FREEDO M IN THE CITY OF GOD

Similar documents
QUESTION 116. Fate. Article 1. Is there such a thing as fate?

Universal Features: Doubts, Questions, Residual Problems DM VI 7

QUESTION 55. The Essence of a Virtue

QUESTION 36. The Causes of Sadness or Pain. Article 1. Is it a lost good that is a cause of pain rather than a conjoined evil?

QUESTION 26. Love. Article 1. Does love exist in the concupiscible power?

QUESTION 22. God s Providence

Moreshortcomingsofsyllogistics.

QUESTION 87. How Our Intellect Has Cognition of Itself and of What Exists Within It

QUESTION 28. The Divine Relations

The question is concerning truth and it is inquired first what truth is. Now

Rachel SAMPLE. Requiem for the Innocents Ï Ï J Ï. ú ú ú ú ú ú SAMPLE. 12 Ï Ï Ï ú ú SAMPLE

QUESTION 20. The Goodness and Badness of the Exterior Act

QUESTION 90. The Initial Production of Man with respect to His Soul

A Note on Two Modal Propositions of Burleigh

OR

QUESTION 83. The Subject of Original Sin

IDOLATRY AND RELIGIOUS LANGUAGE

Summer Preparation Work

QUESTION 34. The Goodness and Badness of Pleasures

270 Now that we have settled these issues, we should answer the first question [n.

QUESTION 59. An Angel s Will

79 THE ROLE OF HABITUS IN ST. THOMAS'S MORAL THOUGHT John B. Kilioran King's College

IMMEDIATE KNOWLEDGE AND HAPPINESS

1 Ted Kirnbauer Romans 10:16-11:10 5/13/18

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Thomas Aquinas on the World s Duration. Summa Theologiae Ia Q46: The Beginning of the Duration of Created Things

QUESTION 30. Mercy. Article 1. Is something bad properly speaking the motive for mercy?

Third Sunday of Easter. April 19, :00 am

Glossed books and commentary literature

Parables of the Kingdom Fr. John Bayer Christ the King Parish, Cistercian Abbey Our Lady of Dallas July 19 and 20, 2014 Matthew 13: 24-43

NOT CLASSICAL, COVENANTAL

QUESTION 45. Daring. Article 1. Is daring contrary to fear?

Saint Augustine and the problem of free will

De Casu Diaboli: An Examination of Faith and Reason Via a Discussion of the Devil s Sin

The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World. In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages, Kripke expands upon a conclusion

Free will and foreknowledge

Is Ockham off the hook?

Augustine s famous story about his own theft of pears is perplexing to him at

2016_ 열린교회 _ 산상세미나 5

QUESTION 65. The Connectedness of the Virtues

Rogers Little Swerve: The Confessions of a Not-So-Open-Theist

The Uniqueness of God in Anselm s Monologion

Avicenna, Proof of the Necessary of Existence

SAMPLE. Wondrous Love Mass. Paul Hillebrand and Kevin Keil

John Duns Scotus s Metaphysics of Goodness: Adventures in 13th-Century Metaethics

V A R I A. Some Aspects of the Pelagian Controversy. Anton ADĂMUŢ *

1/8. The Third Analogy

1 Concerning distinction 39 I ask first whether God immutably foreknows future

Chapter 6. Fate. (F) Fatalism is the belief that whatever happens is unavoidable. (55)

Worship. A Thomistic Perspective on. Francisco J. Romero Carrasquillo, PhD

PROLOGUE TO PART 1-2

Ordinatio III, distinction 30, the single question: Must we love our enemies through

Augustine. On Free Choice (De Libero Arbitrio)

Bless the Lord, O my soul, and all within me, his holy name. Glory be to the Father... ly! ly! ly! ly! Lord. Though. Lord. j œ. ing.

Thomas Aquinas on God s Providence. Summa Theologiae 1a Q22: God s Providence

Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard

QUESTION 34. The Person of the Son: The Name Word

THE METAPHYSICS BOOK IX, CHAPTER IV

Sectional Contents PART ONE REVELATION AND REASON, RATIONALITY AND FAITH CHRIST THE LOGOS

SAMPLE. Table of Contents Eucharistic Prayer II Preface Dialogue...3 Preface...4 Holy...6 Pre-Consecration...8 We Proclaim Your Death...

THE SUBJUNCTIVE IN LATIN A Guide (by no means complete)

Pain, Suffering, and a Benevolent God. Topic: The Problem of Good and Evil

The Early Church worked tirelessly to establish a clear firm structure supported by

QUESTION 8. The Objects of the Will

REVIEW. St. Thomas Aquinas. By RALPH MCINERNY. The University of Notre Dame Press 1982 (reprint of Twayne Publishers 1977). Pp $5.95.

QUESTION 111. The Divisions of Grace

First Treatise <Chapter 1. On the Eternity of Things>

QUESTION 45. The Mode of the Emanation of Things from the First Principle

ANNEX INTERNATIONAL CONTEST. The First Conference

The Will as Mediator between Man and God in Bonaventure s Philosophy **

QUESTION 39. The Goodness and Badness of Sadness or Pain

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

INCARNATION Michael Gorman School of Philosophy The Catholic University of America

Questions Concerning the Existences of Christ

What Everybody Knows Is Wrong with the Ontological Argument But Never Quite Says. Robert Anderson Saint Anselm College

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

QUESTION 63. The Cause of Virtue

c Peter King, 1987; all rights reserved. WILLIAM OF OCKHAM: ORDINATIO 1 d. 2 q. 6

Theme: Bible Heroes Lesson: Jonah Disobeys God Lesson Text: Jonah 1:1-10. Teacher Preparation

Inconsistency within a Reconciling Project Antony Flew Hume Studies Volume IV, Number 1 (April, 1978), 1-6.

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Baha i Proofs for the Existence of God

Iamze Gagua (Tbilisi) THE MYTH OF ACTEON AND THE REASON FOR OVIDIUS' EXILE

QUESTION 86. What Our Intellect Has Cognition of in Material Things

Anselm on Freedom: A Defense of Rogers s Project, A Critique of her Reconciliation of Libertarian Freedom with God the Creator Omnium

BOOK REVIEWS. The arguments of the Parmenides, though they do not refute the Theory of Forms, do expose certain problems, ambiguities and

007 - LE TRIANGLE DES BERMUDES by Bernard de Montréal

WHAT CAN THE BLUES BROTHERS TEACH US ABOUT THE COMMON GOOD? A PRIMER ON THOMAS AQUINAS PHILOSOPHY OF NATURAL LAW. W. Penn Dawson *

THE DEEPER LIFE 2 Thessalonians 5:23 Lars Wilhelmsson

QUESTION 44. The Procession of Creatures from God, and the First Cause of All Beings

THEISM AND BELIEF. Etymological note: deus = God in Latin; theos = God in Greek.

QUESTION 59. The Relation of the Moral Virtues to the Passions

QUESTION 3. God s Simplicity

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

WHAT ARISTOTLE TAUGHT

FORM, ESSENCE, SOUL: DISTINGUISHING PRINCIPLES OF THOMISTIC METAPHYSICS JOSHUA P. HOCHSCHILD

QUESTION 66. The Equality of the Virtues

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

# œ œ. œ œ œ œ œ œ. œ œ œ œ. œ œ œ # œ œ œ. & # œ œ œ œ. & # œ œ œ œ œ. Introit Psalm 118, mode I. Opening Hymn

Latina Christiana I Lesson XV

Transcription:

FREEDO M IN THE CITY OF GOD N oel D. O D onoghue Saint A u g u stin e s De Civitate Dei is one o f the classics o f C hristian apologetics. It is im m ediately and superficially a defence o f the C hristian faith against those w ho saw C hristianity as responsible for the fall o f R o m e in 410, but o f course its scope and intention are m uch w ider than this. It is a full-scale review o f b o th the resources and defences o f C hristendom m ade by its greatest strategist, m ade w ith a specially careful eye to the weak points in this already form idable em pire, u n d ertaken and carried th ro u g h w ith such th oroughness and foresight th a t this em pire could not only w ithstand all fu tu re vicissitudes o f w orld history, b u t could use them to extend its fron tiers. Yet the p aradox is th a t the w eak points are still w eak, and w ere not in fact m ade any stronger by A u g u stin e s sensitive exploration o f them. A t least this is tru e, it seems to m e, in th e case o f the question I wish to exam ine here, th a t o f reconciling m a n s freedom w ith G o d s action. I say th a t there is a parad o x here, for th o u g h I will argue th a t A ugustin e s subtle ploys do not really w ork, yet it will also be clear th a t this p articu lar w eak point will not be b reached by the enem y. I I am concerned specially and exclusively w ith C h apters IX, X an d XI o f the F ifth B ook o f the De Civitate Dei. In this F ifth B ook, the culm ination o f the first p art o f the w ork, A ugustine is concerned w ith th e virtues and trium phs o f pagan R om e, but before considering the significance o f this great h u m an achievem ent he feels constrained to consider the w hole question o f chance, fate, h u m an freedom and D ivine ordinance. H e has to find his w ay betw een tho se w ho say w ith th e Stoics th a t everything is p redeterm ined by fate, and those, like C icero, w ho deny this, an d also deny all Divine foreknow ledge and p red eterm in atio n this in the nam e o f h u m an freedom. A ugustine rejects b o th points o f view w ith great force and assurance, and puts forw ard the C h ristian view point, as he u n d erstands it, w hich affirm s both h um an freedom and the divine foreknow ledge and creativity. T he problem he has to face in these C hapters is th a t o f reconciling the tw o. If we leave aside the repeated rhetorical restatem ent o f his position we are left w ith tw o lines o f argum ent aim ing at a reasonable reconciliation o f the tw o poles o f the a ffirm atio n. T he first is by w ay o f a distinction betw een voluntas an d potestas. S peaking o f G od, th e u n created spirit, he says:

28 NOEL D. O DONOGHUE In eius voluntate summa potestas est, quae creatorum spirituum bonas voluntates adiuvat, malas iudicat, omnes ordinat et quibusdam tribuit potestates, quibusdam non tribuit. Sicut enim omnium naturarum creator est, ita omnium potestatum dator, non voluntatum. Malae quippe voluntates ab illo non sunt, quoniam contra naturam sunt, quae ab illo est. (Chapter IX, Book V) So, all power comes from God, and this includes the power exercised in the willing and doing o f evil deeds. And all good willing, i.e. all free acts that are also good, come from God. But free acts that are evil (malae voluntates) do not come from God. We must remember that he has argued at length in the De Libero A rbitrio that the source o f moral evil is not in God but in the evil will. Now, even though the malae voluntates do not come from God, yet God places them in the order o f events (omnes ordinat). But, and this is really disconcerting, he does not give power to these malae voluntates: quibusdam non tribuit. Yet evil willing is very real in the world, very powerful. If its power does not come from God whence does it come? Earlier in Chapter IX Augustine has quoted Psalm 62: Semel locutus est Deus, duo haec audivi, quoniam potestas Dei est, et tibi, Domine, misericordia, qui reddis unicuique secundum opera eius. It is from here that he takes the word potestas, and as he understands the word here it refers to ultimate power and the ultimate disposition o f things in which evil has no part. God has spoken once and for all, and this can be called fatum (a fando), and in this sense Augustine will accept fate, though not in the Stoic sense which would destroy human freedom. For among the things God orders is human nature and human freedom. Here Augustine comes up with a very subtle argument. Freedom, he says in effect, is either something or nothing. If it is nothing it cannot be predetermined by God, for predetermination and foreknowledge is of what is. It is preordained only if it is something, i.e. if in fact human freedom exists. So far then is divine preordination from destroying freedom that it is essential to it: the two belong together. I shall return to this argument in a moment. It still remains to make real sense o f the assertion that evil willing is not given any power. Let us assume that there is question o f ultimate power, that is to say a place in what an Irish poet has called the final shake-up. It yet does have power, enormous power, here and now, and we are still left with the question o f the source of this power. The scholastics will later distinguish between the order of being and the order o f specification, saying that in evil willing, the being o f the act is given by God but it is man himself who specifies the act. If one presses this distinction it seems to lead back to a meontic view of evil, that the evil

FREEDOM IN THE CITY OF GOD 29 act is good as far as it goes, but is simply lacking in human fulness of scope and order. For example the love A has for B is good, but is it good enough to let B go free if that is best for B? This of course is good Augustinism, but is it what Augustine has in mind here? It may well be at the back of his mind, but it is surely very far back and can scarcely be called on to explicate the text before us. II. Let us look at another paragraph of the same Chapter IX o f Book V of the D e Civitate Dei. This comes immediately before the subtle argument about something and nothing, and it runs as follows: Sunt igitur nostrae voluntates et ipsae faciunt quidquid volendo facimus, quod non fieret si nollemus. Quidquid autem aliorum hominum voluntate nolens quisque patitur, etiam sic voluntas valet, etsi non illius, tamen hominis voluntas; sed potestas Dei, (Nam si voluntas tantum esset nec posset quod vellet, potentiore impediretur; nec sic tamen voluntas nisi voluntas esset, nec alterius, sed eius esset qui vellet, etsi non posset implere quod vellet.) Unde quidquid praeter suam voluntatem patitur homo, non debet tribuere humanis vel angelicis vel cuiusquam creati spiritus voluntatibus, sed eius potius qui dat potestatem volentibus. (Chapter IX, Book V) Here again the distinction between potestas and voluntas is crucial. There seems to be a kind o f parallelism between the two which sometimes runs smoothly and sometimes does not, and this paragraph is concerned with those occasions when it does not. The will wills, but the potestas is not available. This blocks the will but not in its willing. This is as free as ever. As far as voluntas goes the blockage does not matter. Augustine is not here making the point that the will cannot be coerced, that nothing can touch a man s inner freedom. This is true only of som e wills, though it might be argued that only in such cases is will true to itself as free will. But here the point seems to be that the will has its own sphere, its own world, its own reality. And Augustine is arguing both that the will is and does something (and so comes under an all-embracing providence and divine causality) and that of itself and by itself the evil will does nothing, has no potestas at its disposal. How is one to resolve this contradiction? I am not sure that it can be resolved. I am not sure that Augustine is dealing with realities here rather than words? Is it all simply a piece o f rhetorical sleight-of-hand? Or is Augustine a victim o f his own subtlety, his own persuasive apologetic? Perhaps, however, we may find a clue in the statement that the malae voluntates are contra naturam (Chapter IX). For nature is what flows from God, and where the potestas flows from God into the good acts of willing then what is willed is both something and also preordained. But what if this

30 NOEL D. O DONOGHUE good willing is blocked? What if the act of willing runs counter to the flow o f nature? This (evil) act is not from God, for it has no place within the final ordering of things, no place then within the present flow of things. So we can say that this (evil) act has no real power within the order of nature, within the order o f the ultimate and the finally real. Of course the (evil) act is effective here and now, and seems just as powerful as the good act. But in truth the evil act in itself is nothing and in itself achieves nothing; the power that attaches to it belongs in fact entirely to God who disposes all power according to his own will. In doing this God draws good out o f evil, or rather transforms what seems evil into good. Later, Aquinas will say that it is thus most of all that God manifests his goodness, in the power not simply of creating but of creating out of the most recalcitrant material. We might say that God not only created out of nothing but out o f that minus-infinity that is at the other side of nothingness. Perhaps the creative genius of Michelangelo will serve as an analogy of the creative genius of God. Michelangelo made his statue of David from a block of marble that was flawed and this flaw became that marvellously beautiful twist of the young man s body. One can imagine that the block of marble was perfect and that the sculptor came along to find an enemy hacking at it; instead of stopping him, turning o ff the power as it were, Michelangelo recognising the challenge to his own creative power allows the destructive activity to go ahead, at least up to a certain point. It is possible to complete the analogy by supposing that the enemy is sustained in being by the sculptor, who hopes that he will finally turn from his evil ways and become himself creative. Semel locutus est Deus: the final pattern and the great purpose shines out like the sun and it penetrates to the very depths o f all man s ways and days, illuminating man s freedom, so that the good will shine with new radiance and the specious light of the bad will disappear. It is as if the divine light discovered itself within the points of light that mark the pattern of the humanly free and good. G od s locutio, God s fatum does not destroy man s freedom but rather sustains, affirms and transforms it. III. Let us look again at the passage quoted above from Chapter IX: In eius voluntate etc. It will be clear by now, I think, that there is a triple dichotomy in this passage: that between voluntas and potestas, that between good and bad acts o f willing (bonae and malae voluntates), and that between fulfilled and unfulfilled acts o f willing (quibusdam tribuit potestates, quibusdam non tribuit). Our first reading assumed a parallel between the second and third dichotomy which is not there. Good acts may be fulfilled or unfulfilled; bad acts may be fulfilled or unfulfilled. It is true that only good acts receive

FREEDOM IN THE CITY OF GOD 31 divine assistance (bonas adiuvat) but this assistance must be distinguished from potestas. The good act o f the will may not get beyond the point of decision, may be frustrated in the external order, as may happen also with the bad act. There is a sense in which the divine action is the total cause of the good act, even though it is completely free, for all being derives from God and free action is a category of being. But this is not the order o f assistance which involves the co-operation or synergy o f God and man. It is because they ignored this distinction that some o f Augustine s later com mentators and followers fell into the trap of predestinationism and the denial of human freedom. In saying that God is the giver (dator) of freedom Augustine assumes that the gift is, in fact, freedom which requires, further, divine assistance for its proper use. In fact it is only because freedom, precisely as freedom, is something that it comes under God s creative activity. But what o f the evil act? Insofar as it is effective its power comes from God and it is fitted into the final pattern. But the act itself, the evil decision, is not given by God, cannot be counted among his gifts. But surely the evil will, the act o f evil willing can be very real, is a very definite entity? After all it brings, in Augustine s own principle, heavy judgment and heavy punishment. Is it not freedom just as much as the good decision is freedom? Here again, and finally, we reach the crux, the apparent contradiction in Augustine s position. What is to become o f the entity of evil acts in a system in which all entities come from God, and where it is denied that evil acts come from God? It would seem that for Augustine the evil act (as decision, leaving out of question its effectiveness, its external coefficient) is somehow absorbed into the pattern of the divine plan, has its reality only as having ordinatio in this plan (omnes ordinat). But is not this plan already there, already determined in G od s mind and purposes, and with it the evil acts that form part of it? But the evil acts have no positive reality; they are flaws in nature, nonentities. It is true that the divine activity flows into these crevices o f human freedom, creating anew and transforming the whole o f creation. But surely evil acts have evil consequences? Yes, but, for Augustine, these consequences are simply part of the flawed world that awaits transformation and receives it. This is perhaps as far as one can press the matter along Augustine s own track o f thought.1he was on the road away from dualism. It was perhaps a longer road than he thought. What is clear from the above analysis is that 1. For a comprehensive account o f Augustine s concept o f freewill see Augustine, Philosopher o f Freedom by Mary T. Clark (Desclee: Paris & New York 1958). This book includes a full bibliography and a detailed Index o f References. For a more recent discussion see La notion de liberte en philosophic Augustinienne by F.-J. Thonnard in Revue des Etudes Augustiniennes 1970 (16) pp.242ff.

32 NOEL D. O DONOGHUE he will refuse to lighten his pack by casting away either Divine omnipotence or human freedom. Or, to change the metaphor, Augustine will continue to defend the exposed turret of human freedom within the City of God even though it continues to draw the enemies fire. He will not pull back to where so many of his followers have barricaded themselves, in the secure fortress o f predestination. For the rest, it would seem that Augustine was battling with a problem the solution to which forces the Christian apologist towards a very sensitive and spiritual concept o f the divine omnipotence (as an expression o f love), and a relational concept o f human freedom (as the capacity to respond or not to respond to the invitation of love). We are still searching for this.