humanities 3 V. The Scientific Revolution

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford.

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

A Philosophical Critique of Cognitive Psychology s Definition of the Person

by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB

SYSTEMATIC RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY. Contents

Philosophy Courses-1

Examining the nature of mind. Michael Daniels. A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000).

Phenomenal Knowledge, Dualism, and Dreams Jesse Butler, University of Central Arkansas


Fundamentals of Metaphysics

Chapter I. Introduction

LOCKE STUDIES Vol ISSN: X

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2015


Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Cartesian Dualism. I am not my body

PHILOSOPHY 111: HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY EARLY MODERN

Pihlström, Sami Johannes.

Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On

Every simple idea has a simple impression, which resembles it; and every simple impression a correspondent idea

5 A Modal Version of the

Cartesian Dualism. I am not my body

Philosophy in Review XXXII (2012), no. 5

The Theory of Reality: A Critical & Philosophical Elaboration

Chalmers, "Consciousness and Its Place in Nature"

POLI 342: MODERN WESTERN POLITICAL THOUGHT

Philosophy 428M Topics in the History of Philosophy: Hume MW 2-3:15 Skinner Syllabus

What the Problem of Other Minds Really Tells us about Descartes. Gideon Manning The College of William and Mary

Time 1867 words Principles of Philosophy God cosmological argument

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

Reid Against Skepticism

Transcription:

ESSAY REVIEWS CANONIZING CAVENDISH David Cunning. Cavendish. Abingdon: Routledge, 2016. Pp. 322. $145.00 (cloth); $54.95 (e-book). If you have not heard anything about the philosophy of Margaret Cavendish yet, you will soon, and David Cunning s new book may well have a hand in it. Cavendish (1623 73) is a giddily fascinating philosopher (and poet and novelist and playwright and biographer and dandizette) who is being canonized with lightning speed by scholars of early modern philosophy. Cunning s Cavendish, from Routledge s Arguments of the Philosophers series, is the very welcome culmination of a number of years of work by one of the first philosophers to take Cavendish seriously; it is only the second book focused squarely on her natural-philosophical arguments, after Lisa T. Sarasohn s2010the Natural Philosophy of Margaret Cavendish (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press). Along with Sarasohn and a few other intrepid scholars Eileen O Neill, who produced the excellent first critical edition of a philosophical work of Cavendish s, deserves special mention here Cunning has helped Cavendish to achieve one of her deepest desires: to have her ideas disseminated and engaged with by other philosophers. Shy but eccentric, largely autodidactic and wildly creative, Cavendish developed her own unique philosophical system while engaging with the philosophies of Hobbes, Descartes, J. B. van Helmont, and Bacon, among others. She published a huge amount of written work, under her own name, about chemistry, biology, politics, religion, the habits of insects, and much more. But most of her energy is devoted to natural philosophy, metaphysics, and epistemology, the bulk of which is contained in her Philosophical Letters (1664), Observations on Experimental Philosophy (1666), and the Grounds of Natural Philosophy (1668, taken in part from her 1655/1663 Philosophical and Physical Opinions). Among the most HOPOS: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science, vol. 8 (Spring 2018). 2152-5188/2018/0801-0009$10.00. 2018 by the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science. All rights reserved. Electronically published March 23, 2018. 191

HOPOS The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science interesting doctrines found in those works are that nature is composed entirely of matter that is self-moving, sensitive, and rational; a materialism that is impressively thoroughgoing; a complex and subtle explanatory holism; and an account of perception by patterning, which, since matter is sensitive and rational, also serves as a model for causation between bodies. If what you like from your historical philosophers is a grand system, a dazzling vision, and a surprising way of seeing the world, together with some elegant and some extremely weird arguments, then Cavendish is happy to oblige. But Cavendish s unedited style can be difficult to navigate, and her arguments can be very spread out: for example, an argument that matter is self-moving shows up in a section titled Of the Beard of a Wild Oat. Cunning s book has a useful format, especially for those who are new to Cavendish and who would like to teach her work (great idea!): for a number of central topics, Cunning provides a variety of passages so you can get a quick sense of Cavendish s approachtothem. Cunning also does a lot of thoughtful and creative digesting and reconstructing. He has wagered that it will help make Cavendish accessible to new readers to put her into dialogue with more familiar characters from the history of philosophy. This includes not only people who clearly influenced her, like Descartes, Hobbes, and Henry More, but also philosophers who did not, many of whom lived and wrote after Cavendish did. Beware that Cunning, trusting his readers erudition, does not always flag whether Cavendish could have been influenced by a given figure. While this is all right for Bertrand Russell, it is maybe more dangerous for Hume and Berkeley, and I think it is worth emphasizing, for example, that she developed robust arguments against abstraction before Berkeley made, as Hume wrote, one of the greatest and most valuable discoveries that have been made in late years in the republic of letters (Treatise of Human Nature [Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1738/1896], bk. 1, pt. 1, sec. 7). As many further examples attest, Cunning approaches Cavendish with a stock of questions, concepts, perspectives, and distinctions gathered from his years of deep philosophical engagement with other early modern figures. This is especially useful for those who want to seamlessly integrate Cavendish into their courses without changing their focus. At the same time, it can sometimes have the effect of obscuring what in my opinion are Cavendish s real views. As an example, in chapter 1, Cunning introduces what he describes as Cavendish s theory of ideas, arguing that Cavendish explains all thought in terms of imagistic ideas. As Deborah Boyle pointed out in an Author Meets Critics session on Cunning s book at the 2017 Pacific Division meeting of the American Philosophical Association, Cavendish almost never uses the word idea when she is describing her own views. Instead, she really only uses it when refuting sensible species and Platonism. This gloss on Cavendish leads to what I 192

Essay Reviews SPRING 2018 think is an overassimilation to Hume ( Cavendish subscribes to a version of the doctrine that we find later in Hume that all ideas are copies of impressions [35]; Cavendish does not suppose that we encounter anything like necessities in our experience [27]). In the rest of that chapter, Cunning emphasizes Cavendish s epistemic humility, citing passages like this one: Nature being so subtle and curious, as no particular can trace her ways (31). Cunning beautifully explains this as an expression of her desire to instill in us a respect and admiration for entities that might otherwise come to seem familiar, contemptuous, and mundane (31). But while I agree that Cavendish wants to instill humility and wonder, she is also incurably curious and herself given to quite wild and sometimes breathtakingly confident speculations about the causes and grounds of natural phenomena. And while Cunning is right that Cavendish is a fallibilist about knowledge, that does not mean that our best explanations are not particularly explanatory (21) or that there is much that is brute (15); I am also skeptical that her interest in natural-philosophical speculation is quite as guided by practical concerns as Cunning suggests it is (32). Later in chapter 1, Cunning nicely highlights the ways in which Cavendish trusts the senses (37 41). Those passages, as Cunning notes, support the claim not only that the senses are in general veridical but also that the unaided senses are veridical in contrast to assisted sense perception (38). The rest of the section elaborates how Cavendish might respond to external world skepticism, although Cunning does acknowledge that she nowhere attempts to refute skepticism about waking sensory perceptions (38). Cunning goes on to use Hume, Thomas Reid, Descartes, and Spinoza to develop what he takes to be a Cavendishian response to the question of external world skepticism, in a discussion that is very useful, especially if you are exercised by external world skepticism. In chapter 2, Thinking Matter, Cunning describes the powers that matter has, motivating it as a solution to a familiar problem, that of mind-body interaction. Later on, this chapter contains one of my favorite sections, and one that hews closer to Cavendish s own words and concerns. Drawing on his earlier work ( Cavendish on the Intelligibility of the Prospect of Thinking Matter, History of Philosophy Quarterly 23 [2006]: 117 36), Cunning provides a careful treatment of Cavendish s motivation for believing that matter thinks, accompanied by a helpful comparison of Cavendish with Henry More, with whom Cavendish was in dialogue. Cunning contrasts in detail the approach of each to the inadequacies of inanimate matter and to the relationship between natural order and intelligence. He argues, rightly, I think, that Cavendish does think that intelligence is a precondition for order, but not the intelligence of something that transcends matter, so that bodies bring about their own order (72). There are still more questions to be answered about how they do this, but Cun- 193

HOPOS The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science ning s chapter provides a very insightful and comprehensive launchpad for future scholarship on this issue. On pages 72 73, Cunning has a very nice discussion of Cavendish s claim that, to explain natural phenomena, matter must have sense and reason. He writes there that Cavendish would agree with Leibniz s later mill argument, that there is no way to make sense of how unthinking bodies could combine together and form a composite that thinks and perceives. Her solution, Cunning suggests, is that mentality must be already among the immediate properties of matter. But I think this is a statement of a challenge for Cavendish, not a solution. For Cavendish has an analogous problem: how do sense and reason, understood as properties of matter, generate sense and reason, understood as macroscopic mentalistic phenomena? Cavendish appeals to sensitive and rational motions and says that ideas are so many corporeal figurative motions. So, sometimes she seems to think that mentality can be explained at least in part structurally in precisely the way that Leibniz is resisting. After grappling admirably in chapter 3 with how Cavendish squares the aspects of her theism with her natural philosophy and epistemology, which sometimes seem to leave little room for God, Cunning moves on in chapter 4 The Eternal Plenum to discuss Cavendish s matter theory. As the title suggests, Cunning sees Cavendish s plenism as extremely significant. It is worth flagging for the newcomer that Cavendish herself does not seem to invest it with as much importance and that Cunning uses the claim that nature is a plenum as more or less interchangeable with the claim that nature is deterministic. Now, I think there is a real question as to whether nature is deterministic for Cavendish see, for example, Karen Detlefsen s discussion of this in Reason and Freedom: Margaret Cavendish on the Order and Disorder of Nature, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 89 (2007): 157 91. But even if it is, as Colin Chamberlain made clear in the same Author Meets Critics session mentioned earlier, it is not obvious that plenism, especially given Cavendish s account of motion transfer, entails determinism, and Cavendish herself does not make any attempt to support deterministic claims by appealing to the jostlings of packed bodies. In a related point, made earlier in chapter 2, Cunning takes pains to argue that interaction is always by contact....there is no action at a distance (58), providing a few suggestive passages. But despite these passages, along with others in which Cavendish discusses the necessity of a medium in vision, I think there is very little evidence for Cunning s claim that interaction requires contact, and there is more to suggest that Cavendish thinks it does not as Marcy Lascano and Jon Shaheen have also recently pointed out in conversation. Although I do not think that it is tightly related to the fact that Cavendish thinks that nature is a plenum, Cunning s discussion of the interdependence of 194

Essay Reviews SPRING 2018 the parts of nature is very valuable, as is the next section, on bodily individuation. In those sections, Cunning nicely brings out how central to Cavendish s philosophy is the delicate balance between, on the one hand, respect for the deep dependence that she thinks the parts of nature have on each other and on the whole, and, on the other hand, the intrinsic qualities that individual bodies have that seem to play important causal roles in the fundamental phenomena of nature. Given the importance of this theme to Spinoza s metaphysics of nature, Cunning s comparison of the two is apt, but his claim that Cavendish thinks that individual bodies are those that retain a quantity of motion (157) or fixed proportion of motion (151) is undermotivated. More generally, many of Cunning s claims raise the following question: What is motion, for Cavendish and, for that matter, what is matter? (Not to mention the even more difficult question of what is a corporeal figurative motion, a phrase that Cavendish prefers to matter or motion alone.) Cunning acknowledges that it is very important that we locate her definition of matter (50), which he offers is three-dimensional substance that exhibits qualities like size, shape, motion, resistance, life, animation and intelligence (50). I think this is right as far as it goes, but it raises some further questions. First, more needs to be said about what motion, animation, intelligence, and resistance are. Second, Cavendish s use of the word matter is somewhat equivocal. Sometimes it refers to the totality of matter, in which inanimate and animate matter are completely blended. On this use, it is a name for the whole of nature. Other times, matter refers to the stuff that makes up nature. Used in the first way, it makes sense to say that matter has motion, animation, or whatever. Used in the second way, though, it may not. Third, we know that all matter is extended and that it has life and self-knowledge. And we know that animate matter has self-motion. But we still do not know what matter is, for Cavendish. That is, we do not know what its essential properties are, as opposed to what are, say, its universal accidents. These are just a few questions about matter, and Cunning and I agree that these are fair questions to put to Cavendish. But it turns out we do not agree whether similarly probing questions about motion are fair to put to Cavendish. Given the explanatory role that motion seems to play in her natural philosophy it is the source of all change, variety, and natural effects it seems to me even more important to figure out what motion is, for Cavendish. It is clear from his book that Cunning does not think that this is important, but in later discussions, he argues further that Cavendish does not think that we can give an answer or even that we should try. Drawing on his claims in chapter 1 that Cavendish is clear that we should keep our pretensions to knowledge within certain limits, Cunning, in response to comments at the Author Meets Critics session mentioned earlier, argued that she doesn t in fact define the very basic terms of 195

HOPOS The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science her system because she thinks if we wait until there is a pristine and settled view on the nature of things like matter, motion, properties, etc., we will never be able to make headway on matters of great importance. In amusing support of this, Cunning offered the following quotation from Cavendish s Philosophical and Physical Opinions (London: Wilson [1655], 161): There are none that are more intemperate, than Philosophers; first, in their vain Imaginations of Nature; next, in the difficult and nice Rules of Morality: So that this kind of Study kills all the Industrious Inventions that are beneficial and easie for the Life of Man, and makes one fit only to dye, and not to live. Yet this kind of Study is not wholly to be neglected, but used so much as to ballast a Man, though not to fix him; for, Natural Philosophy is to be used as a Delight and Recreation in Mens Studies, as Poetry is, since they are both but Fictions, and not a fit Labour in Man s Life. Many Men make their Study their Grave, and bury themselves before they are dead. Cavendish s epistemically moderate moments (which usually happen when she is criticizing other philosophers) are about as frequent as ones expressing her faith in her own natural sense and reason (more frequent when she herself is doing the speculating), and so it seems to me that choosing one or another general stance when dealing with a specific question is a matter of interpretive license. But in the case of motion, I think it is clear that Cavendish thinks there are many questions we can ask about its nature, even if it is not analyzable into more basic notions. For one, she provides a careful analysis of the notion of place, denying that motion is a change of place and that it is a mode of body. She comments subtly, critically, and at length on the theories of motion of Descartes, Hobbes, and Henry More. I actually think that motion is analyzable into more basic notions for Cavendish, but even if I am wrong, I think these are fair questions to put to her and ones that she has the resources to address in an interesting way. In chapter 5, Cunning discusses the sense in which nature is one thinking being. This chapter includes a very nice section elucidating an important theme for Cavendish: the (value-laden) distinction between nature and artifice. Cunning dives back into the plenum in chapter 6 to figure out how Cavendish squares what he sees as her plenum-related determinism with claims about free action; he argues that she is a compatibilist about free will. This chapter is noteworthy for the welcome use it makes of Cavendish s plays and poems to speak to her natural philosophy. They assume a central role in chapter 7, too, in which Cunning argues that Cavendish believes that when we find ourselves trapped 196

Essay Reviews SPRING 2018 on all sides by the plenum, we can beat a retreat to our imaginations: A life that includes a rich dose of fantasy has a better chance of yielding pleasure than a life in which we rely for pleasure on the behavior of the bodies that surround us (254). The discussion is filled with interesting material that a casual reader, focused only on Cavendish s speculative philosophy, would miss. Finally, in chapter 8, Cunning provides an introduction to Cavendish s social and political philosophy, also focusing on her poetic and literary works. Cunning s study is impressively broad, addressing Cavendish s views on many philosophical questions and drawing on a wide range of materials. It is clearly structured in a way that makes it easy to read and use. It places Cavendish in dialogue with questions and figures that are familiar from the broader philosophical tradition, so that it is very valuable for integrating Cavendish into, say, the debates over external world skepticism or mind-body interaction. And it starts new discussions by treating Cavendish on some new topics. I think that when it comes to Cavendish s metaphysics and natural philosophy, some of her more original contributions to the theory of matter and motion get lost in Cunning s analysis. That is in part because of the lens of epistemic modesty through which he views her claims, treating them as bedrock for her in a way that I think they are not, and in part because of Cunning s use of other philosophers to clarify Cavendish s positions. But that I or others working on Cavendish disagree with Cunning about the meaning of some of those passages or about general interpretive points is to be expected. To have books advancing provocative theses about figures like Cavendish is what is needed, and Cunning has provided much fodder for future conversations and debates about the meaning of Cavendish s philosophy. Alison Peterman, University of Rochester 197