Robert Bellah s Symbolic Realism: A Contemporary Modification to Durkheim s Epistemology

Similar documents
R. Keith Sawyer: Social Emergence. Societies as Complex Systems. Cambridge University Press

The Leadership of Hindu Gurus: Its Meaning and Implications for Practice

SOCI 301/321 Foundations of Social Thought

RS 200A: Proseminar in the History and Theory of Religion

HISTORY OF SOCIAL THEORY I: Community & Religion

Holtzman Spring Philosophy and the Integration of Knowledge

Gilbert. Margaret. Scientists Are People Too: Comment on Andersen. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 6, no. 5 (2017):

The Human Science Debate: Positivist, Anti-Positivist, and Postpositivist Inquiry. By Rebecca Joy Norlander. November 20, 2007

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

SOCI 301/321 Foundations of Social Thought

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

EDUCATION EDUCATION AND RELIGION STRUCTURAL PROCESSES FORMAL INFORMAL THE MOST POWERFUL STRUCTURAL FORCES FOR PROCESSES OF SOCIALIZATION

Sociology 475 Classical Sociological Theory. Office: 8103 Social Science Bldng

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

SOCI 301/321 Foundations of Social Thought

12.0 Objectives 12.1 Introduction 12.2 Society and Individual Consciousness 12.3 Collective Conscience 12.4 Collective Representations

510: Theories and Perspectives - Classical Sociological Theory

ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis

REL 6013 MODERN ANALYSIS OF RELIGION

SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY Michaelmas 2018 Dr Michael Biggs

Reimagining God. The Faith Journey of a Modern Heretic. Lloyd Geering. Study & discussion guide prepared by Jarmo Tarkki

Qué es la filosofía? What is philosophy? Philosophy

BOOK REVIEWS. The arguments of the Parmenides, though they do not refute the Theory of Forms, do expose certain problems, ambiguities and

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

Chapter Six. Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality

Cosmopolitan Theory and the Daily Pluralism of Life

CLASSICAL SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY Sociology 475

Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard

REL 3931: JUNIOR SEMINAR TUESDAY, PERIOD 6 & THURSDAY, PERIODS 5-6 AND 19 FALL 2014

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism

Introduction. 1 Bertrand Russell, The Problems of Philosophy (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, n.d.), 7.

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins

UNIVERSITY OF WISCONSIN-MADISON Department of History. Semester I,

SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY (Michaelmas 2017) Dr Michael Biggs

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY

MDiv Expectations/Competencies ATS Standard

Robert N. Bellah. UNM Digital Repository. University of New Mexico. Richard L. Wood

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY (Michaelmas 2017) Dr Michael Biggs

Honouring Egypt. The Great Pyramids of Giza over 4,500 years ago Akhenaten and Nefertiti 3,350 years ago

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought

SOCIOLOGY OF RELIGION (sample lower level undergraduate course)

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Instructor's Manual for Gregg Barak s Integrating Criminologies. Prepared by Paul Leighton (Boston: Allyn & Bacon, 1997) * CHAPTER 4

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

On the Rationality of Metaphysical Commitments in Immature Science

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

THE CHALLENGES FOR EARLY MODERN PHILOSOPHY: EDITORIAL INTRODUCTION 1. Steffen Ducheyne

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

THE RE-VITALISATION of the doctrine

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

The Other Half of Hegel s Halfwayness: A response to Dr. Morelli s Meeting Hegel Halfway. Ben Suriano

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

ACCOUNT OF SOCIAL ONTOLOGY DURKHEIM S RELATIONAL DANIEL SAUNDERS. Durkheim s Social Ontology

A theory of adjudication is a theory primarily about what judges do when they decide cases in courts of law.

COMITÉ SUR LES AFFAIRES RELIGIEUSES A NEW APPROACH TO RELIGIOUS EDUCATION IN SCHOOL: A CHOICE REGARDING TODAY S CHALLENGES

Kant On The A Priority of Space: A Critique Arjun Sawhney - The University of Toronto pp. 4-7

THE CREATED CONSTITUTION OF MAN

Roots of Dialectical Materialism*

Stabilizing Kant s First and Second Critiques: Causality and Freedom

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Equality, Fairness, and Responsibility in an Unequal World

RAHNER AND DEMYTHOLOGIZATION 555

Neo-Confucianism: Metaphysics, Mind, and Morality

MODELS CLARIFIED: RESPONDING TO LANGDON GILKEY. by David E. Klemm and William H. Klink

Ibuanyidanda (Complementary Reflection), African Philosophy and General Issues in Philosophy

[3.] Bertrand Russell. 1

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Causation and Free Will

ANSWERS TO THE QUESTIONS FOR DISCUSSION

J.f. Stephen s On Fraternity And Mill s Universal Love 1

Motion from the Right Relationship Monitoring Committee for the UUA Board of Trustees meeting January 2012

Human Nature & Human Diversity: Sex, Love & Parenting; Morality, Religion & Race. Course Description

Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 5

Chapter 15 Religion. Introduction to Sociology Spring 2010

1/10. Descartes Laws of Nature

Theory and Methodology in the Study of Religion RE 241, Section Fall 2016

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

Adam Smith and the Limits of Empiricism

COPYRIGHTED MATERIAL ALL RIGHTS RESERVED

Ritual and Its Consequences

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

Justice and Ethics. Jimmy Rising. October 3, 2002

Reflections on sociology's unspoken weakness: Bringing epistemology back in

Positivist Criminology: the search for a criminal type? Dan Ellingworth Understanding Criminology Friday, 24 October 2008

Gibbs, Eddie, Leadership Next, Downers Grove, Illinois: Intervarsity Press, pp. Reviewed by Parnell M. Lovelace, Jr.

INVESTIGATING THE PRESUPPOSITIONAL REALM OF BIBLICAL-THEOLOGICAL METHODOLOGY, PART II: CANALE ON REASON

4 Liberty, Rationality, and Agency in Hobbes s Leviathan

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Philosophica 67 (2001, 1) pp. 5-9 INTRODUCTION

Transcription:

Robert Bellah s Symbolic Realism: A Contemporary Modification to Durkheim s Epistemology ABSTRACT: By privileging practice over idea, a Durkheimian perspective fails to account for how the abstract realm of conceptual ideas, symbols and beliefs can become sacrilized and thereby effect subsequent action. Bellah s theory of symbolic realism faithfully extends Durkheim s theory to explain how symbols can evolve out of practice to become powerful determinants of action. By avoiding the pitfall of privileging practice over ideas, symbolic realism allows for a flexible account of cultural historical variation in Durkheim s theory of practice. Tricia Wang University of California, San Diego Department of Sociology Paper located online at: https://triciawang.pbwiki.com Tricia Wang triciawang@mac.com

Robert Bellah s symbolic realism provides an account for cultural maintenance that explains not only how practice evolves, but also how symbols and beliefs evolve. Although Emile Durkheim was the classical theorist who most inspired Bellah, he realized that Durkheim s model did not recognize the transcendental power of symbols to affect practice. Therefore, Bellah s theory optimizes Durkheim s original account for society, that belief is generated by practice, into a more flexible account for how culture and society develops. Bellah is one of many post-durkheimian scholars dedicated to understanding his works. Among the various reinterpretations of Durkheim s work, the most recent theoretical contribution has been Anne Rawl s extensive analysis of The Elementary Forms of Religious Life. She argues that Durkheim s theory of knowledge has two components: sociology of knowledge and an epistemology based on practice. Rawls argues that it is this latter component that has been repeatedly misunderstood and entirely overlooked by post-durkheimian interpretations (Rawls 2004: 6). She contends that contemporary sociology has fallen into a fallacy of misplaced abstraction creating an unstable hierarchy that favors abstract concepts at the expense of enacted practice (Rawls 2004: 324-326, 332). 1 This is the realm of sociology of knowledge, which privileges concepts over action. She urges the field (of sociology) to distance itself from such a strong focus on belief and to honor Durkheim s epistemological approach that privileges practice. I agree with Rawl s argument that radical postmodernism treats symbols as the ultimate reality; this approach has created an analytical cul-de-sac wherein belief is treated as the prime unit of analysis. But by attempting to bring sociology back to 1 She points out Baudrillard s argument that treats symbols as reality. I agree with her that this branch of post-modern sociology has veered too far into the conceptual realm (Rawls 1997: 27; Baudrillard 1994). Tricia wang Page 2 triciawang@mac.com

Durkheim s epistemology of practice, Rawls perpetuates the very divide that she is critiquing. As the saying goes, plus ca change, plus c est la meme chose. Her critique reinforces the problematic notion of analytical hierarchy in sociology base or superstructure, micro or macro, positivist or idealist approach, and practice or ideas? One side always privileges their analytical method by accusing the other side of inadequacy. But by picking a side and privileging one method, Rawls, and all the other post-durkheimian scholars who perpetuate the false dichotomy of practice versus belief, miss the big picture. By privileging practice over idea, a Durkheimian perspective fails to account for how the abstract realm of conceptual ideas, symbols and beliefs can become sacrilized and thereby effect subsequent action. This analytical inadequacy makes it difficult to account for historical variation in practice. Sociology of knowledge attempts to address this inadequacy by focusing on concepts. Unfortunately, the sociology of knowledge purists have lost sight of the fact that, as Durkheim contends, symbols are rooted in practice. 2 Rawls solution, like other post-durkheimian scholars, fails to look into the work of Robert Bellah, who bridges the sociology of knowledge and epistemology by refusing to privilege practice over ideas or vice versa. I argue that Bellah s theory of symbolic realism faithfully extends Durkheim s theory to explain how symbols can evolve out of practice to become powerful determinants of action; whereas Durkheim privileges practice over idea, Bellah s theory treats practice and ideas as mutably reciprocal. By avoiding the pitfall of privileging practice over ideas, symbolic realism allows for a flexible 2 The division in sociology that Rawls is critiquing is an attempt to bridge practice and symbols, yet the solution she offers Durkheim s theory of practice as more important than ideas is a return to the original dichotomy that the sociology of knowledge camp attempted to solve, but has failed to comprehensively answer. Tricia wang Page 3 triciawang@mac.com

account of cultural historical variation in Durkheim s theory of practice. In what follows, I will show how Bellah agrees with Durkheim that beliefs are rooted in practice, and demonstrate how symbolic realism curtails the privileging of practice over belief in organic solidarity. By doing so, Bellah sets up practice and symbols as mutually interdependent. Both Bellah and Durkheim agree that symbols are important and necessary to society (Durkheim 1995: 223, 232; Bellah 1970: 203). Most importantly, Bellah remains faithful to Durkheim s principal tenet that enacted practice creates the conditions of life which give rise to ideas (Durkheim 1995: 231). These ideas can then shape reality, but they have to be attach[ed] to material things that symbolize them (Durkheim 1995: 229). Affirming Durkheim s prime tenet of material action, Bellah conceives of religion as always embedded in the whole range of human action (Bellah et. al. 2006: 6, 1965: 24). Symbolic realism is genuinely rooted in Durkheim s epistemology, because Bellah clearly maintains that beliefs originate in practice. However, symbolic realism challenges Durkheim s assertion that orders of practice take over shared beliefs in organic solidarity. In Division of Labor in Society, Durkheim argues that an organic solidarity predicated on a forced division of labor, creates excessive individualism (1960: 379-380). 3 In a society where a differentiated labor structure promotes and entrenches individualism, traditional beliefs no longer carry weight (1960: 379). As a result, the power of collective beliefs to constrain individuals wanes. This was Durkheim s critique of modernity, that rational individualism was valued over collective activity in organic solidarity. 4 3 By way of contrast, in mechanical solidarity the beliefs played a larger role than practice 4 This critique is most apparent in Suicide, where he says in organic solidarity, an increase in anomie leads to egoistic suicides (1951). Tricia wang Page 4 triciawang@mac.com

Durkheim sees a return to practice as the only solution for a society comprised of a multiplicity of individuals. He insists that society has to create new practices to generate new beliefs, because symbols left over from mechanical solidarity cannot combat radical individualism. For example, his work in pedagogical sociology reflects an attempt to systematically create a common practice of education for French children, as a basis of generating unifying symbols and morals (Lukes 1973: 109-119). Later on, Durkheim also provides the French Revolution as an example when symbols had to be overturned in practice to generate new beliefs (1995: 213, 215). Durkheim distinctly periodizes historical changes with changes in practice. That is, he clearly privileges practice over beliefs. This is also where the practice-over-belief hierarchy becomes the clearest and most problematic, because a historical periodization based on practice creates a conceptual cul-de-sac because he insinuates that only practices evolve, not symbols. But symbols do evolve. This is where Bellah calibrates Durkheim s model by providing symbolic realism s two most important modifications to Durkheim. Bellah s first construct posits that as the social order evolves, symbols evolve also: neither religious man nor the structure of man's ultimate religious situation evolves, then, but rather religion as symbol systems" (Bellah 1964: 24, Madsen et. al. 2001: 5). 5 If a symbol no longer works for society, it does not simply follow a linear path of disappearance, like in Durkheim s model; a symbol can either lose its power or it can become more powerful. Durkheim does not provide an account for how symbols can become sacrilized. This leads to Bellah s second construct, which is that symbols can take on a life of their own (1970b). Whereas Durkheim believed symbols were only second hand reflections of practice, Bellah insists that symbols as second hand 5 He explains his use of the word evolution as social evolution. The path is flexible and does not have a pre-determined or even planned outcome (Bellah et. al 2006: 19). Tricia wang Page 5 triciawang@mac.com

reflections not only reify the practice, they can also transcend practice and become sacrilized through this process. Bellah s symbolic realism posits practice and symbols in a state of flux (Bellah et. al 2006: 6). In this sense, symbols and practice are mutably reciprocal as one changes, so can the other. His understanding of religions as constituting symbolic forms and acts that relate [humans] to the ultimate conditions of [their] existence means that he sees practice and beliefs as interdependent, and does not privilege one over the other (1964: 24). Bellah thus solves Durkheim s hierarchy by treating symbols as capable of exerting force, while still faithfully acknowledging that symbols are rooted in practice. This treatment gives symbols the power to exert their own moral force; Durkheim says it is only in practice that moral force can be exerted (1995: 213, 223-224, 424). Durkheim always returned to practice as the locus of ritual. Rituals are ceremonies of moral remaking that create and/or redefine the sacred versus the profane (1995: 429). This is consistent with Durkheim's work in pedagogical sociology, where he saw education as the locus of practice to impress a rational morality on French students (Lukes 1973: 115). 6 Clearly, moral force for Durkheim can only be exerted in practice, where for Bellah, it can also be exerted in symbols. Herein lies the key to understanding how Bellah solves Durkheim s problem of characterizing historical periodization with practice. By identifying the root of his conceptual cul-de-sac, that only practice can exert moral force, Bellah masterfully renders symbols as capable of exerting moral force on society 6 Lukes points out that Durkheim s account of morality went through several changes throughout his writing, but these lectures on pedagogy provides the most clear elements of how he defined morality. He defined it by three elements: discipline, attachment to social groups, and autonomy (1973: 115-119). Tricia wang Page 6 triciawang@mac.com

(1968). 7 Bellah recognizes that when there is a strong collective practice supporting a symbol, the symbol can cross a critical threshold and take on a life of its own and affect future enacted practice. Bellah effectively dissolves the hierarchy of practice over idea by recognizing that symbols exert real social force, and account for historical variation and a historical periodization rooted in the mutably reciprocal relationships of practice and symbols. 8 By implicating a symbolic evolution that goes hand-in-hand with action evolution, Bellah s symbolic realism provides an account for religiosity in modernity. His concept of civic religion in America explains that religiosity never disappears; rather it is the symbols and practice that change (1967: 233). Religion (for example beliefs of Protestantism) has not disappeared, rather it has mutated into a form of civic religion sui generis. This is an example of how symbols can exert their own social force. Although the theoretical thrust of symbolic realism asserts that symbols can change and affect action, it is important to note that not all symbols follow this path. Depending on how entrenched a symbol is in the power system, it can be difficult to overturn: once a symbol reaches mythical status, it can become more real over time (Bellah et. al. 2006: 9). This is how symbols become sacrilized a dynamic that Durkheim did not explore. Bellah attributes Durkheim s lack of fully understanding symbols and his mechanistic view of historical periodization based on practice to his symbolic reductivist approach (1970: 90). He recognizes Durkheim s attempt to reach beneath the symbol to grasp 7 Shepard s article provides a good outline that traces Symbolic realism s theoretical elements throughout Bellah s extensive writing until the mid-1970 s. 8 Bellah acknowledges that a common critique of Durkheim is that his model does not account for historical variation, to the extent that others have called him an ahistorical theorist. However, Bellah points out that historical research was a large part of Durkheim s sociology particularly in family, individuation and religion and he has made an invaluable methodological contribution to the field in that comparison and structural taxonomy can account for the variables for an adequate theory of social change (Bellah 1959). Tricia wang Page 7 triciawang@mac.com

the reality it represents as contain[ing] deep inner contradictions precisely with respect to this point (Durkheim 1995:2, Bellah 1970b: 92). 9 A reductivist approach assumes that once you understand the truth, you understand the truth and root of all symbols. 10 Durkheim s methodological approach confirms this, because he believed that society s categories of understanding basically address the same needs; therefore one can study just one religion and understand all religion (Rawls 1997: 13). Durkheim's approach reduces societies to merely their practices, therefore it is of no surprise that he also reduces historical periodization to practices. 11 Let us examine a modern example that traces the relationship between symbols and practice. Racial discrimination is real and symbolic at the same time. It can be located in practice and it can also be carried on as an abstract belief. For example, in Jim Crow America, Blacks were physically barred from drinking public water fountains or riding public buses. Massive protests, boycotts and marches against segregation are examples of communal practices attempting to overturn discrimination as a practice and as a culture. The Civil Rights Act of 1964 declared discrimination against Blacks (and everyone else) illegal. However, the belief of racism against Blacks still persists to this day, and therefore still affects practice, which reinforces beliefs. This is an example of a symbolic belief that has both transcended practice and affected action. The belief of racism is so strong that a person can become racist without ever having to physically 9 Although Bellah points out this contradiction, he compassionately situates Durkheim s reductivist approach among many other scholars (e.g. Feuerbach, Hegel, Weber, Freud) in the context of dealing with the split between religion and science, and reacting against the rational individualism that has been popular since the Enlightenment (1970b). 10 Bellah clarifies Durkheim s contradiction by pointing out that he said religion is a reality sui generis, and if a study of society and religion has to include the totality of subject and object. Therefore, symbols and practice as they correspond to religious symbolization and experience, are inherent in the structure of human existence, all reductionism must be abandoned (1970b: 93). Tricia wang Page 8 triciawang@mac.com

interact with a Black person. Symbols can be passed down through practice to enforce a practice. Symbols are mutable, but they are dependent on practice. This is what also provides historical variation, because one can trace how racism as a symbolic and an enacted practice has mutated. One can argue that although there is a decrease in the practice of racism since the era of American slavery, the enduring belief of racism explains why racism is still a problem symbolically and practically. A purely Durkheimian explanation cannot account for why racism still persists. To eliminate racism, Durkheim would call for a communal action to agitate for a new morality that would generate new symbols. 12 His career as a social scientist exemplifies this simplistic, mechanistic solution for creating new beliefs, whereby new moral forces can be easily generated with enough action. 13 But social change is not exclusively reducible to actions. Bellah acknowledges this by seeing symbols as capable of exerting moral force. This is why after 43 years of the Civil Rights Act, other important pieces of legislation, countless protests, and attention from the media, racism still persists: racism is not only a practice, it lives on as an abstract concept in institutional memory. 14 A Durkheimian response does not suffice for a world where some symbols gain enough institutionalized power to transcend action. 12 Rawls points out that in his detailed outline of Australian totemism that Durkheim posits that generating moral force is an ongoing process for all societies because this is how reason is produced (2004: 171). 13 Rawls provides a great explanation that clarifies Durkheim s position that the confrontation with moral forces generates rational idea, not the belief system. It is only in practice where individuals come together to experience this social force, and that is why Rawls insists that Durkheim privileges practice because it is the only place and time empirical observation is possible. This is the root of his socially based epistemological answer to individualism (2004: 15). 14 Even before American slavery, there has been historical racism against Africans. Tricia wang Page 9 triciawang@mac.com

Bellah empathetically understands Durkheim s intentions within the context of his time period, and optimizes his model into a dynamic analytical framework. By locating symbols as mutable, yet interdependent on practice, Bellah creates a convincing and useful theoretical framework to examine comparative historical variations and developments. We can see that Bellah roots his discourse on symbols in the cybernetic model, which treats symbols as transcending action, but not equivalent with action: Great summary symbols are neither objective nor subjective, neither cosmological nor psychological. Rather, they are relational symbols that are intended to overcome precisely such dichotomies of ordinary conceptualization and bring together the coherence of the whole experience (1970a: 9, 202). He sees the importance of overcoming the very dichotomies that Rawls critiques yet perpetuates. 15 Bellah masterfully bridges sociology of knowledge and sociological epistemology by treating symbols as capable of exerting real moral forces, and by treating symbols as always rooted in practice. He does not make the mistake (that Rawls claims of all post- Durkheimian scholars) of treating the interpretation as the original thing, because he treats the interpreter s reality of beliefs in the larger context of other interpreters (Rawls 2004: 25). As one of earliest developers of contemporary American cultural sociology 16, he realizes that interpretations do not take place in a vacuum, actions cannot be reduced to a single explanation, and that structures as constituted of symbols do not suffice as an 15 This formally developed into his theory of Symbolic realism in his 1969 article on Christianity and Symbolic realism. He has now further developed his theory to explain how symbols operate on three different levels, mimetic, mythic and theoretic (Bellah et. al 2006: 7-11). In a forthcoming book, he will elaborate on how religious and symbolic representations fluctuate between these three levels. 16 Along with Clifford Geertz (Alexander 2001: 2) Tricia wang Page 10 triciawang@mac.com

explanation of the actor s decisions (Alexander and Sherwood 2001: 2). 17 He is careful to avoid a structurally deterministic, functionally simplistic or symbolically reductivist approach. He simply does this by not privileging practice over idea. Where Durkheim privileges, Bellah balances; and where Durkheim divides, Bellah bridges. Symbolic realism should be acknowledged in any treatment that critiques misinterpretations of Durkheim. If anything, towards the end of Durkheim s writing, he implies the need for a symbolic realistic approach in his call for a cult of humanity that would curb excessive patriotism and promote a humane cosmopolitanism (Lukes 1973: 350). This new international civic religion would bring together the entire world to sacrilize humanity. 18 Perhaps if Durkheim expounded on how his religion of humanity would have brought together a multiplicity of nations, cultures, religions, races and ethnicities, we would have a better understanding of how to organize economic life and introduce greater justice to combat the utilitarian ethic [of individualism] that is appeared to [be] incompatible with social necessities (1973: 48, 56). Fortunately, Bellah has picked up Durkheim s baton that a world civil religion is possible, but it requires vital international symbolism (pg 245 Bellah). This is the heart of symbolic realism s contribution to Durkheim s call for a common global solidarity based on humanity. In order to do this, you need a powerful symbol to arise from collective action, one that can respond to the multiplicity of heterogeneous moralities, cultures and nations. This is where symbolic realism can be most useful it acknowledges that a symbol can arise from practice to speak on a universal level and 17 Alexander and Sherwood s article detail how Bellah and Geertz s middle-period of writing bridged forma and informal Parsoniansim and thereby bridging mid- and latetwentieth-century sociology (2001: 3). 18 The exposition Intellectual and Intellectualism, published in 1898, signal a shift in Durkheim s unit of analysis from intra-societal to inter-societal. However, his writing focused only intra-societal analysis and primitive or mechanical societies. Tricia wang Page 11 triciawang@mac.com

transcend down to the individual, and still make room for a multiplicity of differences. However, Durkheim is not a conservative scholar, urging for a return to a traditional or mechanic solidarity. In a world of extreme individualism predicated on a division of labor, to prevent [people] from differentiating themselves more and more from each other, to equalize their personalities, to lead them back to the old conformism of former times...infinitely exceeds all human capability (1973: 52). He does not call for restraining and combating individualism; rather, it is about completing, extending and organizing individualism (1973: 56). In a world of mutable symbols and practice, Bellah responds with a flexible schema that allows for the emergence of a dynamic multidimensional self capable, within limits, of continual self-transformation and capable, again within limits, of remaking the world, including the very symbolic forms with which [s]/he deals with, even the forms that state the unalterable conditions of [her]/his own existence (Bellah 1964: 47). In Bellah s world, an individual not only realizes her/himself through practice, but also through continual self-dialogue that examines belief systems that justify practice. Tricia wang Page 12 triciawang@mac.com

References Alexander, Jeffery and Philip Smith, eds. The Cambridge Companion to Durkheim. 2005.. Cambridge, UK ; New York: Cambridge. Alexander, Jeffery., and Steven J. Sherwood. Mythic Gestures: Robert N. Bellah and Cultural Sociology. In Meaning and Modernity : Religion, Polity, and Self. Madsen, Richard, William M. Sullivan, Ann Swidler, and Steven M. Tipton, eds. 2001. Berkeley: University of California Press. Baudrillard, Jean. 1994. Simulacra and Simulation. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. Bellah, Robert N., and Steven M. Tipton, eds. 2006. "The Robert Bellah Reader." Durhan and London: Duke University Press. Bellah, Robert N. 1959. "Durkheim and History." American Sociological Review 24 (4):447-461.. 1964. Religious Evolution. In The Robert Bellah Reader. Bellah, Robert N., and Steven M. Tipton, eds. 2006. Durham and London: Duke University Press.. 1967. Civil Religion in America. In The Robert Bellah Reader. Bellah, Robert N., and Steven M. Tipton, eds. 2006. Durham and London: Duke University Press. Durkheim, Emile. 1951. Suicide.. New York,: Free Press.. 1966. The Division of Labor in Society. New York,: Free Press.. 1973. On Morality and Society; Selected Writings. Chicago,: University of Chicago Press.. 1983. Pragmatism and Sociology. Cambridge Cambridgeshire ; New York: Cambridge University Press.. 1995. The Elementary Forms of Religious Life. New York: Free Press. Lukes, Steven. 1973. Emile Durkheim, His Life and Work: A Historical and Critical Study. London,: Allen Lane. Madsen, Richard, William M. Sullivan, Ann Swidler, and Steven M. Tipton, eds. 2001. Meaning and Modernity : Religion, Polity, and Self. Berkeley: University of California Press. Nisbet, Robert A. 1976. Emile Durkheim. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.,: Prentice-Hall. Rawls, Anne Warfield. 1997. "Durkheim and Pragmatism: An Old Twist on a Contemporary Debate." Sociological Theory 15 (1):5-29.. 1968. Religion and Progress in Modern Asia. New York,: Free Press.. 1970a. Beyond Belief; Essays on Religion in a Post-Traditional World. New York,: Harper & Row.. 1970b. "Christianity and Symbolic realism." Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion 9 (2):89-96.. 1975. The Broken Covenant : American Civil Religion in Time of Trial. New York: Seabury Press.. 2004. Epistemology and Practice : Durkheim's the Elementary Forms of Religious Life. Cambridge ; New York: Cambridge University Press. Shepherd, William C. 1975. "Robert Bellah's Sociology of Religion: The Theoretical Elements." Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion 14 (4):395-402. Wallace, Ruth A. 1977. "Emile Durkheim and the Civil Religion Concept." Review of Religious Research 18 (3):287-290. Tricia wang Page 13 triciawang@mac.com