Meditations on Knowledge, Truth, and Ideas

Similar documents
Freedom and Possibility

First Truths. G. W. Leibniz

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

WHAT IS HUME S FORK? Certainty does not exist in science.

Cartesian Rationalism

Cartesian Rationalism

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

1/8. Descartes 3: Proofs of the Existence of God

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

Hume on Ideas, Impressions, and Knowledge

The Correspondence between Leibniz and Arnauld

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2010

1/10. Descartes and Spinoza on the Laws of Nature

Class #5-6: Modern Rationalism Sample Introductory Material from Marcus and McEvoy, An Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Mathematics

Reading Questions for Phil , Fall 2013 (Daniel)

Fourth Meditation: Truth and falsity

John Locke. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding

P. Weingartner, God s existence. Can it be proven? A logical commentary on the five ways of Thomas Aquinas, Ontos, Frankfurt Pp. 116.

Real-Life Dialogue on Human Freedom and the Origin of Evil

2017 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

Necessary and Contingent Truths [c. 1686)

Why There s Nothing You Can Say to Change My Mind: The Principle of Non-Contradiction in Aristotle s Metaphysics

Objections to Descartes s Meditations, and his Replies

10 CERTAINTY G.E. MOORE: SELECTED WRITINGS

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres

Meditations on First Philosophy in which are demonstrated the existence of God and the distinction between the human soul and body

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

The British Empiricism

Objections to the Meditations and Descartes s Replies

THE LEIBNIZ CLARKE DEBATES

Principles of Philosophy

Descartes, Leibniz, Spinoza: Concept of Substance Chapter 3 Spinoza and Substance. (Woolhouse)

Class 11 - February 23 Leibniz, Monadology and Discourse on Metaphysics

First Treatise <Chapter 1. On the Eternity of Things>

Class #3 - Illusion Descartes, from Meditations on First Philosophy Descartes, The Story of the Wax Descartes, The Story of the Sun

The Principles of Human Knowledge

Meditations on First Philosophy in which are demonstrated the existence of God and the distinction between the human soul and body

The CopernicanRevolution

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

Spinoza, Ethics 1 of 85 THE ETHICS. by Benedict de Spinoza (Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata) Translated from the Latin by R. H. M.

GOD AND THE PRINCIPLE OF SUFFICIENT REASON

Treatise of Human Nature, Book 1

Aristotle on the Principle of Contradiction :

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2015

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

Objections to the Meditations and Descartes s Replies

Avicenna, Proof of the Necessary of Existence

The Ultimate Origin of Things

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Do we have knowledge of the external world?

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

An Essay Concerning Human Understanding 1 by John Locke

DEGREES OF CERTAINTY AND SENSITIVE KNOWLEDGE: A REPLY TO SOLES. Samuel C. Rickless. [Penultimate version of a paper published in Locke Studies (2015)]

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

Freedom of the Will. Jonathan Edwards

Aquinas, The Divine Nature

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

DESCARTES ON THE OBJECTIVE REALITY OF MATERIALLY FALSE IDEAS

(1) A phrase may be denoting, and yet not denote anything; e.g., 'the present King of France'.

John Locke Innate ideas and innate knowledge

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

The Unmoved Mover (Metaphysics )

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

William Ockham on Universals

Freedom of the Will. Jonathan Edwards

Critique of Cosmological Argument

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

John Locke No innate ideas or innate knowledge

1/10. Descartes Laws of Nature

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

Descartes and Foundationalism

Objections to the Meditations and Descartes s Replies

New Chapter: Epistemology: The Theory and Nature of Knowledge

Since Michael so neatly summarized his objections in the form of three questions, all I need to do now is to answer these questions.

The Names of God. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 12-13) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006)

From the fact that I cannot think of God except as existing, it follows that existence is inseparable from God, and hence that he really exists.

Judgment. Thomas Reid

David O Connor. Hume on Religion H. O. Mounce Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 2 (November, 2002)

Lecture Notes Comments on a Certain Broadsheet G. J. Mattey December 4, 2008

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

An Essay Concerning Human Understanding Book III: Words

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

The Subject Matter of Ethics G. E. Moore

BOOK REVIEWS PHILOSOPHIE DER WERTE. Grundziige einer Weltanschauung. Von Hugo Minsterberg. Leipzig: J. A. Barth, Pp. viii, 481.

1/9. Leibniz on Descartes Principles

The Divine Nature. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 3-11) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian J.

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

Must we have self-evident knowledge if we know anything?

Introduction to Philosophy

Searle vs. Chalmers Debate, 8/2005 with Death Monkey (Kevin Dolan)

Aquinas' Third Way Modalized

Transcription:

1 Copyright Jonathan Bennett [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small dots enclose material that has been added, but can be read as though it were part of the original text. Occasional bullets, and also indenting of passages that are not quotations, are meant as aids to grasping the structure of a sentence or a thought. Four ellipses.... indicate the omission of a brief passage that seems to present more difficulty than it is worth. First launched: September 2004 Meditations on Knowledge, Truth, and Ideas By G. W. Leibniz Controversies are boiling these days among distinguished men over true and false ideas. This is an issue of great importance for recognizing truth - an issue on which Descartes himself is not altogether satisfactory. So I want to explain briefly what I think can be established about the distinctions and criteria that relate to ideas and knowledge. [Here and in the title, knowledge translates cognitio, which means something weaker than knowledge strictly so-called, involving certainty and guaranteed truth, for which the Latin word is scientia]. Here is the skeleton of what I have to say. Knowledge is either dim or vivid; vivid knowledge is either confused or clear; clear knowledge is either inadequate or adequate; and adequate knowledge is either symbolic or intuitive. Knowledge that was at the same time both adequate and intuitive would be absolutely perfect. [Here and throughout, vivid translates clarus. (The more usual rendering as clear is no better from a dictionary point of view, and makes much worse sense philosophically because it has Leibniz saying that knowledge can be at once clear and confused.) This use of vivid points to dim as the better translation of the contrasting term obscurus, and liberates clear for use in translating distinctus.] A dim notion is one that isn t sufficient for recognizing the thing that it represents - i.e. the thing that it is a notion of. Example: I once saw a certain flower but whenever I remember it I can t bring it to mind well enough to recognize it, distinguishing it from other nearby flowers, when I see it again. Another kind of example: I have dim notions when I think about some term for which there is no settled definition - such as Aristotle s entelechy, or his notion of cause when offered as something that is common to material, formal, efficient and final causes. [For a coin, these causes would be, respectively, the metal of which the coin is composed, the coin s shape, weight etc., the force of the die against the hot metal, and the commercial purpose for which the coin was made. Leibniz implies that these seem not to be four species of a single genus.] And a proposition is dim if it contains a dim notion as an ingredient. Accordingly, knowledge is vivid if it gives me the means for recognizing the thing that is represented. Vivid knowledge is either confused or clear.

It is confused when I can t list, one by one, the marks that enable me to differentiate the represented thing from other things, even though the thing has such marks into which its notion can be resolved [= analysed, broken down into its simpler constituents ]. And so we recognize colours, smells, tastes, and other particular objects of the senses vividly enough to be able to distinguish them from one another, but only through the simple testimony of the senses, not by way of marks that we could list. Thus we can t explain what red is to a blind man; and we can t give anyone a vivid notion of things like red except by leading him into the presence of the thing and getting him to see, smell, or taste the same thing we do, or by reminding him of some past perception of his that is similar. This is so even though the notions of these qualities are certainly composite and can be resolved - after all, they do have causes. [Perhaps Leibniz s thought is that the complexity of the causes must be matched by the complexity of the caused quality, and thus by the complexity of the complete notion of it.] Similarly, we see that painters and other skilled craftsmen can accurately tell well-done work from what is poorly done, though often they can t explain their judgments, and when asked about them all they can say is that the works that displease them lack a certain je-ne-sais-quoi. But a clear notion is like the one an assayer has of gold - that is, a notion connected with listable marks and tests that are sufficient to distinguish the represented thing from all other similar bodies. Notions common to several senses - like the notions of number, size, and shape - are usually clear. So are many notions of states of mind, such as hope and fear. In brief, we have a clear notion of everything for which we have a nominal definition (which is nothing but a list of sufficient marks). Also, we have clear knowledge of any indefinable notion, since such a notion is basic, something we start with ; it can t be resolved into marks or simpler constituents, as it has none; so it has to serve as its own mark, and be understood through itself. An inadequate notion is what you have when the notion is clear, meaning that you understand vividly the individual marks composing it, but the grasp of some or all of those marks is (though vivid) confused, because you can t list the marks whereby you recognize those marks. For example, someone s knowledge of gold may be clear yet inadequate: he knows that heaviness, colour, solubility in aqua fortis etc. are the marks of gold, but he can t produce a list of the marks whereby he recognizes heaviness, yellowness, and all the others. When every ingredient of a clear notion is itself clearly known - that is, when the analysis of the original notion has been carried to completion - then our knowledge of it is adequate. (I don t know whether humans have any perfectly adequate knowledge, though our knowledge of numbers certainly comes close.) Symbolic notions are ones in which words stand in for thoughts. We don t usually grasp the entire nature of a thing all at once, especially one whose analysis is long; so in place of thoughts about the things themselves we use thoughts about signs. In our thought we usually omit the explicit explanation of what a sign means, knowing or believing that we have the explanation at our command and could produce it on demand. Thus, when I think about a chiliagon [pronounced kill-ee-a-gon], that is, a polygon with a thousand equal sides, I don t always think about the nature of a side, or of equality, or of thousandfoldedness....; in place of such thoughts, in my mind I use the words side, equal and thousand. 2

The meanings of these words appear only dimly and imperfectly to my mind, but I remember that I know what they mean, so I decide that I needn t explain them to myself at this time. This kind of thinking is found in algebra, in arithmetic, and indeed almost everywhere. I call it blind or symbolic thinking. When a notion is very complex, we can t bear in mind all of its component notions at the same time, and this forces us into symbolic thinking. When we can keep them all in mind at once, we have knowledge of the kind I call intuitive. ( Actually, I treat this as a matter of degree; so I should have said : insofar as we can keep all that in mind at once, to that extent our knowledge is intuitive.) Whereas our thinking about composites is mostly symbolic, our knowledge of a clear basic notion has to be intuitive. That is because symbolic knowledge involves letting words stand in for components of a notion, and basic notions don t have components. This shows that it s only if we use intuitive thinking that we have ideas in our minds, even when we are thinking about something we know clearly. We often mistakenly believe that we have ideas of things in our mind, assuming that we have already explained to ourselves some of the terms we are using, when really we haven t explained any of them. Some people hold that we can t understand what we are saying about a thing unless we have an idea of it; but this is false or at least ambiguous, because we can have understanding of a sort even when our thinking is blind or symbolic and doesn t involve ideas. When we settle for this blind thinking, and don t pursue the resolution of notions far enough, we may have a thought that harbours a contradiction that we don t see because it is buried in a very complex notion. At one time I was led to consider this point more clearly by an old argument for the existence of God.... that Descartes revived. The argument goes like this: Whatever follows from the idea or definition of a thing can be predicated of the thing. God is by definition the most perfect being, or the being nothing greater than which can be thought. Now, the idea of the most perfect being includes ideas of all perfections, and amongst these perfections is existence. So existence follows from the idea of God. Therefore existence can be predicated of God, which is to say that God exists. But this argument shows only that if God is possible then it follows that he exists. For we can t safely draw conclusions from definitions unless we know first that they are real definitions, that is, that they don t include any contradictions. If a definition does harbour a contradiction, we can infer contradictory conclusions from it, which is absurd. My favourite illustrative example of this is the fastest motion, which entails an absurdity. I now show that it does : Suppose there is a wheel turning with the fastest motion. Anyone can see that if a spoke of the wheel came to poke out beyond the rim, the end of it would then be moving faster than a nail on the rim of the wheel. So the nail s motion is not the fastest, which is contrary to the hypothesis. Now, we certainly understand the phrase the fastest motion, and we may think we have an idea corresponding to it; but we don t, because we can t have an idea of something impossible. Similarly, the fact that we think about a most perfect being doesn t entitle us to claim that we have an idea of a most perfect being. So in the above demonstration - the one revived by Descartes - in order properly to draw the conclusion we must show or assume the possibility of a most perfect being. It is indeed true - nothing truer! - that we do have an idea of God and that a most perfect being is possible, indeed, necessary. But that argument is not sufficient for drawing the conclusion, and Aquinas rejected it. 3

So we have a line to draw between nominal definitions, which contain only marks that distinguish the thing from other things, and real definitions, from which the thing can be shown to be possible. And that s my answer to Hobbes, who claimed that truths are arbitrary because they depend on nominal definitions. What he didn t take into account was that a definition s being real is not something we decide, and that not just any notions can be joined to one another. Nominal definitions are insufficient for perfect knowledge [scientia] except when the possibility of the thing defined is established in some other way. Near the start of this paper I listed four classifications of ideas, now at last we come to a fifth - true and false. It is obvious what true and false ideas are: an idea is true when it is a possible notion, and false when it includes a contradiction. Something s possibility can be known either a priori or a posteriori. The possibility of a thing is known a priori when we resolve a notion into its requisites, i.e. into other notions that are known to be possible and to be compatible with one another, and that are required if the notion is to apply. [These requisita could be components of the notion: closed is a component of circular, and could be called a logical requisite for something s being circular. In the very next sentence, however, Leibniz also brings in causal requisites.] This happens, for instance, when we understand how a thing can be produced, which is why causal definitions are more useful than others. A thing s possibility is known a posteriori when we know through experience that it actually exists, for what did or does actually exist is certainly possible! And, indeed, whenever we have adequate knowledge we also have a priori knowledge of possibility: if an analysis is brought to completion with no contradiction turning up, then certainly the analysed notion is possible. For men to produce a perfect analysis of their notions would be for them to reduce their thoughts to basic possibilities and unanalysable notions, which amounts to reducing them to the absolute attributes of God - and thus to the first causes and the ultimate reason for things. Can they do this? I shan t venture to settle the answer to that now. For the most part we are content to have learned through experience that certain notions are real [here = possible ], from which we then assemble others following the lead of nature. All this, I think, finally lets us understand that one should be cautious in claiming to have this or that idea. Many people who use this glittering title idea to prop up certain creatures of their imagination are using it wrongly, for we don t always have an idea corresponding to everything we consciously think of (as I showed with the example of greatest speed). People in our own times have laid down the principle: Whatever I vividly and clearly perceive about a thing is true, i.e. can be said of the thing; but I can t see that they have used this principle well. [Leibniz is referring to a principle of Descartes s that is almost always translated in English as Whatever I clearly and distinctly perceive....] For people who are careless in judgment often take to be vivid and clear what is really dim and confused in their minds. So this axiom is useless unless (1) explicitly stated criteria for vividness and clarity are introduced, and (2) we have established the truth of the ideas that are involved - in my sense, in which an idea is true if and only if it is possible, i.e. could have instances. Furthermore, the rules of common logic - which geometers use too - are not to be despised as criteria for the truth of assertions: for example, the rule that nothing is to be accepted as certain unless it is shown by careful testing or sound demonstration - a sound demonstration being one that follows the form prescribed by logic. Not that we always need arguments to be in syllogistic order as in the Aristotelian philosophy departments....; but the argument must somehow reach 4

its conclusion on the strength of its form. Any correct calculation provides an example of an argument conceived in proper logical form. Such an argument should not omit any necessary premise, and all premises should have been previously demonstrated - or else have been assumed as hypotheses, in which case the conclusion is also hypothetical. Someone who carefully observes these rules will easily protect himself against deceptive ideas. The highly talented Pascal largely agrees with this in his excellent essay On the Geometrical Mind.... The geometer, he says, must define all terms that are slightly obscure and prove all truths that are slightly dubious. But I wish he had made precise the line beyond which a notion or statement is no longer even slightly obscure or dubious. Most of what matters regarding this can be gathered from careful attention to what I have said above; and I shan t go further into it now, because I am trying to be brief. Before finishing, I offer three further remarks, only loosely connected with one another, but all having to do with ideas. (1) There has been controversy over whether we see everything in God - that is, perceive the world by sharing God s ideas with him - or whether we have our own ideas. The view that we see everything in God, though recently made famous through Malebranche s defence of it, is an old opinion, and properly understood it shouldn t be rejected completely. But the point I want to make here is that even if we did see everything in God, we would still also have to have our own ideas - not little sort-of copies of God s ideas, but states of our mind corresponding to the thing we perceived in God. For when go from having one thought to having another, there has to be some change in our mind - some alteration of our mind s state. (2) Don t think that in these changes of state the previous ideas are entirely wiped out. In fact, the ideas of things that we are not now actually thinking about are in our mind now, as the figure of Hercules is in a lump of marble. In God, on the other hand, all ideas are always actually engaged in his thought : he must have not only an actually occurrent idea of absolute and infinite extension but also an idea of each shape - a shape being merely a modification of absolute extension [meaning that a thing s having a certain shape is just its being extended in a certain way]. (3) A final point: when we perceive colours or smells, all that we really perceive - all! - are shapes and of motions; but they are so numerous and so tiny that our mind in its present state can t clearly attend to each one separately, so that it doesn t notice that its perception is composed purely of perceptions of minute shapes and motions. This is like what happens when we perceive the colour green in a mixture of yellow powder and blue powder. All we are sensing is yellow and blue, finely mixed, but we don t notice this, and invent something new - the colour green - for ourselves. 5