Vagueness and supervaluations

Similar documents
Supervaluationism and Fara s argument concerning higher-order vagueness

Williams on Supervaluationism and Logical Revisionism

VAGUENESS. For: Routledge companion to Philosophy of Language, ed. D. Fara and G. Russell.

VAGUENESS. Francis Jeffry Pelletier and István Berkeley Department of Philosophy University of Alberta Edmonton, Alberta, Canada

Supervaluationism and Its Logics

Responses to the sorites paradox

Vague objects with sharp boundaries

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014

THE PROBLEM OF HIGHER-ORDER VAGUENESS

(Some More) Vagueness

TEMPORAL EXTERNALISM, CONSTITUTIVE NORMS, AND THEORIES OF VAGUENESS HENRY JACKMAN. Introduction

Response to Eklund 1 Elizabeth Barnes and JRG Williams

WRIGHT ON BORDERLINE CASES AND BIVALENCE 1

An Introduction to. Formal Logic. Second edition. Peter Smith, February 27, 2019

A Liar Paradox. Richard G. Heck, Jr. Brown University

Supervaluationism and the timeless solution to the foreknowledge problem

The paradox we re discussing today is not a single argument, but a family of arguments. Here are some examples of this sort of argument:

What is Logical Validity?

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016

Horwich and the Liar

Vague Intensions: A Modest Marriage Proposal

Degrees of belief, expected and actual

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

The paradox we re discussing today is not a single argument, but a family of arguments. Here s an example of this sort of argument:!

Journal of Philosophy 114 (2017): Moreover, David Lewis asserts: The only intelligible account of vagueness locates it in

Vagueness and Uncertainty. Andrew Bacon

Journal of Philosophy (forthcoming) Moreover, David Lewis asserts: The only intelligible account of vagueness locates it in

Is the law of excluded middle a law of logic?

Making sense of (in)determinate truth: the semantics of free variables

VAGUENESS, TRUTH, AND NOTHING ELSE. David Luke John Elson. Chapel Hill 2009

Vague, So Untrue. David Braun and Theodore Sider. February 11, 2006

Believing Epistemic Contradictions

THE QUIETIST S GAMBIT

Varieties of Vagueness *

Scott Soames: Understanding Truth

Cut-offs and their Neighbors

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Loading Intelex { Poiesis : Philosophical Topics }

Varieties of Vagueness*

This Magic Moment: Horwich on the Boundaries of Vague Terms

Vagueness, Partial Belief, and Logic. Hartry Field. 1. Vagueness (and indeterminacy more generally) is a psychological phenomenon;

God of the gaps: a neglected reply to God s stone problem

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

Arguments Against Metaphysical Indeterminacy and Vagueness 1 Elizabeth Barnes. Draft, June 2010

Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 1)

Fuzzy Logic and Higher-Order Vagueness

Quandary and Intuitionism: Crispin Wright on Vagueness

The Truth about Vagueness PREPRINT. Forthcoming in On the Sorites Paradox, eds. Ali Abasenezhad and Otavio Beuno, Springer, 2017

Vagueness in a Precise World: Essays on Metaphysical Vagueness

Vagueness as Indeterminacy Brian Weatherson, Cornell University * October 19, 2006

4. The Epistemic Theory of Vagueness

Truthier Than Thou: Truth, Supertruth and Probability of Truth

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Maudlin s Truth and Paradox Hartry Field

Fuzzy Logic and Higher-Order Vagueness

Handling vagueness in logic, via algebras and games. Lecture 1.

Epistemicism, Parasites and Vague Names * vagueness is based on an untenable metaphysics of content are unsuccessful. Burgess s arguments are

(4) It is not the case that Louis is bald and that he is not bald.

Situations in Which Disjunctive Syllogism Can Lead from True Premises to a False Conclusion

Indeterminacy in Causation. Eric Swanson. This isn t the final version of this paper;

Millian responses to Frege s puzzle

Facts and Free Logic. R. M. Sainsbury

Facts and Free Logic R. M. Sainsbury

The Nature and Logic of Vagueness

Vagueness, conditionals and probability

Vagueness and Thought. Andrew Bacon

Vagueness: why do we believe in tolerance?

Conditionals IV: Is Modus Ponens Valid?

The Paradox of Knowability and Semantic Anti-Realism

Quantificational logic and empty names

Conditionals II: no truth conditions?

ILLOCUTIONARY ORIGINS OF FAMILIAR LOGICAL OPERATORS

A Puzzle about Knowing Conditionals i. (final draft) Daniel Rothschild University College London. and. Levi Spectre The Open University of Israel

NB: Presentations will be assigned on the second week. Suggested essay topics will be distributed in May.

Cohen 2004: Existential Generics Shay Hucklebridge LING 720

Against Vague and Unnatural Existence: Reply to Liebesman

FACING UP TO THE SORITES PARADOX. Terry Horgan. University of Memphis

Lecturer: Xavier Parent. Imperative logic and its problems. by Joerg Hansen. Imperative logic and its problems 1 / 16

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Some proposals for understanding narrow content

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

Appeared in: Al-Mukhatabat. A Trilingual Journal For Logic, Epistemology and Analytical Philosophy, Issue 6: April 2013.

LOGICAL PLURALISM IS COMPATIBLE WITH MONISM ABOUT METAPHYSICAL MODALITY

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1

Potentialism about set theory

Imprecise Probability and Higher Order Vagueness

Truth and the Unprovability of Consistency. Hartry Field

Vagueness and Borderline Cases

Modalism and Logical Pluralism

Vagueness and Conversation

A Solution to the Gettier Problem Keota Fields. the three traditional conditions for knowledge, have been discussed extensively in the

Vagueness, Logic, and Ontology

Validity for Strong Pluralists Aaron J. Cotnoir Northern Institute of Philosophy University of Aberdeen

Informational Models in Deontic Logic: A Comment on Ifs and Oughts by Kolodny and MacFarlane

Paradox of Deniability

Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities

Published in Mind, 2000, 109 (434), pp

A theory of metaphysical indeterminacy

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio

Transcription:

Vagueness and supervaluations UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016 John MacFarlane 1 Supervaluations We saw two problems with the three-valued approach: 1. sharp boundaries 2. counterintuitive consequences of truth functionality (or degree functionality) The degree approach fixes (1) but still has (2). Supervaluationism is a way to fix (2), though perhaps it still has (1). The basic idea: A valuation is an assignment of classical extensions to each nonlogical term in the language. An interpretation of the language is a set of valuations. (Not, as in classical semantics, a single valuation.) An interpretation embodies a set of constraints on valuations: some assignments of classical extensions are ruled out as inadmissible. A valuation v is admissible (under an interpretation) if it satisfies the following constraints: the extension of a expression on v includes all the things that definitely fall into the extension of that expression (on the interpretation). the extensions of expressions on v respect penumbral connections. Penumbral connections are, essentially, relations between the meanings of different vague terms. So, for example, it might be required that nothing be in the extension of both orange and red. And t might be required that certain connections hold betw the extensions of tall, short, and taller than. We can represent these constraints using meaning postulates: valuation interpretation admissible penumbral connections meaning postulates x (Red(x) Orange(x)) x, y(tall(y) TallerThan(x, y) Tall(x)) Supervaluation is often motivated by the idea that vagueness arises from semantic indecision: The reason it s vague where the outback begins is not that there s this thing, the outback, with imprecise borders; rather there are many things, with different borders, and nobody has been fool enough to try to enforce a choice of one of them as the official referent of the word outback. Vagueness is semantic indecision. [5, p. 213] April 26, 2016 1

2. Application to sorites The admissible valuations represent the different candidate extensions we re undecided about. A sentence is true on a valuation v iff it is true on v s assignment of classical extensions to its terms. A sentence is true on an interpretation I iff it is supertrue true on every valuation in I. A sentence is false on an interpretation I iff it is superfalse false on every valuation in I. (Equivalently, a sentence is false on an interpretation I if its negation is true in I.) Some sentences will be neither supertrue nor superfalse on an interpretation. Since we identify truth and falsity with supertruth and superfalsity, this means that we give up bivalence, the assumption that every sentence is either true or false (on a given interpretation). Example: true on a valuation v true on an interpretation I supertrue false on an interpretation I superfalse bivalence (1) Joe is bald. when the admissible interpretations contain some valuations that put Joe in the extension of bald and some that do not. But consider (2) Either Joe is bald or he isn t. This comes out true on the interpretation described, despite that fact that neither disjunct is true! So despite giving up bivalence, we keep the law of excluded middle. This is a distinctive feature of supervaluationism. (Contrast intuitionism, which gives up both bivalence and the law of excluded middle.) Indeed, (2) is true on every interpretation: it is logically true. Generalizing: every sentence that is a logically true in classical logic will be logically true (true in all interpretations) in supervaluational semantics as well. To see why, note that every sentence that is logically true in classical logic must be true on every admissible valuation, since admissible valuations are classical interpretations. It follows immediately that every such sentence will be supertrue on all supervaluational interpretations. We have a combination of classical logic and nonclassical semantics. Is that bad? You might wonder whether a sign can mean disjunction if A B is allowed to be true when neither A nor B is true. On the other hand, it seems an attractive feature of supervaluationism that it lets us continue to use classical logic without a commitment to bivalence, which might seem implausible for vague language. law of excluded middle 2 Application to sorites What does supervaluationism say about the sorites paradox? April 26, 2016 2

3. Higher-order vagueness Remember, the fundamental problem was that if we reject the universal premise of the sorites, (3) For any n, if someone with n pennies is rich, then someone with n 1 pennies is rich, which it seems we have to to block the paradox, we seem forced to accept its negation, which is a sharp-boundaries claim: (4) For some n, someone with n pennies is rich and someone with n 1 pennies is not rich. Multivalued approaches solve the puzzle by saying: you can reject (6) (or the conditionals that are its instances) as less than fully true, without accepting its negation (4). What does supervaluationism say about the universal premise (6)? Like multivalued approaches, it says you should reject it! (It s superfalse.) But, unlike multivalued approaches, it says you should accept its negation (4). But isn t this what we found problematic with classical semantics? That rejecting (6) would require accepting (4), a sharp-boundaries claim? So how does supervaluationism improve over classical semantics? The key difference is that, for the supervaluationist, accepting (4) does not commit one to accepting that there is a true witness to the existentially quantified claim: that is, a true instance. In classical semantics, if (4) is true, then for some (perhaps unknown) n, the following instance must be true: witness (5) Someone with n pennies is rich and someone with n 1 pennies is not rich. But the supervaluationist can deny that any sentence of the form (5) is true, while still accepting (4). This is just the extension to quantification of the point we already saw: that there can be a true disjunction with neither disjunct true. So the idea is that we take the sting out of accepting (4) by making it possible to accept (4) while rejecting all of its instances. We can accept that there is a number of pennies such that a person with that many pennies is rich and a person with one fewer penny is not rich, while rejecting, for every particular number n, the claim that a person with n pennies is rich and a person with n 1 pennies is not rich. 3 Higher-order vagueness We started with a notion of admissible valuations. An admissible valuation, we said, must include all the definite F s in the extension of F. So this account presupposes a sharp boundary between the people who are definitely rich and those who are not. And this, you might think, is just as objectionable as having a sharp boundary between the people who are rich and those who aren t. If the worry was about having sharp, unknowable boundaries, we still have them. April 26, 2016 3

3. Higher-order vagueness Suppose we add a definitely operator D that works as follows: Dφ is true on a valuation just in case φ is true on all admissible valuations. (Note: this is a bit like our standard modal.) Then supervaluationism begins to look bad...or so Williamson [9] argues. First, there is the problem of higher-order vagueness. We can just run the sorites with definitely rich instead of bald. The sorites premise seems almost as compelling: D (6) For any n, if someone with n pennies is definitely rich, then someone with n 1 pennies is definitely rich, The usual supervaluationist response (e.g., in [4]) is to say that the notion of admissibility is vague. If that is right, then we are doing our semantics for vague terms in a vague metalanguage. But if we re going to do this, why not just do it at the beginning, and say (7) The extension of bald is the set of bald things. Williamson also points to some logical problems with the introduction of the D operator. Note first that there are two ways of defining validity in a supervaluational semantics. An inference is locally valid if any valuation that makes the premises true makes the conclusion true. An inference is globally valid if any interpretation that makse the premises supertrue makes the conclusion supertrue. locally valid globally valid Williamson argues that local validity can t be the important notion of validity for supervaluationists. Since they identify truth with supertruth, the proper extension of the normal classical notion of validity to supervaluationism is preservation of supertruth. But on global notion of validity, (8) φ, therefore Dφ is valid! (Confirm this for yourself.) But (9) φ Dφ isn t a logical truth. When φ is borderline, (9) is false on some valuations, so it is not supertrue. So, Williamson argues, once we introduce D into our language, we re going to lose some properties of classical validity; If ψ is a logical consequence of φ, then φ ψ is a logical truth. If ψ is a logical consequence of φ, φ is a logical consequence of ψ. April 26, 2016 4

REFERENCES REFERENCES (According to supervaluationism, an argument can be truth-preserving without being non-falsity preserving.) How bad are these results? Williamson says that supervaluations invalidate our natural mode of deductive thinking, such as Conditional Proof (conditional introduction), Dilemma (disjunction elimination), and Reductio (negation introduction). But this isn t clear. We have already seen examples of restricting what can be done inside a subproof for conditional proof ( -introduction), in relevance logics and modal logics. Could we not impose a similar restriction here? Instead of allowing all valid forms of argument inside a subproof for conditional proof, we could allow just locally valid forms of argument. (See [8, pp. 224 5], [7], [6, 4].) Further reading The locus classicus for supervaluationist approaches to vagueness is [2]. A recent defense against some of the objections in Williamson can be found in [4, ch. 7]. For some criticism of Keefe, see [1]. For an entirely different line of criticism, see [3]. References [1] Delia Graff Fara. Scope Confusions and Unsatisfiable Disjuncts: Two Problems for Supervaluationism. In: ed. by Richard Dietz and Sebastiano Moruzzi. Oxford University Press: Oxford, 2010. [2] Kit Fine. Vagueness, Truth and Logic. In: Vagueness: A Reader. Ed. by Rosanna Keefe and Peter Smith. Cambridge, MA: MIT, 1997, pp. 119 150. [3] Jerry A Fodor and Ernest Lepore. What Cannot Be Evaluated Cannot Be Evaluated and It Cannot Be Supervalued Either. In: The Journal of philosophy (1996), pp. 516 535. [4] Rosanna Keefe. Theories of Vagueness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000. [5] David Lewis. On the Plurality of Worlds. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986. [6] John MacFarlane. Truth in the Garden of Forking Paths. In: Relative Truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008, pp. 81 102. [7] Vann McGee and Brian McLaughlin. Logical Commitment and Semantic Indeterminacy: A Reply to Williamson. In: Linguistics and Philosophy 27 (), pp. 221 235. [8] Vann McGee and Brian McLaughlin. Review of Timothy Williamson, Vagueness. In: Linguistics and Philosophy 21 (1998), pp. 221 235. [9] Timothy Williamson. Vagueness. London: Routledge, 1994. April 26, 2016 5