The thought of St. Thomas Aquinas continues to exercise and fascinate. Aquinas Medalist s Address. Anthony Kenny

Similar documents
A PREFACE. Gerald A. McCool, S.J.

What We Are: Our Metaphysical Nature & Moral Implications

The Darkness and the Light: Aquinas in Conversation

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Monday 4:15 6:00; Wednesday 1-3; Thursday 2-3

REVIEW. St. Thomas Aquinas. By RALPH MCINERNY. The University of Notre Dame Press 1982 (reprint of Twayne Publishers 1977). Pp $5.95.

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Tuesday 1-3, Wednesday 1-3, and by appointment

PH 4011: Twentieth-Century Thomism Dominican School of Philosophy and Theology

by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB

Discussion of McCool, From Unity to Pluralism

Development of Thought. The word "philosophy" comes from the Ancient Greek philosophia, which

general development of both renaissance and post renaissance philosophy up till today. It would

Aquinas & Homosexuality. Five Dominicans Respond to Adriano Oliva

Wednesday, April 20, 16. Introduction to Philosophy

Wisdom in Aristotle and Aquinas From Metaphysics to Mysticism Edmond Eh University of Saint Joseph, Macau

On the Relation of Philosophy to the Theology Conference Seward 11/24/98

William Hasker s discussion of the Thomistic doctrine of the soul

Building Systematic Theology

PHILOSOPHY. Chair: Karánn Durland (Fall 2018) and Mark Hébert (Spring 2019) Emeritus: Roderick Stewart

ST. THOMAS AQUINAS ( ) AND HIS TEACHINGS TODAY DATE: MARCH 17 TH 2018 ROSA, SEUNG HEE KANG MYSTERIALUCIS CHAPTER

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Undergraduate Calendar Content

PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY

Analytical Thomism: Traditions in Dialogue

Phil 104: Introduction to Philosophy

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

Contemporary Philosophy of Religion

Chapter Summaries: Introduction to Christian Philosophy by Clark, Chapter 1

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God

A Review of Norm Geisler's Prolegomena

Honors Ethics Oral Presentations: Instructions

Ancient & Medieval Virtue Ethics

Philosophy Courses-1

McKenzie Study Center, an Institute of Gutenberg College. Handout 5 The Bible and the History of Ideas Teacher: John A. Jack Crabtree.

Introduction to Philosophy 1301

A Very Short Primer on St. Thomas Aquinas Account of the Various Virtues

Teachur Philosophy Degree 2018

! Jumping ahead 2000 years:! Consider the theory of the self.! What am I? What certain knowledge do I have?! Key figure: René Descartes.

Philosophy Courses-1

Introduction to Philosophy: The Big Picture

Introduction to Analytical Thomism

Course Coordinator Dr Melvin Chen Course Code. CY0002 Course Title. Ethics Pre-requisites. NIL No of AUs 3 Contact Hours

Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 1

The Existence of God

Course Text. Course Description. Course Objectives. StraighterLine Introduction to Philosophy

PHILOSOPHY 111: HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY EARLY MODERN Winter 2012

Qué es la filosofía? What is philosophy? Philosophy

QUESTION 44. The Procession of Creatures from God, and the First Cause of All Beings

c:=} up over the question of a "Christian philosophy." Since it

Philosophy 102 Ethics Course Description: Course Requirements and Expectations

CS305 Topic Introduction to Ethics

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya

UNDERGRADUATE STUDIES CERTIFICATE IN PHILOSOPHY (CERTIFICATES)

Philosophy. The unexamined life is not worth living. Plato. O More College of Design Mission Statement

Worship. A Thomistic Perspective on. Francisco J. Romero Carrasquillo, PhD

narrow segment of life with a short-lived feeling ( I m happy with my latest pay raise ). One

Introduction to Ethics

Curriculum Vitae Contact Harvard University Department of Philosophy 25 Quincy Street Cambridge, MA

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true.

IDOLATRY AND RELIGIOUS LANGUAGE

Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics

BAYLOR UNIVERSITY. Appointment of first holder of J. Newton Rayzor Sr. Distinguished Chair in Philosophy

CURRICULUM VITAE. Date and place of birth: 27th December 1945, Liverpool, England

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

In the Collège de France there is a lecture room whose seats. descend in rows to a desk on which a podium is flanked by two green

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

Descartes: A Guide for the Perplexed

PHIL 1313 Introduction to Philosophy Section 09 Fall 2014 Philosophy Department

The Challenge of God. Julia Grubich

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

AKC Lecture 1 Plato, Penrose, Popper

Theme 1: Ethical Thought, AS. divine command as an objective metaphysical foundation for morality.

INTRODUCTION. Human knowledge has been classified into different disciplines. Each

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

PHIL1010: PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS FORDHAM UNIVERSITY PROFESSOR ROBIN MULLER M/TH: 8:30 9:45AM OFFICE HOURS: BY APPOINTMENT

Self-Evidence in Finnis Natural Law Theory: A Reply to Sayers

Practical Wisdom and Politics

INTRODUCTION TO A TRANSCENDENTAL CRITICISM OF PHILOSOPHIC THOUGHT 1

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

(P420-1) Practical Reason in Ancient Greek and Contemporary Philosophy. Spring 2018

PHILOSOPHY (PHIL) Philosophy (PHIL) 1. PHIL 56. Research Integrity. 1 Unit

GREAT PHILOSOPHERS: Thomas Reid ( ) Peter West 25/09/18

FAITH & reason. The Pope and Evolution Anthony Andres. Winter 2001 Vol. XXVI, No. 4

Thursday, November 30, 17. Hegel s Idealism

Introduction to Ethics

A Major Matter: Minoring in Philosophy. Southeastern Louisiana University. The unexamined life is not worth living. Socrates, B.C.E.

The Five Ways THOMAS AQUINAS ( ) Thomas Aquinas: The five Ways

Process Thought and Bridge Building: A Response to Stephen K. White. Kevin Schilbrack

Tuesday, November 11, Hegel s Idealism

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo

TO D D C. REAM. VER THE COURSE OF THE PAST FIFTEEN YEARS, intellectual historians have

Ibuanyidanda (Complementary Reflection), African Philosophy and General Issues in Philosophy

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Lecture 12 Deontology. Onora O Neill A Simplified Account of Kant s Ethics

COURSE OUTLINE. Philosophy 116 (C-ID Number: PHIL 120) Ethics for Modern Life (Title: Introduction to Ethics)

Honours Programme in Philosophy

Epistemology and sensation

Department of Philosophy

Transcription:

Aquinas Medalist s Address Anthony Kenny Abstract: The author begins by observing that he has often been described as an analytical Thomist. He proceeds to argue that regardless of what school one belongs to genuine philosophical engagement with Aquinas s texts means one should be both reverent and critical. If we are to consider the relevance of Aquinas s thought for contemporary philosophy, the author suggests, the best way for us to write about Aquinas is the way in which he wrote about Aristotle: stating his views as clearly and sympathetically as possible, showing their connection with current concerns, and contesting them politely but firmly if they appear to be erroneous. The thought of St. Thomas Aquinas continues to exercise and fascinate the minds of many. After the Second Vatican Council Thomism lost the commanding position that it had for nearly a century occupied in the training of Catholic clergy; but in compensation many philosophers outside the Roman fold took up the serious study of the Summa Theologiae and the Summa contra Gentiles. The seminary manuals had, in any case, functioned at some distance from Thomas actual writings, and the disrepute that has overtaken manual Thomism has in the long run served the Saint s reputation well. In the English speaking world it is possible to distinguish four different schools among contemporary admirers of Aquinas. First, there are the conservatives who continue to work in the neo-scholastic tradition of Gilson and Maritain, albeit in a chastened and less triumphalist form. A doughty exponent of this school of thought is Ralph McInerny, who has sought to make Thomism accessible in many works, and whose recent Gifford lectures presented a popular defence of traditional natural theology in its relation to theoretical and practical reasoning. Second, there are the transcendental Thomists who combine close and sympathetic appreciation of the writings of St. Thomas with a respect for the importance of the critical insights of Immanuel Kant. Prominent leaders of this line of thought were the Jesuits Joseph Marechal and Peter Hoenen, and at the present time the school is represented above all by followers of the late Bernard Lonergan, S.J. 2007, American Catholic Philosophical Association, Proceedings of the ACPA, Vol. 80

24 Intelligence and the Philosophy of Mind Third, there are those who follow an agenda drawn from post-modernism, among whom are the members of the theological movement that styles itself Radical Orthodoxy. John Milbank and Catherine Pickstock are vociferous proponents of this tendency, which has gained influence in the Church of England. Finally, there are several philosophers in the analytic tradition, who seek to interpret Aquinas in the light of recent currents of thought in philosophy of language and philosophy of mind. Many of these have been heavily influenced by Wittgenstein, who like Aquinas stands at the opposite pole of philosophy from the Cartesian tradition which sees epistemology as the basic philosophical discipline and private consciousness as the fundamental datum of epistemology. There is by now an impressive corpus of works of this so-called analytical Thomism. Some of the leading practitioners are Catholics, such as Peter Geach and John Finnis; some indeed, like the late Herbert McCabe, were members of St. Thomas s own Dominican Order. But there have been other influential writers of this school who like Norman Kretzmann have never been Catholics or like Alasdair MacIntyre have held varying religious allegiance. I find that I am myself from time to time described as an analytical Thomist. I am happy to be called a Thomist if that means a person who admires and studies St. Thomas. But I have never been a Thomist if a Thomist is a paid-up member of a particular philosophical party. I first met Thomism in the scholastic manuals of the Gregorian university in Rome, and took an instant and lasting dislike to it. It was Bernard Lonergan, at the end of my Roman course, and Peter Geach and Herbert McCabe in Oxford, who taught me to distinguish between Thomas and Thomism. There are some Thomists who so swear by the words of the Saint that they resent any criticism of him and will not accept any contradiction of him (unless it comes from a Pope, as when Pius IX defined the immaculate conception). Such an entrenched position is sometimes called citadel Thomism. I believe that it represents a misunderstanding of the nature of philosophy. The student of philosophy is not called on to subscribe to one or other philosophical ism, but rather, in the light of the varied teachings of the great philosophers of the past, to make up her own mind on each philosophical issue that presents itself. Philosophy is such a difficult subject that to achieve a consistent overall philosophical Weltanschaung has proved beyond the reach of even the greatest geniuses such as Plato, Aristotle, Descartes and Kant. A fortiori, we lesser mortals cannot help but be eclectic. I regard Aquinas as ranking, as a philosopher, with the greatest geniuses of the discipline, but I think that our engagement with him, as with them, must be critical as well as reverent. In a number of books I have tried to present his thought in a manner that shows its relevance to the issues that occupy philosophers working in the contemporary analytic tradition. There are those who argue that the conceptual world of the thirteenth century was so different from that of the twentieth century that any attempt at such bridge-building is bound to fail. I disagree: I think that philosophy is perennial in the sense that many of the conceptual problems that we confront today are the very same problems as those that faced Plato and Aristotle.

Medalist s Address 25 Other issues are as it were the descendants of the ancient issues, and can best be understood by tracing their provenance. Aquinas s thought, I believe, is just as relevant to the twenty-first century as Aristotle s thought was to the thirteenth century. And the best way for us to write about Aquinas is the way in which he wrote about Aristotle: stating his views as clearly and sympathetically as possible, showing their connection with current concerns, and contesting them politely but firmly if they appear to be erroneous. Of course much that was written by ancient and medieval philosophers has been superannuated by the progress of science, but there remains a substantial corpus that is as relevant today as ever. Those of us who call ourselves philosophers today can genuinely lay claim to be the heirs of Plato and Aristotle. But we are only a small subset of their heirs. What distinguishes us from the other heirs of the great Greeks, and what entitles us to inherit their name, is that unlike the physicists, the astronomers, the medics, the linguists, we philosophers pursue the goals of Plato and Aristotle only by the same methods as were already available to them. Aquinas stands in a similar relation to today s philosophers. His philosophy of nature has been antiquated, in great part, by the swift progress of natural science since the Renaissance. His philosophy of logic and language has been enormously improved on by the work of logicians and mathematicians in recent centuries. But his writings on metaphysics, philosophical theology, philosophy of mind, and ethics are still as rewarding to read as anything written on those topics by philosophers between his age and ours. Much writing on ethics in contemporary Anglophone philosophy draws its ultimate inspiration from Jeremy Bentham. On the one hand it is consequentialist: no form of action is absolutely ruled out as immoral, for a sufficiently imposing end may justify the most abhorrent of means. On the other hand it is sensationalist: the ultimate criteria of right and wrong are pain and pleasure, conceived as private experiences. It follows that animals belong to the same moral community as humans, because they like us can feel pain and pleasure. Fetuses, however, do not, since they are incapable of feeling either. Aquinas s ethics stands in splendid contrast to this noxious utilitarianism. While the calculation of consequences has its place in his system, this is within a framework which rules out certain actions as absolutely forbidden. It is rationality, not sensation, that is the mark of human beings, so that animals form no part of our moral community. A creature s potentialities, no less than its experiences, are relevant to the evaluation of its moral worth, and they should be our guide in deciding how to treat a fetus. Only Aquinas s fellow Christians can endorse the whole of Aquinas s ethical system, with its emphasis on theological as well as moral virtues. But his treatment of the moral virtues, and his analysis of human actions and intentions, commends itself to secular as well as to religious readers. This is unsurprising, since much of the ethical parts of the Summa Theologiae read like a commentary on the Nicomachean Ethics of the pagan Aristotle.

26 Intelligence and the Philosophy of Mind The first book that I wrote on Aquinas, The Five Ways (1969), was a discussion of the proofs of God s existence to be found at the beginning of the Summa Theologiae. I concluded that none of them achieved its object. I continue to believe this, but I now think that it might have been better to concentrate my attention on the Summa contra Gentiles as Norman Kretzmann later did in his magisterial The Metaphysics of Theism. Later I was invited to write a brief introduction to Aquinas in the Oxford series Past Masters (1969). The book contained three chapters, the first a summary of the Saint s life and works, the second devoted to Being and the third to Mind. I argued that St. Thomas s philosophical psychology was equal to anything currently on the philosophical market, but I took a critical view of the real distinction between essence and existence and the thesis that God was self-subsistent being. Later I expanded each of these judgements in full-length books. In Aquinas on Mind (1993), I spelt out that for Aquinas the intellect is the capacity for thought, for the particular kind of thought peculiar to language-users. The agent intellect, or concept-forming ability is species-specific in humans; the receptive intellect is the set of concepts and beliefs possessed by an individual. Aquinas s account places him between empiricists who regard ideas as arising simply from experience, and rationalists who postulate innate ideas. He also stands in the middle between realists and idealists. He agrees with the realists that the human mind is capable of genuine knowledge of an extra-mental world. But he agrees with the idealists that the universals that the mind uses to conceptualise experience have no existence, as universals, outside the mind. His map of the mind is a complicated one but it is superior to that offered by many another famous philosopher. My attitude to Aquinas s metaphysics is an ambiguous one. There run through his works two grand Aristotelian principles. The first is that there is no actualisation without individuation; the second is that there is no individuation without actualisation. The first principle is anti-platonic; the second, anachronistically, we can call anti-leibnizian. These principles seem to me to be fundamental to any sound ontology, and they are key elements of Aquinas s philosophy of creation. But if Aquinas is an Aristotelian on earth, he is a Platonist in heaven. I argued in Aquinas on Being (2002) that the idea of God as pure Being is vulnerable to all the arguments that can be brought against Plato s theory of Ideas, and that the distinction between essence and existence embodies a deep philosophical confusion between different senses of the verb to be. That book, not unnaturally, attracted a hail of criticism from citadel Thomists. It is, therefore, highly magnanimous of the American Catholic Philosophical Association to award me the Aquinas medal. I value it highly not only because my admiration of Aquinas s gigantic achievement far outweighs my criticism of aspects of his apparatus, but also because it is an honour to be enrolled in the same company as those distinguished scholars and philosophers who have won the medal in the past. I am most grateful to you all and offer you my warmest thanks. I must end, however, on a note of caution. You will remember that shortly after his death a number of Aquinas s teachings incurred academic and ecclesiastical

Medalist s Address 27 sanction. On March 7, 1277, they were condemned by Bishop Tempier in Paris and ten days later by a special congregation of the university of Oxford. The Oxford condemnation specified that those who taught the Thomist theses were to be allowed forty days to recant, and if they continued to uphold them they were to be deprived of their degrees. The Paris condemnation was revoked two years after the Saint s canonization. The Oxford one, so far as I know, has never been withdrawn. So when I get back to Oxford I had better not boast of having received the Aquinas medal, for fear of losing my M.A. University of Oxford