Subjective Logic: Logic as Rational Belief Dynamics. Richard Johns Department of Philosophy, UBC

Similar documents
6. Truth and Possible Worlds

Theories of propositions

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

Varieties of Apriority

Strawson On Referring. By: Jake McDougall and Siri Cosper

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Coordination Problems

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Analyticity and reference determiners

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

Philosophy 3100: Ethical Theory

Constructing the World, Lecture 4 Revisability and Conceptual Change: Carnap vs. Quine David Chalmers

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Grounding and Analyticity. David Chalmers

Lecture 4. Before beginning the present lecture, I should give the solution to the homework problem

Pragmatic Presupposition

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

Fundamentals of Metaphysics

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

The Inscrutability of Reference and the Scrutability of Truth

A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports. Stephen Schiffer New York University

Frege and Russell on Names and Descriptions Naïve theories

An argument against descriptive Millianism

Quine: Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes

Against Sainsbury and Tye s Originalism

An Introduction to. Formal Logic. Second edition. Peter Smith, February 27, 2019

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

ILLOCUTIONARY ORIGINS OF FAMILIAR LOGICAL OPERATORS

Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

Conceivability and Possibility Studies in Frege and Kripke. M.A. Thesis Proposal. Department of Philosophy, CSULB. 25 May 2006

1.2. What is said: propositions

A Priori Knowledge: Analytic? Synthetic A Priori (again) Is All A Priori Knowledge Analytic?

Class 33 - November 13 Philosophy Friday #6: Quine and Ontological Commitment Fisher 59-69; Quine, On What There Is

Is phenomenal character out there in the world?

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

On Quine, Grice and Strawson, and the Analytic-Synthetic Distinction. by Christian Green

Sense, Communication, and Rational Engagement Imogen Dickie and Gurpreet Rattan, University of Toronto

1. Introduction. Against GMR: The Incredulous Stare (Lewis 1986: 133 5).

Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames Draft March 1, My theory of propositions starts from two premises: (i) agents represent things as

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments

Analyticity, Reductionism, and Semantic Holism. The verification theory is an empirical theory of meaning which asserts that the meaning of a

Conceptual Analysis meets Two Dogmas of Empiricism David Chalmers (RSSS, ANU) Handout for Australasian Association of Philosophy, July 4, 2006

Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames. sentence, or the content of a representational mental state, involves knowing which

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection.

Names Introduced with the Help of Unsatisfied Sortal Predicates: Reply to Aranyosi

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

Puzzles of attitude ascriptions

Is the law of excluded middle a law of logic?

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

Comments on Ontological Anti-Realism

Consciousness might be defined as the perceiver of mental phenomena. We might say that there are no differences between one perceiver and another, as

Kripke s Naming and Necessity. The Causal Picture of Reference

15. Russell on definite descriptions

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

A Posteriori Necessities

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Wolfgang Spohn Fachbereich Philosophie Universität Konstanz D Konstanz

Class #9 - The Attributive/Referential Distinction

A Primer on Logic Part 1: Preliminaries and Vocabulary. Jason Zarri. 1. An Easy $10.00? a 3 c 2. (i) (ii) (iii) (iv)

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

Twentieth-Century Analytic Philosophy by Avrum Stroll

xiv Truth Without Objectivity

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

Philosophy 220A: Symbolic Logic I. Department of Philosophy University of British Columbia. 1. What is logic?

Quantificational logic and empty names

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Phil 435: Philosophy of Language. [Handout 7] W. V. Quine, Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes (1956)

[3.] Bertrand Russell. 1

The Philosophy of Language. Quine versus Meaning

Philosophy 125 Day 4: Overview

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

17. Tying it up: thoughts and intentionality

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE

Millian responses to Frege s puzzle

37. The Analytic/Synthetic Distinction

Todays programme. Background of the TLP. Some problems in TLP. Frege Russell. Saying and showing. Sense and nonsense Logic The limits of language

Dynamics of change in logic

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC 1 Sets, Relations, and Arguments

PLANTINGA ON THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. Hugh LAFoLLETTE East Tennessee State University

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016

Russell: On Denoting

LENT 2018 THEORY OF MEANING DR MAARTEN STEENHAGEN

Moore on External Relations

Constructing the World

KAPLAN RIGIDITY, TIME, A ND MODALITY. Gilbert PLUMER

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Truth and Modality - can they be reconciled?

Transcription:

Subjective Logic: Logic as Rational Belief Dynamics Richard Johns Department of Philosophy, UBC johns@interchange.ubc.ca May 8, 2004 What I m calling Subjective Logic is a new approach to logic. Fundamentally it is a theory about what sentences mean, i.e. a theory of the proposition, but it includes an account of logical consequence, the propositional connectives, probability, and the nature of truth. This theory, I believe, helps to clarify of a number of important philosophical issues. 1. Subjective and Objective Propositions So what do sentences mean, according to subjective logic? They actually have two different kinds of meaning one at the level of truth, or the real world, and another at the level of belief, or the epistemic state. I call these the objective meaning, and the subjective meaning, respectively. Philosophers in the analytic tradition have focused almost exclusively on the objective meaning of a sentence, so I am using the term subjective logic (perhaps unwisely) for the position that recognises both kinds of meaning. In this talk I will be dealing just with subjective meaning. Why do we need two kinds of proposition? We are forced to this position, I believe, by virtually the same reasoning that led Frege to distinguish between Sinn and Bedeutung (sense and meaning). Indeed, I see my distinction between objective and subjective propositions as a modification of Frege s Sinn/Bedeutung distinction. We all know the story about Hesperus, the evening star, and Phosphorus, the morning star. At one time they were believed to be two different objects, but it was later discovered that they are in fact the same planet (which we now call Venus). Now consider an ancient astronomer, Ralph, who is living prior to the discovery of the identity of Hesperus and Phosphorus. He writes down the following pair of sentences. Hesperus has a moon Phosphorus has a moon 1

Do they have the same meaning, or two different meanings? Do they express the same proposition, or two different propositions? We now know that Hesperus and Phosphorus are the same planet (Venus), so the sentences have the same truth conditions. They represent the same possible state of affairs. But for Ralph, our ancient astronomer who (in the absence of evidence) does not believe that Hesperus is Phosphorus, they express different beliefs. He might say, for example, that he thinks it unlikely there s any moon orbiting Hesperus (having failed to see one). Yet he wouldn t know about Phosphorus, as he never gets up early enough to see it. Most discussions of this problem attempt to make sense of it without introducing subjective propositions. Russell s theory that names abbreviate definite descriptions is the most obvious example. None is as compelling as the observation that: For the ancient astronomer (in his epistemic state) Hesperus and Phosphorus are two different planets. Taking this idea seriously requires that we admit two kinds of sentence meaning: the subjective meaning (in the epistemic state) and the objective meaning (in the real world). Since Hesperus and Phosphorus are distinct planets, in Ralph s epistemic state, the two sentences have different subjective meanings. Since Hesperus and Phosphorus are the same real planet, the two sentences have the same objective meaning. Another way to think about this problem is in terms of what it is for two sentences to be synonymous, or express the same proposition. Two different criteria have been proposed, as shown in the table below. Objective Criterion Truth conditions Two sentences express the same proposition iff it is not possible for one to be true and the other false. Subjective Criterion Belief conditions Two sentences express the same proposition iff it is not possible for one to be believed more strongly than the other. For the two sentences above, we see that they have the same truth conditions, but different belief conditions (for Ralph), so that these two criteria appear to be inconsistent. Rather than reject one of them, however, we should regard them as talking about two different kinds of proposition. 2. Other Logical Notions The distinction in logic between the objective and the subjective applies not just to propositions, but to all logical concepts. For example, the relation of logical consequence or entailment between propositions also has objective and subjective flavours. What is logical consequence? 2

It is generally held to be a matter of necessary truth preservation. This objective concept is actually of limited application, however. In most contexts, we really should be talking about rational belief preservation. The idea of an object as the meaning of a singular term has objective and subjective flavours. So does the concept of probability. There isn t time today to discuss each of these, but this table provides a summary. Objective Flavour Real world Truth Possible state of affairs Metaphysically-necessary implication Real object Physical chance Subjective Flavour Epistemic state Belief Subjective proposition (thought) Logical entailment Epistemic object Epistemic probability 3. Subjective Propositions as Epistemic Expansions What exactly are subjective propositions? Let us be guided by H. P. Grice here. Grice held that, in uttering a sentence S, the speaker intends that the audience come to believe some proposition. This proposition is said to be the meaning of S. We can use this idea, although it will be convenient to change the terminology a little, borrowing a term from belief dynamics. An expansion is a change of epistemic state that occurs when one learns something new, or acquires a new belief. Beliefs that are certain, having subjective probability one, are preserved under expansion. Expansion is the one kind of belief change that is possible for perfectly rational thinkers the ideal of cumulative knowledge gain. Other kinds of belief change involve loss of information, mistakes, or correction of earlier mistakes. A sentence such as the cat is on the mat is usually uttered with the intention to cause the audience s epistemic state to undergo an expansion. We may (rather crudely) picture this expansion as below. 3

In the initial epistemic state the position of the cat is indeterminate. It could be on the mat, or on the chair, or hiding under the table. (These degrees of belief are shown in the picture by the degrees of opacity in the cat.) In the expanded epistemic state, by contrast, the cat is definitely on the mat and nowhere else. An epistemic state is sometimes viewed as a set of propositions, so that an expansion is simply the addition of an extra proposition to the set. This view has difficulty with sentences like Vulcan does not exist. (Vulcan was a planet once postulated to account for the perihelion shift in Mercury s orbit. It proved hard to observe, and the perihelion shift was later explained by General Relativity.) The intended expansion for Vulcan does not exist presumably is something like this: 4

The speaker intends the listener to expunge the notional object Vulcan from his epistemic state. It makes little sense to see the expanded epistemic state as a set that includes Vulcan does not exist among its members, since the name Vulcan in this state is meaningless. (The sentence becomes meaningless during its acceptance.) Rather, the meaning of the sentence seems to be the expansion itself. Propositions, on this alternative view, are information vectors from one epistemic state to another. (I realise that my treatment of this Vulcan example departs significantly from that proposed by Russell and Quine, but I think this one is better as it allows natural languages to contain singular terms. It s a virtue of subjective logic that this treatment becomes possible.) It is a mistake, in my view, to regard an epistemic state as a set of propositions, or as a probability function over a set of propositions, or indeed as any kind of construction using propositions as raw material. An epistemic state is not like that. It is more like an internal, cognitive map of the world. It is the world according to some person, at some time. Let us pursue this map analogy, and suppose someone is trying to draw a map based on your verbal description of the territory. It will be very hard to do this if they start with a blank sheet of paper, so let s suppose that a few basic landmarks (such as the coastline) are already in place. One s descriptions will then be sentences like: Hope is 150 km east of Vancouver along the 5

Highway 1. Each description will enable more features to be drawn, based on what s already there. After the map is complete, it is impossible to derive from it the set of descriptions used to draw it. The map shows Kamloops as being 355km east of Vancouver, for example, but this might not have been among the descriptions. Instead, Hope s position might have been given as 150 km east of Vancouver, and Kamloops s as 205 km east of Hope. In a similar way, while epistemic states contain propositions in some sense, it is not in the crude sense of set membership. It is worth mentioning that this account of subjective propositions, as epistemic expansions, allows sentences of fiction to have subjective meaning. (Such sentences clearly have no truth conditions, and do not describe possible states of affairs.) We humans have the capacity of imagination, that allows us to build quite complex epistemic states that we do not actually inhabit. When reading a novel, for example, the author guides us in a series of expansions that gradually construct such a fictional epistemic state. The later sentences of the novel have meaning in that epistemic state. Fictional and serious epistemic states are often mixed together. Sherlock Holmes, for example, is a fictional character who lives in a real city. 3. Presuppositions The view that (subjective) propositions are epistemic expansions helps us to see that most sentences presuppose a certain amount of knowledge. The Loch Ness Monster weighs over 40 tons, for example, presupposes that there is some sort of pre-historic creature living in Loch Ness. An epistemic expansion, of course, is an expansion from some state of knowledge to another, and generally the initial state is not empty. A proposition, in general, merely tops up the knowledge we already have. I sometimes call these relative propositions. The view that a proposition is picked out by the class of possible worlds where it is true only applies to propositions with no presuppositions. The initial epistemic state, in this case, is completely empty of knowledge. [Like a position vector.] 4. Logical consequence Logical consequence is usually defined in terms of preserving truth from premiss to conclusion. This account does not work well outside of mathematics, however, as the following example shows. Hesperus has a moon Phosphorus has a moon 6

The argument is invalid, as conclusion is not a logical consequence of the premiss, yet the argument is necessarily truth preserving. (I assume, following Kripke, that true identities are metaphysically necessary.) Also, in some valid arguments the premisses and conclusion do not all have truth values, as they concern fictional characters. Consider, for example, the following argument involving Tolkien s fictional character Aragorn. This argument is valid, even though the second premiss and the conclusion lack truth values. All humans are mortal Aragorn is human Aragorn is mortal The following definition deals with such examples. Definition The expansion of K by A is written K + A. Definition Definition A entails B relative to K iff K+A is an expansion of K+B. A entails B simpliciter if and only if, for all K such that K+A and K+B exist, K+A is an expansion of K+B. The rough idea here is that a valid inference is one that is made by a rational thinker. It can be show that entailment in this sense is always truth preserving, but the converse does not hold. (A truth-preserving argument may be invalid, as shown by the example above.) Consistency is also easy to define in terms of expansion. A is consistent with B if and only if there is some proposition that entails them both. 5. The Connectives The truth-functional connectives are usually defined using truth tables, but these are theoretically burdened (requiring possible worlds) and of limited scope (applying only to propositions without presuppositions). Better definitions are possible within subjective logic, namely: Conjunction of A, B: the weakest proposition that entails A and entails B (total information). Disjunction of A, B: the strongest proposition that is entailed by A and entailed by B (information overlap). Negation of A: the weakest proposition that is inconsistent with A. (minimum denial) 7

These can be applied to propositions with presuppositions as well as those without. Note that the negation of A, for example, shares all the presuppositions of A. The negation of: is The Loch Ness Monster weighs over 40 tons The Loch Ness Monster weighs no more than 40 tons. Thus the law of excluded middle holds only for propositions that make no assumptions. If A then B: This sentence does not express a proposition. It is believed, in an epistemic state K, to the extent that B is believed in K+A. (This is Frank Ramsey s theory of the conditional.) One consequence of this reading is Ernest Adams claim that P K (If A then B) = P K (B A), where P K gives the degrees of belief for propositions in the epistemic state K. 6. Philosophical Uses of Subjective Logic I have barely begun to work out the uses of epistemic logic in philosophy, but here are a few things. 1. We can understand truth as correspondence between the epistemic state and the real world. We can define a true proposition as one that is entailed by (or consistent with) the actual world, and prove that logical entailment is truth preserving. 2. The debate about whether meanings are in the head reveals itself as being rather silly. Subjective meanings are in the head, but objective meanings are not. 3. Epistemic probability theory becomes part of logic. 4. We can understand the analytic/synthetic distinction. A proposition is analytic just in case it is believed with certainty in every (rational) epistemic state, and synthetic otherwise. 5. We can understand what it means to deny the existence of a thing, using a proper name for it, e.g. The planet Vulcan does not exist. The sentence is uttered with the intention that the listener expunge the notional object Vulcan from his epistemic state. 8