POSITIVISM AND CHRISTIANITY A STUDY OF THEISM AND VERIFIABILITY

Similar documents
145 Philosophy of Science

Chapter 31. Logical Positivism and the Scientific Conception of Philosophy

Ayer and the Vienna Circle

Evidence and Transcendence

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

LENT 2018 THEORY OF MEANING DR MAARTEN STEENHAGEN

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Comments on Scott Soames, Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, volume I

An Empiricist Theory of Knowledge Bruce Aune

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

Templates for Writing about Ideas and Research

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

Gary Ebbs, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry, Cambridge. University Press, 2017, 278pp., $99.99 (hbk), ISBN

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

INDUCTIVE AND DEDUCTIVE

Module 1: Science as Culture Demarcation, Autonomy and Cognitive Authority of Science

A Critical Study of Hans Küng s Ecclesiology

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

PHILOSOPHICAL RAMIFICATIONS: THEORY, EXPERIMENT, & EMPIRICAL TRUTH

Sydenham College of Commerce & Economics. * Dr. Sunil S. Shete. * Associate Professor

This is a longer version of the review that appeared in Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 47 (1997)

Naturalism and is Opponents

STUDIES IN ANALOGY. University oj Notre Dame THE HAGUE MARTINUS NIJHOFF RALPH MCINERNY

Commentary on Sample Test (May 2005)

Adam Smith and the Limits of Empiricism

Dworkin on the Rufie of Recognition

VERIFICATION AND METAPHYSICS

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

Propositional Revelation and the Deist Controversy: A Note

Logical positivism, the enfant terrible of twentieth-century philosophy, began around

Lectures and laboratories activities on the nature of Physics and concepts and models in optic: 1. Scientific sentences


Although Quine is widely known as an influential critic of logical positivism, there is now a

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

HENRY E. KYBURG, JR. & ISAAC LEVI

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection.

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

EMPIRICISM AND SOCIOLOGY

Faith and Thought. A Journal devoted to the study of the inter-relation of the Christian revelation and modem research. Vol. 92 Number I Summer 1961

FOUNDATIONS OF EMPIRICISM

Otto Neurath. Logical Positivism, the Unity of Science Movement and ISOTYPE. Stephen Smith. ARH 490/590 Twentieth Century Language and Vision Seminar

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

1 Why should you care about metametaphysics?

CONCEPT FORMATION IN ETHICAL THEORIES: DEALING WITH POLAR PREDICATES

ON QUINE, ANALYTICITY, AND MEANING Wylie Breckenridge

Presuppositional Apologetics

Junior Research Fellow and Lecturer in Philosophy Worcester College, University of Oxford Walton Street Oxford OX1 2HB Great Britain

HUME'S THEORY OF IMAGINATION

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010).

Emory Course of Study School COS 522 Theology in the Contemporary Church

Lecture 6. Realism and Anti-realism Kuhn s Philosophy of Science

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

PRIMARY AND SECONDARY PRECEPTS IN THOMISTIC NATURAL LAW TEACHING

THE HISTORIC ALLIANCE OF CHRISTIANITY AND SCIENCE

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

LANGUAGE AND ILLUMINATION

Philosophy 780: After Empiricism: Experience and Reality in Kant, Hegel, and Sellars

THE EVENT OF DEATH: A PHENOMENOLOGICAL ENQUIRY

Review of Ronald Dworkin s Religion without God. Mark Satta Ph.D. student, Purdue University

Moral Argument. Jonathan Bennett. from: Mind 69 (1960), pp

Dumitrescu Bogdan Andrei - The incompatibility of analytic statements with Quine s universal revisability

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

Twentieth-Century Analytic Philosophy by Avrum Stroll

THE PROBLEM WITH SOCIAL TRINITARIANISM: A REPLY TO WIERENGA

Index of Templates from They Say, I Say by Gerald Graff and Cathy Birkenstein. Introducing What They Say. Introducing Standard Views

World Religions. These subject guidelines should be read in conjunction with the Introduction, Outline and Details all essays sections of this guide.

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Analyticity, Reductionism, and Semantic Holism. The verification theory is an empirical theory of meaning which asserts that the meaning of a

ACADEMIC SKILLS PROGRAM STUDENT SERVICES AND DEVELOPMENT

On possibly nonexistent propositions

Introduction to Technical Communications 21W.732 Section 2 Ethics in Science and Technology Formal Paper #2

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

THEO 697 The Enlightenment and Modern Theology

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

Ch V: The Vienna Circle (Moritz Schlick, Rudolf Carnap, and Otto Neurath)[title crossed out?]

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

A. J. Ayer ( )

COMPARATIVE STUDIES IN PHENOMENOLOGY

Wilhelm Dilthey and Rudolf Carnap on the Foundation of the Humanities. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

UNIVERSITY OF CALICUT SCHOOL OF DISTANCE EDUCATION. (2011 Admn. onwards) VI Semester B.A. PHILOSOPHY CORE COURSE CONTEMPORARY WESTERN PHILOSOPHY

UNIVERSITY OF ALBERTA MATHEMATICS AS MAKE-BELIEVE: A CONSTRUCTIVE EMPIRICIST ACCOUNT SARAH HOFFMAN

Theological Discourse and the Problem of Meaning

SOVIET RUSSIAN DIALECTICAL MA TERIALISM [DIAMAT]

John Haugeland. Dasein Disclosed: John Haugeland s Heidegger. Edited by Joseph Rouse. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2013.

Lectures on S tmcture and Significance of Science

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

THE PHILOSOPHY OF JOHN DEWEY

V3301 Twentieth-Century Philosophy PHIL V TR 2:40pm-3:55pm- 516 Hamilton Hall - Fall Professor D. Sidorsky

Philosophy. Aim of the subject

THE POSSIBILITY OF AN ALL-KNOWING GOD


AN IDEALISTIC PRAGMATISM

Transcription:

POSITIVISM AND CHRISTIANITY A STUDY OF THEISM AND VERIFIABILITY

POSITIVISM AND CHRISTIANITY A STUDY OF THEISM AND VERIFIABILITY by KENNETH H. KLEIN MARTINUS NIJHOFF / THE HAGUE / 1974

To myfather 1974 by Martinus NijhoJ!, The Hague, Netherlands Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1st edition 1974 All rights reserved, including the right to translate or to reproduce this book or parts thereof in any form ISBN-13: 978-90-247-1581-7 e-isbn-13: 978-94-010-2014-5 001: 10.1007/978-94-010-2014-5

CONTENTS INTRODUCTION VII Chapter I. STATEMENT OF THE ISSUES A. Overview of the Positivist stand upon theism 1 B. Exposition of the Positivist stand on the issues 5 1. "The statement that God exists is, at least putatively, a statement of fact" 5 2. "A necessary condition of a genuine statement of fact is that it must be Verifiable" 13 3. "The statement that God exists is not Verifiable". 21 Retrospect 37 C. Appendix: Unintelligible words and unintelligible sentences 38 Chapter II. THEISM WITHOUT BELIEF IN GoD. 49 A. Religious belief construed as a moral commitment 51 B. Religious belief construed as "slanting". 57 C. Religious belief construed as the contemplating of a "symbol picture". 61 Discussion 68 Transition to Chapters III and IV 73 Chapter III. TESTABILITY AND FACTUAL SIG1"1FICANCE. 75 A. The search for a criterion of factual significance. 76 B. Formulations and difficulties. 81 1. The paradigm case: The criterion of verifiability 82 2. The criterion of verifiability in principle. 84 3. The extended criterion of verifiability in principle 86 4. The criterion of falsifiability in principle. 91

VI CONTENTS 5. The criterion of partial verifiability 6. The criterion of Verifiability C. Further problems 1. Statements about other minds. 2. Statements about "unobservables" in science Retrospect 92 93 97 97 104 111 Chapter N. ARE THEOLOGICAL SENTENCES TESTABLE?. A. Terrestrial falsifiability. B. Eschatological verifiability C. Terrestrial verifiability Retrospect Chapter V. DILEMMAS A. Summary of the argument. B. Objections and dilemmas. 1. Conclusive Verifiability. 2. Verifiability in principle 3. Ad hoc exceptions 4. The translatability criterion 5. Falsifiability and theological statements 6. The transcendence of God. SELECTED BmLlOGRAPHY INDEX 113 115 121 133 149 151 152 154 154 157 159 161 166 169 175 180

INTRODUCTION This essay is conceived as a critical exposition of the central issues that figure in the ongoing conversation between Logical Positivists and neo Positivists on the one hand and Christian apologists on the other. My expository aim is to isolate and to describe the main issues that have emerged in the extended discussion between men of Positivistic turn of mind and men sympathetic to the claims of Christianity. My critical aim is to select typical, influential stands that have been taken on each of these issues, to assess their viability, and to isolate certain dilemmas which discussion of these issues has generated. I am convinced that the now commonly rejected verifiability theory of meaning is very commonly misunderstood and has been rejected by and large for the wrong reasons. Before it is cast off-if it is to be cast off-what is needed is a reconsideration of that theory and of the objections that its several formulations have elicited. Furthermore, at least partially because of a misconstruing of the verifiability doctrine, there have been some interesting-though in my opinion unsuccessful-claims advanced about the testability-status of sentences expressive of Christian belief. Moreover, in their haste to vindicate Christianity, some apologists have been fairly cavalier, in my opinion, about what "Christianity" involves. This volume offers what I hope will be a clear statement and analysis of the principle points at issue between Positivism and Christianity, together with my own assessment of where the argument stands now. My attempt throughout has been to provide for teachers, students, and interested laymen an orderly, concise discussion of several of the most crucial, interrelated issues that figure prominently in this manifestly vivid, still-unclosed chapter of contemporary analytic philosophy of religion. My claim will be that the problems posed by Positivism for Christianity, and for any theism of this type, have not yet been resolved either by the alleged discrediting of Positivism or by the apologetic efforts formulated thus far. The issues examined here are historically associated with the formulation,

vm INTRODUCTION dissemination, and eventual widespread influence of the doctrines of Logical Positivism, a philosophical movement which enjoyed prominence in Austria, England, and America during the second and third decades of this century. Although Logical Positivism, considered as a philosophical movement, is passe, its influence upon recent philosophy of religion is massive, its philosophical afterbirth-linguistic analysis-has been sanguine, and some of its own tenets are still defended, albeit in usually sharply modified form. The doctrines of Logical Positivism have a complicated genealogical history, stemming not only from the writings of Kant and the tradition of British empiricism, but also from writers of more recent vintage-physicists, logicians, sociologists, and philosophers of science. The immediate progenitors of Positivism were a small group of philosophers, scientists, and mathematicians more or less loosely gathered together by Moritz Schlick in the early 1920's at the University of Vienna who gave themselves the name of "the Vienna Circle." The officially recognized precursors of Positivist ideas are remembered in a sort of Positivist manifesto-wissenschaftliche Weltauf!assung, Der Wiener Kreis-written in 1929 by Rudolf Carnap, Otto Neurath, and Hans Hahn. No attempt will be made in this volume at historical completeness, completeness either with respect to the full evolution and variety of Positivist doctrines or with respect to the burgeoning variety of responses offered in service to Christian apologetics. Readers interested in the broader conceptual picture would do well to look at A. J. Ayer's Logical Positivism and at Frederick Ferre's Language, Logic, and God and to follow up some of the generous bibliographical leads provided there. My focus in this essay is with-so to speak-hard-core Positivism as it bears on Christianity and with more or less direct, first-generation responses to Positivism in defense of Christian orthodoxy. Developments in Christian apologetics within the last decade or so have been very interesting indeed. These developments, however, open an entirely new chapter and I have thought it best, in the interest of preserving singleness of theme, to neglect them in this study. My book takes a dual look at one of the central doctrines of Logical Positivism-dual, in that I will be looking both at the doctrine itself (the verifiability-doctrine) and also at the impact which this doctrine has made in one field of inquiry (Christian apologetics). That portion of the book which will be devoted to examining the doctrine itself will try to ascertain whether or not the doctrine is tenable and, if so, in what form. If the doctrine is tenable, it constitutes, or appears to constitute, a challenge to-indeed an attack upon-the intelligibility of that type of religious belief exemplified by Christianity. Of course the Positivists' attack upon Christianity was but

INTRODUCTION IX one instance of their hostility to "metaphysics" in general. By focusing upon this one instance of their attack, I do not mean to suggest that Christianity was singled out for special disfavor. But since the Positivistic bite was forcefully felt by philosophers of religion and particularly by Christian apologists, it is appropriate to field the argument at the point of one of its foci of conflict, even though there were others as well. Whether or not the doctrine which the Positivists employed to undermine Christianity is tenable, there are many writers of contemporary philosophy of religion who certainly think that it is. Certain writers are sufficiently worried about the potential destructive fecundity of the doctrine in question that they have tried to answer the Positivists in some way or another. What these answers characteristically have in common is the attempt to vindicate Christianity, or some more general religious orientation of which Christianity is a special case, from Positivist objections. Given this common concern, however, two quite different types of response occur. Some hold that Christianity is not really susceptible to the Positivist's attack in the first place, since Christians are not really disposed to hold what the Positivists think they hold, although they sometimes appear to do so. Others hold that although Christianity is susceptible, in principle, to the Positivists' objection, sentences expressive of a Christian's basic beliefs are not unintelligible in the way the Positivists alleged since these sentences, in their typical use, meet the requirements of intelligibility. These replies to the Positivists' argument, whether the argument is initially sound or not, are interesting in their own right since they highlight topics of concern both to Christian theologians and to philosophers of religion, notably the distinction between the first and the second persons of the Trinity and, more generally, the topic of the transcendence of God. There is another sort of reply to the Positivists which is relevant to their attack upon Christianity. One might raise objections to the doctrine from which the Positivists argued. Professional philosophers have in fact raised such objections, although not necessarily for the purpose of vindicating Christianity or metaphysics. The raising of objections to Positivist doctrine will be considered here as a type of response relevant to their sort of attack upon Christianity, first, because it was indeed a response to Positivism, albeit not one offered in behalf of Christianity, and second, because this type of response is obviously adaptable to the intent of the Christian apologist: if there is no satisfactory formulation of a Positivist type criterion of factual significance, then the Positivist attack upon Christianity fails. Assaying the force of the Positivist attack, therefore, requires assaying the force of the principal objections that have been raised against the several formulations of the Positivists' criterion of factual significance.

x INTRODUCTION The organization of the five chapters of this book is as follows: The purpose of chapter one is to set forth the Positivists' attack upon that type of religious belief exemplified by Christianity and in particular to describe the Positivists' stand on each of the three issues upon which their argument turns. Chapters two, three, and four will discuss each of these three issues in tum by examining three different types of reply, each keyed to one of the constituent issues. The reply considered in chapter two is illustrated by reference to several kinds of meta-theological approach which were influential during the early years of the last decade. Writers who took approaches such as these either explicitly deny, or tend to deny by suggestion, that sentences expressive of a Christian's fundamental belief are of the sort that would make Christianity even open to objections of the Positivist type. The reply considered in chapter three consists in urging that the various formulations of the criterion of factual significance, upon which the Positivists' program rests, are open to very strong objections. The reply considered in chapter four is exemplified by certain attempts neither to circumvent the attack, nor to nullify it, but rather to meet it directly, that is, by trying to show how statements expressive of Christian belief might be tested. Chapter five looks back over my argument and attempts to concede the force of certain recent non-trivial objections to some of its crucial steps without conceding their individual or collective force to overthrow it altogether. I have also tried there to isolate certain dilemmas which the issues discussed generate. A few words of explanation about my notational devices might be in order. I have tried to restrict the employment of single quotation marks, over and above the usual occasions of marking quotations-within-quotations and direct quotations from authors who use them normally, to occasions when the expression so quoted-a word or sentence-is mentioned, as they say, rather than used; that is, when the expression itself is talked about. Double quotation marks acknowledge direct quotation or, where undocumented, indicate the use of the expression so designated in some typical, atypical, or merely specially featured sense. An example might help to make this clear. 'There is a God' (note single quotation marks) is a use-neutral utterance-inscription, or a verbal token when spoken, which could be and normally would be used by someone to make the statement that there is a God. "There is a God" (note double quotation marks) is an inscription of the statement made by someone who uses the utterence 'There is a God' (single quotes) to assert that there is a God. Since I shall usually be discussing not the use-neutral utterance-inscriptions but the statements which typical Positivists and theists could use and normally would use such inscrip-

INTRODUCTION XI tions to make, these inscriptions will ordinarily be enclosed within double quotation-marks. I have also found it convenient to employ some shorthand conventions for locating sources; these are explained in the footnotes where they are introduced. In all cases the pagination of each citation will always be to the volume originally mentioned in locating the citation; for example, all references to an article cited from its reprinting in a larger volume will be to the pagination of that larger volume, even though that volume is mentioned only on the occasion of its first reference. I would like to express my thanks to the many colleagues and students who furthered my labors and to exculpate them one and all for faults and shortsightednesses which remain. Special thanks are due in three quarters. First and foremost, I wish to remember Rogers Albritton, who was my mentor at Harvard University where this book took its original shape as my doctoral dissertation. I should also like to thank the Committee on Creative Work and Research-notably John Strietelmeier- at Valparaiso University, which released me from my teaching duties for half a year to revise the manuscript. I also give thanks to my wife, Mary, whose encouragement and patience were crucial in bringing this phase of the work to completion. Valparaiso University July, 1973