Nietzsche s agon for politics?

Similar documents
Friedrich Nietzsche and European Nihilism Paul van Tongeren

Iowa Journal of Cultural Studies

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

What Can New Social Movements Tell About Post-Modernity?

Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008

Nietzsche s Philosophy as Background to an Examination of Tolkien s The Lord of the Rings

Philosophy of Ethics Philosophy of Aesthetics. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Philosophical Review.

Cosmopolitan Theory and the Daily Pluralism of Life

A Philosophical Study of Nonmetaphysical Approach towards Human Existence

Phil 2303 Intro to Worldviews Philosophy Department Dallas Baptist University Dr. David Naugle

History of Education Society

Practical Wisdom and Politics

Book review by Yunus Tuncel, Ph.D., The New School

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

To Provoke or to Encourage? - Combining Both within the Same Methodology

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Going beyond good and evil

3. RELIGIOUS EDUCATION IN CATHOLIC SCHOOLS

Plato's Republic: Books I-IV and VIII-IX a VERY brief and selective summary

The Human Deficit according to Immanuel Kant: The Gap between the Moral Law and Human Inability to Live by It. Pieter Vos 1

A Framework for the Good

Violence as a philosophical theme

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Monday 4:15 6:00; Wednesday 1-3; Thursday 2-3

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

Wisdom: Plato, Aristotle, and Nietzsche

Florida State University Libraries

Chapter Six. Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

The Problem of Freedom. Taylor Thompson, Columbia University

ON DEGREE ACTUALISM ALEXANDRA LECLAIR 1 INTRODUCTION

BENJAMIN R. BARBER. Radical Excess & Post-Modernism Presentation By Benedetta Barnabo Cachola

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT FALL SEMESTER 2009 COURSE OFFERINGS

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

Well-Being, Time, and Dementia. Jennifer Hawkins. University of Toronto

REVIEW THE DOOR TO SELLARS

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

The Role of Love in the Thought of Kant and Kierkegaard

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Christopher Janaway, Beyond Selflessness: Reading Nietzsche s Genealogy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xi

Radical Centrism & the Redemption of Secular Philosophy

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Contesting Nietzsche

Spinoza on God, Affects, and the Nature of Sorrow

PROSPECTS FOR A JAMESIAN EXPRESSIVISM 1 JEFF KASSER

Yunus Tuncel, Agon in Nietzsche. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 2013.

Follow this and additional works at: Part of the Philosophy Commons

ETHICS AND THE FUTURE OF HUMANKIND, REALITY OF THE HUMAN EXISTENCE

SAT Essay Prompts (October June 2013 )

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God

Introduction. Anton Vydra and Michal Lipták

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

Religious Education as a Part of General Education. Professor George Albert Coe, Ph.D., Northwestern University, Evanston, Illinois

1/10. Descartes Laws of Nature

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

John Locke Institute 2018 Essay Competition (Philosophy)

Interpassivity: The necessity to retain a semblance of the mundane?

Differences between Psychosynthesis and Jungian Psychology 2017 by Catherine Ann Lombard. Conceptual differences

Qué es la filosofía? What is philosophy? Philosophy

MDiv Expectations/Competencies ATS Standard

Life has become a problem.

National Quali cations

Is Love a Reason for a Trinity?

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

BLEEDING HEARTS AND BLOODY MINDS REASON IN ACTION IN ALTRUISTIC BENEVOLENCE. Howard Adelman

James V. Schall characteristically introduces. Unserious Docility. Thomas P. Harmon

ON THE INCOMPATIBILITY BETWEEN ARISTOTLE S AND KANT S IMPERATIVES TO TREAT A MAN NOT AS A MEANS BUT AS AN END-IN- HIMSELF

ON WRITING PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAYS: SOME GUIDELINES Richard G. Graziano

Master of Arts in Health Care Mission

Teachur Philosophy Degree 2018

ETHICAL POSITIONS STATEMENT

Johnson_Understanding Ethical Statements in the Educational Learning Environment_ docx

Nietzsche and Problem of Nihilism

What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age

The Challenge of God. Julia Grubich

In Search of a Political Ethics of Intersubjectivity: Between Hannah Arendt, Emmanuel Levinas and the Judaic

Gibbs, Eddie, Leadership Next, Downers Grove, Illinois: Intervarsity Press, pp. Reviewed by Parnell M. Lovelace, Jr.

The Social Nature in John Stuart Mill s Utilitarianism. Helena Snopek. Vancouver Island University. Faculty Sponsor: Dr.

When is philosophy intercultural? Outlooks and perspectives. Ram Adhar Mall

Plato s Concept of Soul

Affirmative Dialectics: from Logic to Anthropology

Anaximander. Book Review. Umberto Maionchi Carlo Rovelli Forthcoming, Dunod

The Need for Metanormativity: A Response to Christmas

A Backdrop To Existentialist Thought

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial.

The Human Science Debate: Positivist, Anti-Positivist, and Postpositivist Inquiry. By Rebecca Joy Norlander. November 20, 2007

Truth, Justice, and the Common Good: Core Capstone Final Essay

Phil Aristotle. Instructor: Jason Sheley

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body

Relative and Absolute Truth in Greek Philosophy

EXECUTION AND INVENTION: DEATH PENALTY DISCOURSE IN EARLY RABBINIC. Press Pp $ ISBN:

- 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance

Transcription:

Nietzsche s agon for politics? Yunus Tuncel Agon in Nietzsche Marquette University Press, Milwaukee, Wisconsin, 2013, 293pp., $29.00 / 17.50, ISBN: 978-0874628234 Christa Davis Acampora Contesting Nietzsche University of Chicago Press, Chicago and London, 2013, 280pp., $35.00 / 24.50, ISBN: 978-0226923901 Contemporary Political Theory (2015) 14, e12 e17. doi:10.1057/cpt.2014.3; published online 28 October 2014 In the last decades, Nietzsche s conception of agon has been the source of an important current in political theory, namely, agonistic democratic theory. Proponents of democratic agonism take for granted that agon is a political concept. Recently, two works on the concept of agon in Nietzsche have cast into doubt its political character. What is gained and what is lost in our understanding of Nietzsche and of contemporary political theory by shifting the locus of agon away from politics? Agon in Nietzsche offers a detailed study of ancient Greek sources on the culture of competition and how Nietzsche connects to this tradition of contest, particularly in his early period of writing (1870 1874), but also in his later writings. According to Tuncel, the spirit of ancient Greece is always present in Nietzsche s thought and writings and he shows how central ideas like eternal return, overhuman and will to power can be traced back to the spirit of ancient agonism (p. 8). For Tuncel, agon is a dynamic that essentially makes possible Greek culture, to which the Greek idea of politics belongs as one component among others. Hence agon cannot be reduced to politics. Where then does agon find its roots? Tuncel begins his book by arguing that agon has a decidedly religious root. In the first two chapters of the book, The Mythic Context of Agon and The Sacred in Agon, Tuncel argues that Nietzsche derives his notion of agon from Greek polytheism and from its conception of the sacred. Greek polytheism is open-ended, hierarchical, creative and playful and can be conceived as hierarchically overlapping agonistic circles from the gods down to the mortal competing forces (p. 28). Tuncel holds that what motivated Nietzsche throughout his writing career was to combat the reduction of the sacred to the confines of www.palgrave-journals.com/cpt/

everyday morality and rational theology, as well as its further obliteration by scientific rationality and its philosophically shallow idea of secularism (p. 59). The religious origin of agon is again visible in Tuncel s discussion of the cathartic effects of agon as a form of cultural transfiguration throughout Chapters 3 5. Here agon functions within a general scheme of giving meaning to life by explaining suffering and giving a sublimated form to potentially destructive passions and affects. In Suffering, Destruction and Transfiguration (Chapter 3), Tuncel shows how agon provides a cultural context that allows for the externalization of destructive animal instincts (p. 74). As such agon prevents the internalization of the destructive human tendencies such as revenge, resentment and ultimately bad conscience (p. 76). In Agon and War (Chapter 4), Tuncel discusses how in Greek agonistic culture, but also in Nietzsche s own writings, war is transformed into agon and, in Agonal Feelings (Chapter 5), he treats hate and love, ambition and envy as feelings inscribed in and cultivated through contest and how contest keeps these feelings in measure thus avoiding their inherent dangers of destruction or excess. Tuncel reaches the political meaning of agonism, starting in Chapter 6, The Question of Agonistic Unity and Active Justice, with a discussion of how competition unified ancient Greeks and their cities around agreed upon rules, customs and laws. But here the potential limitations of keeping Nietzsche s agonism tied down so closely to the Greek understanding of it become more and more apparent. Tuncel argues that Nietzsche s own conception of active justice goes back to the idea of agonal justice of the ancient Greek culture of competition. In fact, Tuncel s analysis of justice puts emphasis on a conception of unity that seems philosophical, rather than political, because it privileges unity over equality: equals are such because they participate in one and the same ethical substance, for example. The work of agonal justice is part of the lived reality of the agonal individual and his world-view which enables him, on the one hand, to manifest his individuality as a striving individual in struggle with his opponent, on the other, to be part of a unity that cultivates such an individuality (p. 115). The modern conception of political equality does not depend on a previously accepted unity of ethical substance or communal value. Tuncel understands Nietzsche s critique of modernity as arising from his philosophy of agon. According to this philosophy, the problem of modernity is precisely its inability to form unity in which the individual can give form to its singular distinction (p. 118). The question that would need to be put here is whether Nietzsche himself holds on to such a concept of unity in the sense that Tuncel reconstructs for the Greeks, or is he not rather interested in its moment of collapse and the birth of something quite different. In recent political theory, working out of the Nietzschean paradigm of will to power, Esposito has argued that what is needed is a nonmetaphysical, non-substantialist conception of unity. Tuncel seems to come close to Esposito s idea of communitas when he writes that what holds people together is a locus that pertains to all and none (p. 123). e13

From a modern perspective, it is clear that Greek culture wrestled with the problem of individuality and perhaps, if one follows Hegel s well-known analysis, collapses under its pressure. Tuncel discusses how the Greeks employed agon in order to make a place for individuality without allowing it to overcome their cultural form or unity. Chapters 7 through 10 offer interesting discussions of the Greek agonistic individualism, especially as this is found in their ideals of rhetoric and paideia. Tuncel emphasizes that both in the Greek paideia and in Nietzsche, agon is not only about the making of the higher individual through exercise and fighting among equals, but also about community making (p. 199). But this privilege of community is what could be further questioned: on what basis is it asserted by the Greeks? Tuncel convincingly argues that what distinguishes Greek paideia and Nietzsche s conception of education is openness towards animality: rather than taming the beast within man, they promote a morality of breeding where animality is cultivated, revered and held up as a symbol for imitation (p. 209). Festivals and Spectacles of Agon (Chapter 11) shows that competition must be understood within the more general context of the life of a culture, where contest took place in the form of festivals and spectacles, both central themes in the Greek world and in Nietzsche s work. The festivals and spectacles of agon provide an opportunity to let loose the human being s animal self thereby entering into union with other, nature and animal life (p. 214). This leads one to ask whether, at least for Nietzsche, there is not an outside to culture, namely, animal life, that stands beyond the cultural imperative of unity that otherwise agon is called upon to recreate. Given the overall religious and cultural reading of agon that Tuncel offers in this book, it comes as no surprise that in Political Theory and Agon (Chapter 12) he also directs his critical energy to dismantle the politico-theoretical reading of agon found in contemporary democratic theorists. Tuncel is particularly critical of the attempts to hold up Nietzsche to the standard of democracy (p. 233f ). Instead, he claims that one needs to understand Nietzsche s ideas and his critique from the ground up and try to put the pieces together for a social and political vision (p. 234). Unfortunately, Tuncel remains silent on what this social and political vision may be. In contrast to Tuncel who reads Nietzsche s conception of agon out of its ancient Greek sources, Acampora develops the notion of agon primarily out of a reading of Nietzsche s philosophy. The main argument put forth in Contesting Nietzsche is that Nietzsche s views of the agon shape what and how he argues in the field of philosophy. However, the consequence of this thesis appears to be that Nietzsche s philosophy is ultimately reducible to a theory of value, a value philosophy, whereas for Tuncel the creation of values is just one aspect of agon in Nietzsche. According to Acampora s interpretation, agon offers Nietzsche the guiding thread to conceive of the distinction between culture and nature by viewing agonistic interaction as generating values that can be shared and truly bring about a sense of common purpose and community; as well as how this general orientation of evaluation and its transmission and reproduction of values differed from Nietzsche s contemporary e14

culture (p. 9). For Acampora, agon served as a site for the production of meaning, for making and remaking the social order and cultural fabric (p. 36) by channelling and sublimating the human being s tendencies to aggression and resistance (p. 4). What is the common root that holds together the political or social function of agon as taming of aggressiveness that makes possible community, and the function of providing a value for life that allows us to bear the fact of suffering and meaninglessness of life itself? The answer given by Acampora turns on the centrality of Homer and the idea of struggle at the heart of tragic art. In Agon as Analytic, Diagnostic, and Antidote (Chapter 1), she begins by laying out Nietzsche s agonistic framework based on a detailed analysis of Nietzsche s Homer s Contest. In Chapter 2, Contesting Homer: The Poiesis of Value, Acampora shows that Nietzsche considers how Homer revaluates the significance of human existence by replacing the conception of human life as essentially a form of punishment from which only death can provide relief (the wisdom of Silenus). Homer is an exemplary affirmative revaluator who achieved this distinction by introducing a means of social and cultural organization that facilitated the pursuit of positive higher values, namely, excellence through contest (p. 9). In Chapter 3, Contesting Socrates: Nietzsche s (Artful) Naturalism, Acampora follows Nietzsche s critique of Socrates and Plato according to which their sublimation of agon into philosophical dialectics diminishes contestability, constricts the possibilities for agonistic engagement and fixes in advance the potential outcomes, such that the regenerative potency of agonism was lost (p. 11). In contrast to Platonic metaphysics and Socratic dialectics, Nietzsche upholds a philosophical form of artistry that Acampora designates as artful naturalism, based on a productive contest between art and science (p. 12). Furthermore, Nietzsche views Socrates as shifting the field of agonism from the social and public to the psychic and private thus diminishing the communal benefits of agonism. Socrates destroyed the basic elements for the contest at the heart of tragedy when he drove out Dionysus and transmogrified Apollo (p. 83). Socrates replaced tragedy by a form of contestation that is ultimately self-destructive and liable to a particularly intense form of selfdirected violence (p. 83). Such violence is precisely what lies at the heart of Contesting Paul: Toward an Ethos of Agonism (Chapter 4) that takes up Nietzsche s contest with Paul and his adoption and spiritualization of struggle in Christianity. Acampora holds that the model of Christian agony encourages a form of struggle that debilitates those who emulate it (p. 110). The death of agon under Paul is for Nietzsche the assassination of any form of nobility: it obliterates distinction, difference and the very basis for genuine respect (p. 122). What is at stake in Nietzsche s contest with Paul is the development of moral values, specifically in their relation to epistemic values, and the processes and organization involved in generating these values (p. 12). In this context, Acampora discusses our current conceptions of guilt and responsibility as well as the more general problem of agency and Nietzsche s critique of e15

conceptions of intentional agency. She claims that a reconceptualization of moral agency is required to overcome the Pauline economy of guilt and debt and to redeem us from the suffering and pain it inflicts on human beings (p. 13). However, it is unclear whether for Acampora the critique of Paul is functional to an ethical understanding of agon as generator of communal values that precede and perhaps cannot cope with the irony of the modern ideas of equality and subjectivity. The book culminates with a discussion of Nietzsche s conception of subjectivity in Contesting Wagner: How One Becomes What One Is (Chapter 5). For Acampora, Nietzsche s famous formula to become what one is refers to an idea of the subject as a dynamic order of rank between a multiplicity of drives and this organization is political (p. 160). The becoming refers to how one goes about ordering the drives that one is, and in this way turning contingency into necessity and attaining the love of destiny, amor fati. Acampora argues that for Nietzsche there are essentially two ways of ordering drives: through love and through war. It is with respect to love that the contest with Wagner s ideal of selflessness helps Nietzsche develop his own conception of ideal selfishness [Selbstsucht] as a form of care of self that is intended to give place to the procreation of great deeds and thoughts. Acampora s detailed discussion of Nietzsche s conception of selfishness is stimulating, particularly when she attempts to link it with Nietzsche s conception of responsibility. Ultimately, Acampora models responsibility on the relation between a mother to a child, basing herself on the image that Nietzsche uses to exemplify the relation of the subject pregnant with the thought or deed that will overcome it (pp. 176 178). Here, Acampora could have pursued her discussion of natality as political, for instance, by relating it to Arendt s claim that actions are rooted in the condition of natality. Arendt s theory of action was clearly influenced by Nietzsche. Likewise, when Acampora next discusses the other mode of becoming who one is, namely, through a praxis of war, of agonism with others who are valued as enemies, the political meaning of war as an ordering of rank does not clearly come through. Thus, the original claim that such organization of drives is always political remains undeveloped. Much like Tuncel, Acampora emphasizes that what motivated and nourished Nietzsche s interest in these facets of Greek culture was the social and public good of competition, not the ways in which competitive institutions celebrated individuality and personal accomplishment (p. 6). In other words, Nietzsche saw in the Greek agon a dynamic that made possible the unity or ethical substance of a peculiar culture and its values and meanings, and how this same dynamic allowed this culture to proliferate its values and meanings in the agonistic encounter with other cultural formations. By the end of Contesting Nietzsche one wonders how this discussion of agon fits together with Nietzsche as the philosopher who questions the value of values, not as the philosopher who theorizes how value is culturally produced and reproduced. What seems to be missing in Acampora s wide-ranging discussions of his philosophy is perhaps a more basic horizon within which Nietzsche discusses value and agency, namely, the horizon of nihilism, on the one hand, and of e16

trans-human life, on the other. Is agon ultimately a device that contains, for relative short periods of time, the encounter of nihilism and the drives of life, or, does it also cover up the abysses that make it possible? In conclusion, these two admirable studies offer many arguments and much textual evidence to understand the productivity of agon, both for Nietzsche s philosophy and for Greek culture, but neither shows definitively that Nietzsche s philosophy or his politics are themselves contained by the dynamic of agon. On the side of philosophy, Nietzsche seems just as much interested in what elements of life bring down the machinery that creates values and gods in given communities, as in what makes these machines work within given cultural formations. Thus, perhaps, Socrates destructive activity and the emergence of the ascetic ideal ultimately tell us more about the nihilistic components of reality and life than Homer s establishment of Greek culture. On the side of politics, it is unclear whether Nietzsche ever was satisfied with a return to a Greek conception of individuality, contained within the imperatives of cultural unity or substance: this would impoverish what he had to say about the productive ways in which one can adopt and overcome modern equality and subjectivity. Vanessa Lemm University of New South Wales, Sydney, NSW 2052, Australia Universidad Diego Portales, Santiago de Chile, Chile e17