Review of: Mark Johnston, Saving God: Religion after Idolatry, Princeton University Press, 2009 *

Similar documents
Reviewed by Lynne Rudder Baker, University of Massachusetts Amherst

[JGRChJ 9 (2013) R28-R32] BOOK REVIEW

True and Reasonable Faith Theistic Proofs

If God brought about the Big Bang, did he do that before the Big Bang?

Evidence and Transcendence

THEISM AND BELIEF. Etymological note: deus = God in Latin; theos = God in Greek.

Historical attestation: Eyewitness. testimony

Ivan and Zosima: Existential Atheism vs. Existential Theism

Are Miracles Identifiable?

What is Atheism? How is Atheism Defined?: Who Are Atheists? What Do Atheists Believe?:

ARMSTRONGIAN PARTICULARS WITH NECESSARY PROPERTIES *

Philosophy of Religion 21: (1987).,, 9 Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht - Printed in the Nethenanas

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology. In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

Atheism: A Christian Response

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Presuppositional Apologetics

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

12. A Theistic Argument against Platonism (and in Support of Truthmakers and Divine Simplicity)

CHRISTIAN THEOLOGIANS /PHILOSOPHERS VIEW OF OMNISCIENCE AND HUMAN FREEDOM

What God Could Have Made

MIRACLES ARE NOT VIOLATIONS OF THE LAWS OF NATURE BECAUSE THE LAWS DO NOT ENTAIL REGULARITIES

Simplicity and Why the Universe Exists

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

The cosmological argument (continued)

First Principles. Principles of Reality. Undeniability.

STILL NO REDUNDANT PROPERTIES: REPLY TO WIELENBERG

Is the Existence of Heaven Compatible with the Existence of Hell? James Cain

ELEONORE STUMP PENELHUM ON SKEPTICS AND FIDEISTS

Either God wants to abolish evil and cannot, or he can but does not want to, or he cannot and does not want to, or lastly he can and wants to.

Historical Criticism and the Bible

BENEDIKT PAUL GÖCKE. Ruhr-Universität Bochum

HABERMAS ON COMPATIBILISM AND ONTOLOGICAL MONISM Some problems

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

Has Modernity Shown All Arguments for the Existence of God to be Wrong?

Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues

Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2

Armstrongian Particulars with Necessary Properties

The Logical Problem of Evil and the Limited God Defense

Does God exist? The argument from miracles

Chapter 2--How Do I Know Whether God Exists?

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

The Goodness of God in the Judaeo-Christian Tradition

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

IDOLATRY AND RELIGIOUS LANGUAGE

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

Exemplars. AS Religious Studies: Paper 1 Philosophy of Religion

What am I? An immaterial thing: the case for dualism

SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5)

TILLICH ON IDOLATRY. beyond the God of theism... the ground of being and meaning" (RS, p. 114). AUL TILLICH'S concept of idolatry, WILLIAM P.

Since Michael so neatly summarized his objections in the form of three questions, all I need to do now is to answer these questions.

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

SAMPLE. Much of contemporary theology has moved away from classical. Contemporary Responses to Classical Theism GOD IN PROCESS THEOLOGY

USAGE STATEMENT & AGREEMENT. This document is the property of the author(s) and of

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

Creation & necessity

Today we begin our discussion of the existence of God.

Delton Lewis Scudder: Tennant's Philosophical Theology. New Haven: Yale University Press xiv, 278. $3.00.

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

Theme 1: Arguments for the existence of God inductive, AS

Louisiana Law Review. Cheney C. Joseph Jr. Louisiana State University Law Center. Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue Repository Citation

RAHNER AND DEMYTHOLOGIZATION 555

The Odd Couple. Why Science and Religion Shouldn t Cohabit. Jerry A. Coyne 2012 Bale Boone Symposium The University of Kentucky

Ronald Dworkin, Religion without God, Harvard University Press, 2013, pp. 192, 16.50, ISBN

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers

Nancey Murphy, Bodies and Souls, or Spirited Bodies? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006). Pp. x Hbk, Pbk.

Why There s Nothing You Can Say to Change My Mind: The Principle of Non-Contradiction in Aristotle s Metaphysics

Hume s Critique of Miracles

Christ-Centered Critical Thinking. Lesson 6: Evaluating Thinking

THEOLOGY IN THE FLESH

The Supernatural and the Miraculous

VERIFICATION AND METAPHYSICS

Descartes. Efficient and Final Causation

GCE. Religious Studies. Mark Scheme for June Advanced Subsidiary GCE Unit G571: Philosophy of Religion. Oxford Cambridge and RSA Examinations

Chance, Chaos and the Principle of Sufficient Reason

Miracles and New Testament Studies

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first.

Well, how are we supposed to know that Jesus performed miracles on earth? Pretty clearly, the answer is: on the basis of testimony.

Are There Philosophical Conflicts Between Science & Religion? (Participant's Guide)

PHILOSOPHY 5340 EPISTEMOLOGY

Theme 1: Arguments for the existence of God inductive, AS

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

5: Preliminaries to the Argument

Swinburne. General Problem

THE CHALLENGES FOR EARLY MODERN PHILOSOPHY: EDITORIAL INTRODUCTION 1. Steffen Ducheyne

IN QUEST OF AUTHENTIC DIVINITY: CRITICAL NOTICE OF MARK JOHNSTON S SAVING GOD: RELIGION AFTER IDOLATRY

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Discussion notes: The Ordinary Christian s Creed Weeks 3-4 John A. Jack Crabtree October 30, 2011

The Sea-Fight Tomorrow by Aristotle

A Study of Order: Lessons for Historiography and Theology

BEGINNINGLESS PAST AND ENDLESS FUTURE: REPLY TO CRAIG. Wes Morriston. In a recent paper, I claimed that if a familiar line of argument against

Transcription:

Review of: Mark Johnston, Saving God: Religion after Idolatry, Princeton University Press, 2009 * Daniel von Wachter ** 3 January, 2011 The content of the book The thesis of this book is that religions, such as Christianity, which assume that there is a God who sometimes intervenes in the universe and who wants to give man a meaningful life and and afterlife, is idolatrous, childish, and naive, and that instead panentheism is true, God in all, and all in God (119). In the preface, Johnston writes that the book contains some philosophy but is not a work of philosophy. That means that he often declines the philosophically interesting pathways that branch off from what he says, and that he does not interact much with the philosophical literature. * This is a preprint, forthcoming in Dialectica. ** International Academy of Philosophy, Santiago de Chile, http://vonwachter.de, epost@abc.de replace ABC by von-wachter. 1

The book starts with the question Is your God really God? (1) That means: is your faith and trust directed to the one who is in fact the Highest One (9)? The achievement of believing in God can come about only in the wake of God s self-revelation. (9) What we need, in order to clarify the meaning of God thought of as a descriptive name, is a conjunction of descriptions, call it D, such that it no longer seems a substantial question whether D is God. The reader might expect after reading this that Johnston will develop a clear description of the nature of God or analyse alleged revelations. But in fact Johnston develops a revisionary conception of God based on metaphorical descriptions of God. The reason Johnston gives for rejecting traditional monotheism is that it is idolatrous. The basic form of idolatry is worship of lifeless idols. (20) The idol worshipper assumes that the god is here, somehow contained where the idol is, embodied in the idol. Another aspect of idolatry is that the wrong gods are worshipped, but Johnston dismisses this understanding of idolatry as narrow ethnocentrism because it means that it is always the others who are idolaters. (28) He suggests that the mistake of idolatry is the attempt to domesticate the experience of Divinity, to put it to some advantage in a still unredeemed life. And then the true God slips away. In the end, of course, Johnston s view also amounts to saying that it is the others who are idolaters, namely those who believe that God intervenes in the course of events or gives a man an afterlife. Johnston does not argue much for this claim. It is based on the tacit assumption that there is no such God, because on the assumption that there is such a God one would not call belief in such a God idolatrous. Although the subtitle of the book, Religion after Idolatry, may be taken to suggest that the charge of idolatry is the key argument against traditional monotheism, Johnston s claim depends more on his rejection of supernaturalism. Supernaturalism Johnston defines as belief in invisible spiritual agencies whose putative interventions would violate the laws of nature, at least as those laws are presently 2

understood. (40) He calls this a mantic worldview. (41) The claim that interventions in the course of events, such as the resurrection of Jesus, would be violations of the laws of nature Johnston does not defend. He simply assumes that science has shown that there are no, or cannot be, interventions. This, like many aspects of Johnston s book, reminds the reader of German liberal theology. For example, Rudolf Bultmann famously claimed in the same vain: It is impossible to use electric light and the wireless and to avail ourselves of modern medical and surgical discoveries, and at the same time to believe in the New Testament world of daemons and spirits. (Bultmann 1961, p. 5) And like Bultmann, instead of rejecting Christianity, Johnston reinterprets religion to fit naturalism, or replaces it by something which he does not call atheism although it entails that there is no God as usually understood. Johnston assumes that every event flows with a certain probability from previous events, as a matter of natural law. (48) Our world is closed under purely natural causation. Johnston also assumes that there are no immaterial things, such as souls. (184 and 127) So Johnston presupposes naturalism. He also says, as German liberal theologians typically said, that God is not another efficient cause alongside the physical causes (118), although of course theism claims that God sustains all things in being and is thus not just another efficient cause alongside the physical causes. Johnston defends his position with an argument for naturalism from true religion. True religion entails that we should hope that ontological naturalism is true. For ontological naturalism would be a complete defense against the supernatural powers and principalities that could otherwise exploit our tendency to servile idolatry and spiritual materialism. (51) He must mean by this that belief in divine interventions is idolatrous and that belief in naturalism is incompatible with this belief. Another argument which Johnston gives against supernaturalism is that it leads to violence. He suggests that there is religiously 3

required (160) violence. Christianity, he claims, allegedly born from the gospel of love, has fallen into the violence of crusades and inquisitions, and the vengeful threats of apocalypse and hell. Sacrifice, atonement, apocalypse, crusade, jihad (in the baser sense), all this followed by the exquisite tortures of hell are natural outcomes of supernaturalist theism. By mentioning atonement and hell here, he seems to suggest that saying that Christ atoned for our sins or that some will be punished in hell is an act of violence, as if the punishing were done not by God but by the preacher who says that there is a hell. In another chapter Johnston offers an explanation for religious violence: If someone believes that he has been told by God how to live, then he will naturally also believe that God legitimates and cooperates in his violence against the infidels (169). No further defense of these claims is given. Why should a theist not believe that he has no right to kill infidels? While it is possible that some religions teach us to kill infidels, this does not seem to follow in any way from classical theism. To the contrary, theistic belief induces a desire to live a good life because God is believed to be good, and that excludes killing other men. And Johnston s reference to crusades and inquisitions is not backed up by any historical evidence nor by any discussion of the question whether possible wrong actions in the name of Christianity were really carried out by Christians and whether they were done despite rather than because of the Christan faith. A central claim of classical theism, which Johnston rejects, is that God is the first cause of the universe and that hence the universe is distinct from God. Johnston argues against the existence of such a separate creation. (95) Suppose that there is something created by the Highest One, but nonetheless distinct from the Highest One, in that it is not some part, aspect, principle, or mode of the Highest One. Call this other thing the separate creation. If there is such a separate creation, then we 4

would expect the perfections of the Highest One to be to some extent reflected in that separate creation. Consider, then, the joint reality made up of the Highest One and the separate creation. It would seem that this joint reality might be a more appropriate object of worship than the subpart of the reality that is the Highest One. [... ] But only the Highest One deserves worship. So there is no separate creation. What is called creation is some part or aspect or principle of mode of the Highest One. That is why a worshipful attitude to the whole of reality is not idolatrous. (95) So if God creates something, then that thing deserves to be worshipped too. Johnston s worshipful attitude towards creation reminds the reader of Friedrich Schleiermacher s (1799, p. 38) contemplating and feeling the universe. As everything that deserves worship must be a part of God, there cannot be a separate creation. The objectionable premise in this argument is of course that what is created by God deserves to be worshipped. God can perhaps create a being that deserves worship (as Christianity claims that the Father brought into being the Son and the Spirit, who also deserve worship), but why should everything that God creates deserve worship? God could create a rabbit, a golden mountain, or a sun, which would not deserve worship because, although they are made by God, they are not God. But Johnston is content with the argument as it stands. This leads Johnston to panentheism, the view with the motto God in all, and all in God. (119) He wants to distinguish this from pantheism, defined as the view that God and the natural realm are identical. Against such pantheistic identification of God and the natural realm, the panentheist will assert that God is partly constituted by the natural realm, in the sense 5

that his activity is manifest in and through natural processes alone. But this reality goes beyond what is captured by the purely scientific description of all the events that make up the natural realm. (119) How is God more than the natural realm, a causal realm closed under natural law (120)? The answer must lie in the following identification: The Highest one = the outpouring of Existence Itself by way of its exemplification in ordinary existents for the purpose of the self-disclosure of Existence itself. (120) As everything exemplifies Existence or God, understanding something amounts to understanding the Divine Mind: At the idealized limit of this process of deepening understanding, we would come to grasp those modes of presentation of reality that are fully adequate and complete, and so reveal the nature of what they present. In this sense, we would be conforming our minds to the Divine Mind, which may be construed as the totality of fully adequate and complete modes of presentation of reality. (155) So the Mind of God is the totality of fully adequate modes of presentation. Somehow, God is more than the natural realm as captured by the purely scientific description because that description fails to capture the presentational aspect. However, presentation is not another realm: Reality is Being-making-itself-present-to-beings, not a sort of conjunction or fusion of two realms, the realm of sense and the realm of nature. [... ] The beings, that is, each and every creaturely thing that exists, are themselves exemplifications of Being. (156) 6

In order to justify saying that there is a God while at the same time ruling out interventions and denying that there is a separate creation, Johnston says that speaking about God is analogical, i. e. non-literal. The Love of the Highest one was analogized as its outpouring in ordinary existents, its Will as self-disclosure, its Mind as the most revealing presentations found in the realm of sense, and its Power as the totality of the laws of nature. In these respects, the Highest One has by analogy the characteristics of a person, but a person far removed from ordinary personality. [... ] These analogical ways of speaking are] chosen here because they explicitly discourage the idolatrous hope for a Cosmic Intervener who might confer special worldly advantage on his favorites. (158f) The last chapter of the book, Christianity without Spiritual Materialism, seeks to offer a reinterpretation of, or alternative to, Christianity. Throughout the book there are several criticisms of Christianity: supernaturalism is childish and naive and incompatible with the results of science; Christianity requires violence, such as the crusades and inquisitions (160); the Christian doctrine of penal substitution is morally incoherent (161); the belief in Jesus resurrection is mystical theology (43); belief in the afterlife, the other worlds, and so forth is an idolatrous substitute for genuine faith in the importance of goodness (124); and Judaism is a higher religion because it is relatively indifferent to the very idea of an afterlife (176). But nevertheless Johnston does not want to say just that Christianity is wrong but wants to reinterpret it. While original Christianity teaches that salvation consists in the forgiveness of sin (Col. 1:14) and leads to a desirable life after death, Johnston says that salvation is the grace of finding a way to live that keeps faith with the importance of goodness and love even in the face of 7

everything that can happen to you (180). Our original sin consists in self-will combined with the aspiration to possess the knowledge of how to live (168). Eve s mistake was her hope that knowledge about how to live could be possessed by human beings. Although Christ did not really rise from the dead, Christ was resurrected in the sense that those who are truly good win a collective victory over death (186). Evaluation Let me indicate three areas where Johnston s book invites objections. First, Johnston s rejection of supernaturalism is defended only by affirmation, not by argument. Johnston wants to reject supernaturalism not by discussing the usual arguments for the existence of God but by taking the shortcut of claiming that interventions are impossible or incompatible with science. He just relies on calling an intervention a violation of the laws of nature and then assumes that science has shown that there are and cannot be interventions. This approach has been thoroughly criticised again and again ever since David Hume made it popular, for example by George Campbell (1762) and recently by Robert Larmer (1988) and by John Earman s book with the telling title Hume s Abject Failure: The Argument against Miracles (2000). It is certainly not obvious that miracles are ruled out by the laws of nature or by science. Suppose that God moved a stone from position A to position B. Even if we assume that the deterministic Newtonian laws of motion are the ultimate ones, this does not contradict these laws. They say what forces there are acting on the stone. In particular, the law of gravity says that there is a certain force between the stone and the ground. Is that law violated if God moves the stone from A to B? It would be violated if God thereby abolished the force, but there is no reason to assume this. Which law then would be violated? Johnston should 8

tell us. He has given no reason for rejecting supernaturalism and hence no reason for preferring panentheism to theism. So Johnston calls supernaturalism childish and naive, although he gives no arguments against it and does not discuss even a single text from the enormous contemporary literature defending the coherence of theism. Secondly, Johnston needs for his defense of panentheism the thesis that speaking about God is analogical. Without this, he should simply say There is no God. Discussing the doctrine of analogy he mentions Thomas Aquinas. Aquinas reason for saying that predications about God are analogical is this: To say of a man that he is just is to say that being just is amongst his properties. By contrast, being just is not amongst the properties of God but, according to Aquinas doctrine of simplicity, God is identical with his being just, as well as with his being omnipotent, etc. Therefore Aquinas says that speaking about God is very different from speaking about a man. Johnston has no reason like this for saying that speaking about God is analogical. He only says that this thesis discourages the hope for a Cosmic Intervener. (158) But not every view can be expressed analogically or metaphorically with the words There is a God. It is wrong simply to take one s view about ultimate things and say that it is the analogical meaning of There is a God. Whether a sentence has an analogical or metaphorical meaning and what this might be is not something the speaker can decide, but it is determined by the context. Johnston does not show that God actually has the meaning which he wishes it to have. And who means by God something remotely similar to what Johnston means by it? Nobody except a few theologians. It is therefore wrong to express Johnson s view by saying There is a God. Doing so is at best poetical and at worst just confusing. Thirdly, Johnston s panentheism seems to be incoherent or meaningless. Johnston calls God almighty (49), but also excludes the possibility that God can intervene in the course of events. That seems incoherent because being almighty entails being able to in- 9

tervene. Further, Johnston writes that God reveals himself, but also says that God does not do anything for us (20). Further, Johnston s description of God as the outpouring of Being by way of its exemplification in ordinary existents for the sake of the selfdisclosure of Being (158) and of God s mind as the totality of fully adequate modes of presentation (156) seems to be incompatible with his claim that God is a person who has love, will, mind, and power (158). Further, Johnston s thesis that God is partly constituted by the natural realm (117) is incompatible with his thesis that there is no separate creation, because the latter, as Johnston seems to understand it, implies that neither God nor a part of God is distinct from nature. Johnston s reply is that all speaking about God is analogical. But has he succeed in giving meaning to sentences about God which is clear and coherent? Is there a possible belief that one could express by saying that there is the outpouring of Being by way of its exemplification in ordinary existents for the sake of the self-disclosure of Being (158)? If not, then Johnston s description of what he wants to call God or the Highest One is meaningless. The belief which comes closest to what Johnston is getting at can be expressed clearly by saying There is no God, but Johnston does not want to say that. I cannot say that this is a book that deserves our attention. It is a rant against supernaturalism and Christianity, puts forward a meaningless view, and gives no reasons for preferring this view to either theism or atheism. References Bultmann, Rudolf (1961). New Testament and Mythology. In: Kerygma and Myth. New York: Harper & Row. URL (cit. on p. 3). Campbell, George (1762). A Dissertation on Miracles. Edinburgh: Kincaid & Bell. URL (cit. on p. 8). Earman, John (2000). Hume s Abject Failure: The Argument against Miracles. Oxford UP (cit. on p. 8). 10

Johnston, Mark (2009). Saving God. Religion after Idolatry. Princeton University Press. Larmer, Robert A. (1988). Water into Wine? An Investigation of the Concept of a Miracle. McGill-Queen s University Press (cit. on p. 8). Schleiermacher, Friedrich (1799). Über die Religion: Reden an die Gebildeten unter ihren Verächtern. Göttingen: Vandenkoeck & Ruprecht. URL (cit. on p. 5). 11