Similar documents

Philosophical Review.



David O Connor. Hume on Religion H. O. Mounce Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 2 (November, 2002)

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT David Hume: The Origin of Our Ideas and Skepticism about Causal Reasoning

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first.

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Sometimes doing what is Right has No Right Answer: On Hilary Putnam s Pragmatism with Existential Choices

Logic, Truth & Epistemology. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.


Naturalism and is Opponents

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View


World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Epistemology. Theory of Knowledge

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

Bart Streumer, Unbelievable Errors, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ISBN


Commentary on Professor Tweyman's 'Hume on Evil' Pheroze S. Wadia Hume Studies Volume XIII, Number 1 (April, 1987)

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 8

University of International Business and Economics International Summer Sessions. PHI 110: Introduction to Philosophy

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Evidence and Transcendence

History of Modern Philosophy. Hume ( )

Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics

Cartesian Rationalism

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses. David Hume

R. M. Hare (1919 ) SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG. Definition of moral judgments. Prescriptivism

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 3

Kevin Scharp, Replacing Truth, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013, At 300-some pages, with narrow margins and small print, the work

1. What is Philosophy?

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

A Problem for the Kantian-style Critique of the Traditional Metaphysics By Eugen Zelenak

5: Preliminaries to the Argument

Some Notes Toward a Genealogy of Existential Philosophy Robert Burch

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

Bigelow, Possible Worlds and The Passage of Time

Kant and his Successors

Process Thought and Bridge Building: A Response to Stephen K. White. Kevin Schilbrack

Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism


Consciousness might be defined as the perceiver of mental phenomena. We might say that there are no differences between one perceiver and another, as

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

PHIL 480: Seminar in the History of Philosophy Building Moral Character: Neo-Confucianism and Moral Psychology

An Early Account of David Hume. Hume Studies Volume 1, Issue 2 (November, 1975), J.C. Hilson

Skepticism is True. Abraham Meidan

Epistemological Externalism and the Project of Traditional Epistemology. Contemporary philosophers still haven't come to terms with the project of

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

COURSE GOALS: PROFESSOR: Chris Latiolais Philosophy Department Kalamazoo College Humphrey House #202 Telephone # Offices Hours:

First Principles. Principles of Reality. Undeniability.

A History of Western Thought Why We Think the Way We Do. Summer 2016 Ross Arnold

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Comments on Leibniz and Pantheism by Robert Adams for The Twelfth Annual NYU Conference on Issues in Modern Philosophy: God

Truth and Realism. EDITED BY PATRICK GREENOUGH AND MICHAEL P. LYNCH. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. ix Price h/b, p/b.

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

Student Outcome Statement

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Is Innate Foreknowledge Possible to a Temporal God?

PH 1000 Introduction to Philosophy, or PH 1001 Practical Reasoning

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

EXAM PREP (Semester 2: 2018) Jules Khomo. Linguistic analysis is concerned with the following question:

Aristotle on Non-Contradiction

Mistaking Category Mistakes: A Response to Gilbert Ryle. Evan E. May

PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0

Klein on the Unity of Cartesian and Contemporary Skepticism

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Cartesian Rationalism

PHIL 3140: Epistemology

BENJAMIN R. BARBER. Radical Excess & Post-Modernism Presentation By Benedetta Barnabo Cachola

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Gary Ebbs, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry, Cambridge. University Press, 2017, 278pp., $99.99 (hbk), ISBN

Nagel, Naturalism and Theism. Todd Moody. (Saint Joseph s University, Philadelphia)

Qué es la filosofía? What is philosophy? Philosophy

NOTE: Courses, rooms, times and instructors are subject to change; please see Timetable of Classes on HokieSpa for current information

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

Templates for Writing about Ideas and Research

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

GOD'S SILENCE IN THE DIALOGUE ACCORDING TO MARTIN BUBER

CHAPTER ONE What is Philosophy? What s In It For Me?

Should We Assess the Basic Premises of an Argument for Truth or Acceptability?

PHIL 100 AO1 Introduction to Philosophy

Philosophy 125 Day 4: Overview

DR. LEONARD PEIKOFF. Lecture 3 THE METAPHYSICS OF TWO WORLDS: ITS RESULTS IN THIS WORLD

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

ZAGZEBSKI ON RATIONALITY

THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S

Philosophy Courses-1

Transcription:

Robert J. Fogelin. Walking the Tightrope of Reason: The Precarious Life of a Rational Animal Ira Singer Volume 31, Number 1, (2005) 169-172. Your use of the HUME STUDIES archive indicates your acceptance of HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.humesociety.org/hs/about/terms.html. HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the HUME STUDIES archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Each copy of any part of a HUME STUDIES transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. For more information on HUME STUDIES contact humestudies-info@humesociety.org http://www.humesociety.org/hs/

Volume 31, Number 1, April 2005, pp. 169 172 ROBERT J. FOGELIN. Walking the Tightrope of Reason: The Precarious Life of a Rational Animal. New York: Oxford University Press, 2003. Pp. xii + 203. ISBN 0-19-516026-6, cloth, $22.00; ISBN 0-19-517754-1, paper, $13.95. This lively little book 170 small-format pages, excluding front and end matter has its origin in the author s 1995 Romanell-Phi Beta Kappa lectures at Dartmouth College. Consistent with this origin, it speaks primarily to a general audience rather than to philosophical specialists (as Fogelin says in his Preface). Nevertheless, even specialist readers will find Walking the Tightrope of Reason valuable. It revisits figures (Sextus, Hume, Kant, Wittgenstein) and issues (skepticism s depth and uses, reason s infirmities and indispensability) that have long and productively occupied Fogelin, and here we see his thoughts about these figures and issues clearly and whole. The book consists of an Introduction and seven nicely unified chapters. In the Introduction Fogelin claims that reason, left to its own devices, moves between the unsatisfactory poles of (1) rationalist metaphysics and (2) skepticism or relativism. On issue after issue, thinkers at these opposed extremes subscribe to some common underlying disjunctive principle: for instance, either God exists or everything is permitted, either texts have fixed meanings or they are meaningless, either something is certain or nothing is even probable. Fogelin willingly concedes that such choices can seem deep and unavoidable, and that in many cases we may never entirely free ourselves from the sense that we must make such radical choices. But to the extent that we can free ourselves, Fogelin proposes, we will do so by constraining reason to work within the ordinary, workaday world (5). This view of reason s usefulness within limits, and self-destructiveness beyond those limits, Fogelin later labels circumspect rationalism (70); sketching this view and its appeal is the book s goal. Chapter One, Why Obey the Laws of Logic? explores the law of non-contradiction. Fogelin labels traditional defenders of this logical law Parmenideans (partisans of stability and unity), and labels radical opponents of this law Heracliteans (partisans of dynamism and diversity). Heraclitean remarks include Emerson s jibe at foolish consistency and Whitman s claim that, since he contains multitudes, he can blithely contradict himself. Nietzsche and many postmodernists are examples of more thoroughgoing Heracliteans. Fogelin, inspired here by Wittgenstein, argues that Parmenideans and Heracliteans share a mistaken assumption: that the law of non-contradiction is an ontological constraint, ruling out real change. Instead the law is a constraint on language, a tautology. In one way, this first chapter exemplifies Fogelin s general method: uncovering the

170 BOOK REVIEWS shared assumption behind two opposed philosophical extremes. In another way, though, the chapter is atypical, since it is straightforwardly deflationary (abandon the assumption, and the problem vanishes), while Fogelin usually emphasizes that philosophical problems about human reason are deep and durable. Perhaps Chapter One is atypical in this way because, while Fogelin doesn t exactly take sides in the dispute between Heracliteans and Parmenideans, still his main point is that denying the law of non-contradiction is a foolish error (41). (In general, where postmodernism is concerned, Fogelin pulls no punches and spares no ridicule.) In Chapter Two, Dilemmas and Paradoxes, Fogelin argues, again following Wittgenstein, that our lives are governed by systems of rules that are inconsistent, at the margins anyway; and that we should learn to live with inconsistency in... a discriminating and civilized manner (42) rather than becoming obsessed with eliminating inconsistency at all costs, or allowing ineliminable inconsistency to stymie us. His first example of an inconsistent system of rules is an imagined game he dubs Ludwig, where unskillful play can lead to a dilemma: two rules, you must move here and you mustn t move here, come into conflict. (Incidentally, in light of this description it is mildly surprising that Fogelin doesn t consider the real example of stalemate in chess: a situation in which a player is both required to move and unable to move. In fact the rules of chess are structured such that this paradox yields a clear result, namely, a draw.) If we cannot make the rules of Ludwig consistent, or can only make them consistent by decreasing the game s interest, and if Ludwig is dilemma-prone only at the margins, then the sensible course is indeed to live with the inconsistency. Fogelin goes on to discuss weightier examples, including these: (1) Liar s paradoxes reveal that language is dilemmaprone, yet we go on speaking even without an agreed-on resolution or dissolution of such paradoxes, and perhaps should count them as the price we pay for the richness of language. (2) Moral dilemmas reveal the richness and complexity of our moral lives. In these domains and others, Fogelin argues, we should admit but not exaggerate reason s limits; while perfect consistency is a fond rationalist hope, practical engagement does usually keep us clear of the regions of paradox (65). Chapter Three, Pure Reason and Its Illusions, examines extreme conceptual relativism or perspectivism, according to which there are indefinitely many mutually incompatible ways of seeing the world, all of them equally good or bad. (Not to be missed here is a characteristically funny anecdote about a distinguished French physicist. ) Kant is the focus of this chapter in two ways: First, Kant s claim that the mind structures experience is the seed for the extreme perspectivist claim. Fogelin presents this brief philosophical genealogy as a matter of a good idea run riot and gone bad. For Kant s conservative relativizing of experience to one set of concepts allows for mutual intelligibility and collaborative, progressive inquiry, whereas radical relativism, foreshadowed by Protagoras and exemplified by Nietzsche and certain postmodernists, allows for no such constructive possibilities. Second, Kant s

BOOK REVIEWS 171 exposition of dialectical illusions captures reason s tendency, when freed from the constraint of structuring experience and set to the task of explaining reality as it is in itself, to degenerate into absolute absolutism or absolute relativism (90). A crucial point here is that radical relativism derives its appeal from the mistaken belief that absolutism is the only available alternative. Chapter Four, Skepticism, canvasses three skeptical arguments: cartesian skepticism about the external world, Humean skepticism about induction, and Pyrrhonian skepticism about dogmatic philosophy. A summary of Fogelin s detailed account would require much space; therefore, I will note only two main points. (1) Fogelin is unpersuaded by claims that, because skeptical arguments propose remote or ineliminable grounds for doubt, they are nonsensical. Instead skeptical arguments strike him as unanswerable, once they arise. (2) But when and why do skeptical arguments arise? Fogelin claims that they arise whenever we philosophize. Whenever we think about our beliefs and commitments as carefully and thoroughly as we can, we naturally ascend to the highest possible level of scrutiny. So skepticism arises not because skeptics philosophize badly, but rather because they philosophize well, conscientiously, unrestrictedly; therefore the remedy for skepticism will not likely be found in more philosophy. Chapter Five, Modest Responses to These Challenges, and Chapter Six, Matters of Taste, develop Fogelin s skeptical solution to reason s difficulties. The non-conceptual must constrain the conceptual, or more plainly we must concretely engage with the world, to save reason from itself and have it serve us well. Causal wisdom should be our aim, most of the time; and causal wisdom requires immersion in the causal business of living. Chapter Five develops this idea by exploring Hume s efforts to mitigate skepticism, and by reflecting on natural science and its successes; Chapter Six develops the idea by exploring aesthetic value (taken as representative of the objects that the humanities study), with Fogelin giving a brief, perceptive, and highly appreciative reading of Hume s essay Of the Standard of Taste. In Chapter Seven, Last Words, Fogelin counsels us to embrace some degree of irremediable dissatisfaction with our faculties and their products as the only viable alternative to dialectical illusion or abject skepticism (170). This might seem to be the counsel of despair; yet, almost in the same breath, he urges us to recognize the fun to be had by those who engage with the world in a critical and self-critical way, a sort of fun that is twinned with dissatisfaction. The power to revel in irremediable dissatisfaction is perhaps partly a function of the author s own disposition, but it is also partly a function of this particular dissatisfaction s source and nature. It is not passive and finished dissatisfaction, an effect of giving up on knowing about anything extra-mental; it is active and progressive dissatisfaction, an effect of continuing (and playful) engagement with the extra-mental. Characteristically, in the end Fogelin refuses either to declare victory over skepticism or to surrender to it. In walking this tightrope rather than falling to the side Volume 31, Number 1, April 2005

172 BOOK REVIEWS of skepticism defeated or to the side of skepticism triumphant, Fogelin avowedly follows Hume. Not that he follows Hume uncritically; for Fogelin argues (1) that Hume concedes too much to skepticism when he declares that we shall never know why bread nourishes, and (2) that Hume concedes too little to skepticism when he declares that, having once passed through the skeptical inferno, we can achieve a stable intellectual ease forever after. On the latter point, Fogelin expresses his preference for Kant and Wittgenstein, interpreting them as saying that our intellectual lives must always be in some measure precarious. Still, in balancing skeptical and anti-skeptical arguments, in claiming that only practical engagement saves us from total skepticism, and in insisting on the pleasure of philosophizing even when philosophy reveals disappointing truths to us, Fogelin is decidedly Hume-inspired. Though Fogelin, in a nod to the Pyrrhonian tradition, declares in the Preface that he aims only to report how things strike me (ix), he surely hopes that many of his readers will find their points of view tending to coincide with his own. Therefore this book does have large ambitions, and a correspondingly large set of argumentative (or at least persuasive) tasks, which it can only accomplish in a preliminary way. Most importantly, even those persuaded by Fogelin that reason s situation is precarious might not be persuaded that circumspect rationalism, as he sketches it, is a sufficiently coherent and defensible position; and even those persuaded that Fogelin s sketch of circumspect rationalism is a good start will have questions that can only be addressed by the detailed development of the view. For instance, does Fogelin want to say that circumspect rationalism is not itself a well-justified philosophical position, but is simply the fact that conceptualizing must be constrained by the extra-conceptual in order to avoid destroying itself? Or does he, on the contrary, want to say that circumspect rationalism is a kind of causal wisdom, a reflective understanding of how practical engagement enables us to avoid skepticism legitimately, and so is a philosophical position of an especially reflective and appropriately humble kind? Perhaps here Fogelin again follows Hume, in leaving an appealing idea for a skeptical solution or mitigated skepticism in need of further development. Anyone interested in Hume s epistemology, in epistemology in general, or in critical reflection on philosophy s methods and ambitions, will want to read this delightful book. Moreover, the book is accessible enough that it might be a useful supplementary text for an upper-level course in epistemology, especially one that aims to illuminate the contemporary scene by engaging with historical figures. IRA SINGER Department of Philosophy Hofstra University Hempstead, NY 11549, USA ira.j.singer@hofstra.edu