Robert Audi, The Architecture of Reason: The Structure and. Substance of Rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xvi, 286.

Similar documents
Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

Reliabilism and the Problem of Defeaters

2 Intuition, Self-Evidence, and Understanding

Intuition, Self-evidence, and understanding 1. Philip Stratton-Lake

Skepticism and Internalism

Perceptual Normativity and Accuracy. Richard Kenneth Atkins Presented at Central APA, 2011

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

SUPPOSITIONAL REASONING AND PERCEPTUAL JUSTIFICATION

Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to The Theory of Knowledge, by Robert Audi. New York: Routledge, 2011.

PRACTICAL REASONING. Bart Streumer

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Emotions and Epistemic Value: How Our Hearts Tell Us What Our Minds Cannot Jason Sangiamo Spring Introduction

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

A Priori Bootstrapping

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

The Skeptic and the Dogmatist

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

ABSTRACT: In this paper, I argue that Phenomenal Conservatism (PC) is not superior to

TESTIMONY AS AN A PRIORI BASIS OF ACCEPTANCE: PROBLEMS AND PROSPECTS. Robert Audi

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

PHENOMENAL CONSERVATISM, JUSTIFICATION, AND SELF-DEFEAT

Pictures, Proofs, and Mathematical Practice : Reply to James Robert Brown

PHIL 480: Seminar in the History of Philosophy Building Moral Character: Neo-Confucianism and Moral Psychology

A Solution to the Gettier Problem Keota Fields. the three traditional conditions for knowledge, have been discussed extensively in the

An Inferentialist Conception of the A Priori. Ralph Wedgwood

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

richard swinburne Oriel College, Oxford University, Oxford, OX1 4EW

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

The form of relativism that says that whether an agent s actions are right or wrong depends on the moral principles accepted in her own society.

The Many Problems of Memory Knowledge (Short Version)

Varieties of Apriority

Interest-Relativity and Testimony Jeremy Fantl, University of Calgary

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

FOUNDATIONALISM AND ARBITRARINESS

Craig on the Experience of Tense

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

Is atheism reasonable? Ted Poston University of South Alabama. Word Count: 4804

Phenomenal Conservatism and the Internalist Intuition

Virtue Ethics without Character Traits

DOUBT, CIRCULARITY AND THE MOOREAN RESPONSE TO THE SCEPTIC. Jessica Brown University of Bristol

Reliabilism: Holistic or Simple?

From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Justified Inference. Ralph Wedgwood

Bayesian Probability

A Defense of the Significance of the A Priori A Posteriori Distinction. Albert Casullo. University of Nebraska-Lincoln

Review of Steven D. Hales Book: Relativism and the Foundations of Philosophy

A proper de jure objection to the epistemic rationality of religious belief

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

PH 1000 Introduction to Philosophy, or PH 1001 Practical Reasoning

DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON

what makes reasons sufficient?

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2011

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

Is there a distinction between a priori and a posteriori

Infinitism Is the Solution to the

Is There Immediate Justification?

I guess I m just a good-old-fashioned internalist. A prominent position in philosophy of religion today is that religious experience can

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

3. Knowledge and Justification

Self-Evidence in Finnis Natural Law Theory: A Reply to Sayers

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Boghossian, Bellarmine, and Bayes

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome

McDowell and the New Evil Genius

Every simple idea has a simple impression, which resembles it; and every simple impression a correspondent idea

Is Moore s Argument an Example of Transmission-Failure? James Pryor Harvard University Draft 2 8/12/01

NON-COGNITIVISM AND THE PROBLEM OF MORAL-BASED EPISTEMIC REASONS: A SYMPATHETIC REPLY TO CIAN DORR

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

Four Arguments that the Cognitive Psychology of Religion Undermines the Justification of Religious Belief

Huemer s Problem of Memory Knowledge

Who Has the Burden of Proof? Must the Christian Provide Adequate Reasons for Christian Beliefs?

PERCEPTUAL INTUITIONISM WITHOUT ETHICAL PERCEPTION

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract

PARFIT'S MISTAKEN METAETHICS Michael Smith

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Internalism and Properly Basic Belief. Matthew Davidson, CSUSB Gordon Barnes, SUNY-Brockport

What Should We Believe?

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

IS EVIDENCE NON-INFERENTIAL?

CARTESIANISM, NEO-REIDIANISM, AND THE A PRIORI: REPLY TO PUST

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Review of Erik J. Wielenberg: Robust Ethics: The Metaphysics and Epistemology of Godless Normative Realism

The Frontloading Argument

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice

Boghossian s Implicit Definition Template

A Moorean Argument for the Full Moral Status of those with Profound Intellectual Disability. Introduction

Do we have knowledge of the external world?

Bayesian Probability

foundationalism and coherentism are responses to it. I will then prove that, although

Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2009

Knowledge is Not the Most General Factive Stative Attitude

Transcription:

Robert Audi, The Architecture of Reason: The Structure and Substance of Rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001. Pp. xvi, 286. Reviewed by Gilbert Harman Princeton University August 19, 2002 Audi develops analogies between theoretical and practical reason. He takes them to have a similar foundational structure based in experience. He indicates how recognition of this similarity allows insights about one sort of reason to be applied to the other sort. In particular, it becomes clear that egoism is not a reasonable account of practical reason. In addition to these main themes, Audi distinguishes and assesses various sorts of relativism about reason and develops an account of what it is to be a reasonable and rational person. There are numerous interesting points along the way, many more than can be addressed in a short review. Audi supposes that beliefs may be (defeasibly) grounded in other beliefs or in certain foundational experiences, such as perceptual or sensory experiences, whereas desires may be grounded in other desires and beliefs or in certain foundational experiences of liked or disliked experiences. In both cases the foundations are experiences rather than beliefs about experiences. (He argues that Sellars attack on the myth of the given does not apply to his version of foundationalism.) He allows for other foundational sources of justification for beliefs in addition to sensory experience, namely, introspection, remembering (both remembering the experience and remembering that something is or was the case), and reason (or reflection or intuition). 1

Justified non-inferential beliefs are based on foundational sources. Justified inferential beliefs are based on justified beliefs. The same foundational structure holds for desires or wants, where intrinsic wants are analogous to non-inferential beliefs. Foundational experiences for wants are intrinsically liked or disliked because they are pleasant or unpleasant, but this does not mean, say, that wanting to swim for pleasure is wanting to swim as a means to pleasure: one envisions the pleasure as in the swimming. So wanting to swim can be an intrinsic want. Audi distinguishes objectual wanting (wanting the pain to stop), behavioral wanting (wanting to swim), and propositional wanting (wanting there to be no more war). Wanting the pain to stop is objectual wanting (wanting this to stop) rather than propositional (wanting that I am free from the pain), so in an important sense it is not egoistic. He says that a similar point holds for belief. Many philosophers have conflated the question of what justifies a belief with the problem of how it can be defended... The basis of my justification for believing that there is a tree before me is a particular visual experience... I am not part of the object of the experience (102) and selfreferential beliefs need not be taken as primary in perception (103). We should reject epistemic egocentrism just as we reject egoism. There is at least one disanalogy between theoretical and practical reason. Suppose that P and Q are incompatible propositions, that you have conclusive reasons to believe their disjunction, P or Q, and that your total evidence does not favor one alternative over the other. Then from the point of view of theoretical reason, it would seem you must suspend judgment and not believe one or the other. On the other hand, if A and B are incompatible courses of action (for example, representing two ways of getting to a place you need to get to), if you have conclusive reasons to take one of these courses of action, and if you have no more reason to take one rather than the other, then from the point of view of practical reason you really must decide and must not fail to make a decision. Audi notes this difference but describes it in the following way. In the practical case, you are justified in choosing course of action A and you are justified in choosing course of action B, whereas in the theoretical case you are neither justified in believing P nor justified in believing Q; however, he thinks you might be rational in believing P and rational in believing Q in the case described, which seems absolutely wrong to me. 2

One worry about Audi s approach lies in the particular way in which it depends on the notion of a ground or basis of a belief or desire, whether ultimate or not. He says at one point that one s grounds for a belief are the sorts of things that a successful justification for it would provide where a justification is a process of arguing for the belief by supplying premises that support the belief. But, as already mentioned, one s ultimate grounds can include experiences, where experiences of the relevant sort are not premises and are not the sort of thing that a successful argument provides. He allows that a justificatory argument might include premises about certain experiences, but it is the experiences, not the claims about them, which are the ultimate source of justification. He allows that the current grounds of a belief need not be the original grounds. The current grounds of a belief support it in the way that pillars support a porch (where one pillar might replace another in bearing the weight). Support is a kind of psychologically unobtrusive evidential sustenance relation. However, we cannot identify supporting beliefs with those one would offer if asked to justify one s belief, because it can be difficult to tell when we are discovering a new ground... and when we are articulating one that was already a tacit basis of that belief. Sometimes a belief is simply retained in memory with no record of the original reasons and no new grounds. It is not completely clear to me what status Audi attributes to such a belief. Suppose the belief is not currently on one s mind; it is just sitting there in memory. It therefore cannot be grounded in a present memory experience, because there is no such experience. Is such a belief grounded in memory simply by virtue of being retained in memory? Or is it ungrounded? Some theorists would say that the justification of such a belief depends on its earlier history. But Audi appears to accept a kind of internalism of the present moment which rules out such an appeal to history. He does say that, An important exception to the view that intentional actions are grounded in intrinsic desires is this. One might have forgotten why one is going into the kitchen, hence have a desire to do so that is merely non-intrinsic: neither intrinsic nor instrumental. He calls this a residual desire (footnote 8, p. 246). So presumably a belief for which one has forgotten one s reasons without having acquired any others is also ungrounded, a residual belief. At an earlier point Audi says, A merely non-inferential belief will be neither justified nor capable of 3

conferring justification on any belief grounded in it; for similar reasons I suggest that a merely noninstrumental desire will tend to be neither rational (though it need not be irrational) nor capable of conferring rationality on any desire or action grounded on it (128). What worries me about this is that a typical reader of this review may have a million separate beliefs about what words mean, about the names and phone numbers of acquaintances, about historical dates and various other useful and useless facts. In relation to that vast store of beliefs, the reader s current experiences are quite limited, including current sensory experiences, current memory experiences, experiences of introspection, and experiences of reflection and intuition. A moment s reflection suffices to indicate that the actual experiences of the reader at this time are insufficient to serve as any sort of foundational justification of all but a few of those million beliefs. Furthermore, it is quite possible, even likely, that almost all of those million beliefs are simply retained in memory with no record of the original reasons and no new grounds in relevant support relations, although Audi denies it. Once it is clear that a belief can be inferential by virtue of standing to one or more other beliefs in the kind of psychologically unobtrusive evidential sustenance relation just illustrated, it also becomes apparent that a great many of our beliefs are inferential. They are based on one or more other, evidential beliefs of ours, as opposed to being non-inferentially grounded in a current experience or mental state or simply retained in memory (35). As we have seen, in a typical case, a person will have a foundation of non-inferential beliefs rational on the basis of experience or reason and a vast superstructure of beliefs based on them (205). On the contrary, this is far from apparent. It rests on a very strong and dubious psychological hypothesis about support relations. To be sure, people do indeed provide justifications for their beliefs when asked, but the justifications often have little to do with why they originally held the views or why they hold them now. People tend to rationalize, they fabricate reasons when asked 4

what their reasons are. When the original reasons for belief are undermined or when actually cited reasons for belief are undermined people tend to continue believing as they do. If challenged, instead of giving up a belief, they come up with other new reasons for it (Ross and Anderson, 1982; Haidt, 2001). Audi notes that, it is philosophically prudent to try to account for rationality without multiplying beliefs, inferences, or thought processes of any kind beyond necessity (34). It is also philosophically prudent to avoid unnecessarily speculative psychological hypotheses! The problem I worry about here applies to many other foundational theories and I am not what the best response to it is. Audi ought to be able to adapt that best response to the attractive theory he presents here. References Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review. 108, 814-834. Ross, Lee, and Anderson, Craig A., (1982). Shortcomings in the attribution process: on the origins and maintenance of erroneous social assessments, in Judgement under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 5