KANT ON THE BEGINNINGS OF HUMAN HISTORY - CONJECTURES BY A SOCIOLOGIST by Richard Swedberg German Studies Colloquium on Immanuel Kant, Conjectures on

Similar documents
Various historical aims of research

prohibition, moral commitment and other normative matters. Although often described as a branch

IDHEF Chapter 2 Why Should Anyone Believe Anything At All?

SOCIOLOGICAL THEORIES I

Sociological Theory Sociology University of Chicago Graduate Class: Fall 2011 John Levi Martin. Tuesdays and Thursdays, 10:30 11:50, SS 404

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

POLI 343 Introduction to Political Research

Predicate logic. Miguel Palomino Dpto. Sistemas Informáticos y Computación (UCM) Madrid Spain

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

INTRODUCTION. THE FIRST TIME Tocqueville met with the English economist Nassau Senior has been recorded by Senior s daughter:

What Happens When Wittgenstein Asks "What Happens When...?"

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

What Is Science? Mel Conway, Ph.D.

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

David O Connor. Hume on Religion H. O. Mounce Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 2 (November, 2002)

What is truth? what is. Are we responsible. Have free will? Could robots ever What is be conscious?

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

The Nature of Human Brain Work. Joseph Dietzgen

Hoong Juan Ru. St Joseph s Institution International. Candidate Number Date: April 25, Theory of Knowledge Essay

PREFERENCES AND VALUE ASSESSMENTS IN CASES OF DECISION UNDER RISK

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

510: Theories and Perspectives - Classical Sociological Theory

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

Kant s Misrepresentations of Hume s Philosophy of Mathematics in the Prolegomena

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

Problems of Philosophy

Introduction The Science Wars in Perspective

DALLAS BAPTIST UNIVERSITY THE ILLOGIC OF FAITH: FEAR AND TREMBLING IN LIGHT OF MODERNISM SUBMITTED TO THE GENTLE READER FOR SPRING CONFERENCE

Pictures, Proofs, and Mathematical Practice : Reply to James Robert Brown

A Review of Norm Geisler's Prolegomena

Genre Guide for Argumentative Essays in Social Science

Tools Andrew Black CS 305 1

He believes that religion and its ethics leave a deep dimensions of the society.

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER VI CONDITIONS OF IMMEDIATE INFERENCE

Replies to critics. Miranda FRICKER

Lecture 6 Kantianism. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

MISSOURI S FRAMEWORK FOR CURRICULAR DEVELOPMENT IN MATH TOPIC I: PROBLEM SOLVING

HISTORY OF SOCIAL THEORY I: Community & Religion

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford.

Chapter Summaries: Introduction to Christian Philosophy by Clark, Chapter 1

All They Know: A Study in Multi-Agent Autoepistemic Reasoning

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Humanizing the Future

There are a number of writing problems that occur frequently enough to deserve special mention here:

270 Now that we have settled these issues, we should answer the first question [n.

Lecture 25 Hume on Causation

The Development of Laws of Formal Logic of Aristotle

How Trustworthy is the Bible? (1) Written by Cornelis Pronk

Under contract with Oxford University Press Karen Bennett Cornell University

R. G. Collingwood, An Essay on Metaphysics, Clarendon Press, Oxford p : the term cause has at least three different senses:

The CopernicanRevolution

Certainty, Necessity, and Knowledge in Hume s Treatise

Kent Academic Repository

Sociology 475: Classical Sociological Theory. MWF 2:25-3:15, 6228 Social Science

Lecture 12 Deontology. Onora O Neill A Simplified Account of Kant s Ethics

Tom Conway, Colorado State University, Department of English Spring 2015 Context: Assignment 2: Sustainable Spaceship Argument Overview sustainably

Hello again. Today we re gonna continue our discussions of Kant s ethics.

Computer Ethics. Normative Ethics and Normative Argumentation. Viola Schiaffonati October 10 th 2017

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY FALL 2014 COURSE DESCRIPTIONS

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

RS 200A: Proseminar in the History and Theory of Religion

Kevin Scharp, Replacing Truth, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013, At 300-some pages, with narrow margins and small print, the work

1/9. The Second Analogy (1)

EPISTEMOLOGY for DUMMIES

Honours Programme in Philosophy

1/12. The A Paralogisms

The way we convince people is generally to refer to sufficiently many things that they already know are correct.

MEDITATIONS ON THE FIRST PHILOSOPHY: THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

METHODENSTREIT WHY CARL MENGER WAS, AND IS, RIGHT

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract

World Religions. These subject guidelines should be read in conjunction with the Introduction, Outline and Details all essays sections of this guide.

Computer Ethics. Normative Ethics Ethical Theories. Viola Schiaffonati October 4 th 2018

Playing Chamber Music at a Rock Festival? The Social Construction of Reality in US Sociology. PD Dr. Silke Steets

PHILOSOPHY IM 25 SYLLABUS IM SYLLABUS (2019)

Gives users access to a comprehensive database comprising over a century of Nietzsche research.

Story Versus Essay: The Particular Feud of Universal Virtue. As Plato once cogitated, If particulars are to have meaning, there must be universals.

Thirty - Eight Ways to Win an Argument from Schopenhauer's "The Art of Controversy"...per fas et nefas :-)

Lecture Notes on Classical Logic

Religious Instruction, Religious Studies and Religious Education

CLASSICAL SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY Sociology 475

ARE YOU READY? Lecture 2 Loss of Truth

Honors Ethics Oral Presentations: Instructions

Hume s Missing Shade of Blue as a Possible Key. to Certainty in Geometry

Courses providing assessment data PHL 202. Semester/Year

Unit 1 Philosophy of Education: Introduction INTRODUCTION

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

2013 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved. 1

New people and a new type of communication Lyudmila A. Markova, Russian Academy of Sciences

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Monday 4:15 6:00; Wednesday 1-3; Thursday 2-3

The midterm will be held in class two weeks from today, on Thursday, October 9. It will be worth 20% of your grade.

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Peter Bornedal, General Lecture, 203. Copyright (C) by P. Bornedal

Christ-Centered Critical Thinking. Lesson 6: Evaluating Thinking

Reply to Florio and Shapiro

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Transcription:

KANT ON THE BEGINNINGS OF HUMAN HISTORY - CONJECTURES BY A SOCIOLOGIST by Richard Swedberg German Studies Colloquium on Immanuel Kant, Conjectures on the Beginning of Human History, Cornell University, November 11, 2006 1

2 When Peter Gilgen asked me to participate in this colloquium on Kant s Conjectures on the Beginning of Human History (1786), he referred to the fact that I am a sociologist; and that adding the perspective of sociology to this colloquium might be interesting for the audience. After thinking for a while, I realized (but did not tell Peter!) that the reason I was happy to participate was precisely because the topic of the colloquium did NOT deal with sociology. This impression was increased when I started to investigate what was meant by the term conjecture (as Kant s Mutmassung is usually translated). A conjecture, according to the main interpretation of this term (in The Oxford English Dictionary), is defined as follows: throwing or casting together, a conclusion derived from comparison of facts, an inference, conclusion, guess, etc. This definition delighted me: something that could be a conclusion and a guess was surely worth anybody s attention. What a nice contrast to sociology with its demand for testable hypotheses, good data sets, a rigorous presentation of facts, and so on! The more I read about conjecture in The Oxford English Dictionary, the better it became: As a verb, conjecture could mean to conclude, infer, or judge, from appearance or probabilities, and especially the equation of appearance with probability cheered me up. Conjecture could also mean to form an opinion or supposition as to facts on grounds admittedly insufficient; to guess, surmise; to propose a conjecture in textual or historical criticism, etc. What attracted me again was this idea of forming an idea of thinking based on grounds [that were] admittedly insufficient. Jeremy Bentham was cited in OED as using the expression a conjecturist (a term that sounded better than the more common conjecturor ); and I got an immediate desire to learn whatever it took to be a conjecturist. The examples in OED were all very old; and it was clear that conjecture, as a noun or a verb, belonged primarily to the past. A number of obscure and hard or impossible to understand quotations littered the article in OED. Some of these had a distinctly poetic tone to them, such as two Shakesperian quotes. In the prologue to Henry IV, one can read: Now entertain conieucture of a time When weeping Murmer fills the

3 Universe. Much Ado About Nothing contains a more whimsical line: And on my eyelids shall Coniecture hang, To turn all beauty into thoughts of harme. What I found attractive about the idea of conjectures, in all brevity, was that it seems to represent a form of thinking that has been forgotten - but is perhaps worth resurrecting. As a method, it does not meet the demands of proof, logic, reason and so on, that good thinking should do, according to accepted criteria. But nonetheless, it is a form of thought that leads to a result which, after all, is what good thinking should do. It is also a type of thinking that is playful and whimsical and invites to jokes all qualities that characterize Kant s little piece, Conjectures on the Beginnings of Human History. But let me now stop for a moment and honor my commitment to Peter to introduce a bit of sociology into all of this (and I will then return to my concern with conjecturing as a method of thinking). Sociologists have been deeply influenced by the work of Kant, mainly at the beginning of the discipline. The three fathers of sociology modern academic sociology was created at the end of the 19 th century and the beginning of the 20th century were all influenced by the work of Kant. This means Emile Durkheim, Georg Simmel and Max Weber. Durkheim was as a young man profoundly influenced by neo-kantian philosopher Renouvier. Georg Simmel, who saw himself primarily as a philosopher (and not a sociologist), was similarly influenced by neo-kantianism and wrote several volumes on Kant in this capacity. Max Weber was a neo-kantian as well, especially close to Henrich Rickert and the the so-called Baden or Southwestern School of neo-kantianism. How did the classics make use of Kant s ideas? In all brevity as follows: Emile Durkheim insisted that human beings could not know reality directly, but always perceived it through representations a position clearly inspired by Kant. What made Durkheim s claim sociological, was that these representations are collective in nature ( collective representations as they are known). Georg Simmel often worked with the concepts of form and content in his sociology. In a well-known theoretical essay called How is Society Possible? he also argues that just as the mind produces nature through categories in the mind, so is society created, through social categories that human beings share.

4 And Max Weber claims that the humans always invest their actions with meaning a position clearly influenced by Kant s work. When these actions are oriented to others, you get sociology (which Weber defines as the study of social action). Modern sociologists do not read Kant or refer to his work. But they do use ideas that build on Kant, for example in the theory of the social construction of reality. The degrees of separation are four in this case: Berger and Luckman formulated the idea of social construction of reality, and they were students of Alfred Schutz who was a student of Weber, who in his turn was a student of Kant. Before finishing this brief account of sociology and Kant, let me also add that modern sociologists have tried to get at Kant s ideas (as well as the ideas of other philosophers) with the help of networks. Especially Randall Collins has been active in this enterprise; and his analysis is to be found in a book called The Sociology of Philosophies: A Global Theory of Intellectual Change (1998). This work represents the best introduction to the network approach to philosophy and Kant. Let me now (and much too abruptly!) return to Kant s piece on the conjectures on the beginnings of human history; and to the notion that conjecture represents a special form of thinking, well worth resurrecting and knowing more about. Let me again reiterate that the reason for taking this task seriously (but not so seriously, as to destroy the playful spirit of conjecturing) is that this conjecturing is a form of thought that leads to serious and important results. Note that Kant starts out with the quasi-absurd idea of using the Bible as a source of human history but ends up with some very serious ethical ideas about the way for the individual to behave, in accordance to reason. Kant argues that there are certain things that are, as he puts it, discoverable by conjectural means. Kant makes clear that this way of proceeding must not be seen as a (in his words) serious activity, and that it only represents a healthy mental recreation - or a journey on the wings of imagination (in his most poetic description). But there is more to the method of conjecturing than so, according to Kant. One can, for example, go too far and indulge, as Kant puts it, in wild conjectures. What exactly wild means in this context is not clear. But just as there is a lower limit, so to speak, to the method of conjecturing, so there is apparently also an upper limit as well.

5 Conjecturing does not mean, for example, to wildly guess but to guess in a reasonable way. What then characterizes conjecturing beyond these descriptions by Kant, which represent pretty much all that he has to say about conjecturing (and which can all be found on the first few pages of his article)? Let me start out by noting that Kant is engaging in what we may term a pure type of conjecturing drawing exclusively on conjectures, and not just using them as an additional form of thinking or technique. In the opening lines of the article Kant indicates what the conventional use of drawing on conjectures is, and then goes on to say that he wants to go beyond this use. The conventional use is when you already have quite a bit of facts or knowledge, and need to fill in the gaps, something that allows us, according to Kant, to discover things with reasonable certainty (as he puts it) and to add to making things intelligible. But what Kant himself wants to explore, is what happens when you draw solely on conjectures (as he puts it). This would seem to be and I quote again! little better than drawing up a plan of fiction. But it is better and much better. What does the pure type of conjecturing then look like? There are several elements to an answer. One is clear enough: you have to draw on your reason; you have to think! But you must not just think in any way whatever; and you definitely have to avoid conventional ways of thinking, such as normal forms of logic and arguments based on full knowledge of some phenomena. You have to think, it appears, in a playful manner. Kant s article contains several jokes, even though he has put the best jokes in the footnotes (all these jokes are incidentally about thinking, or not so incidentally perhaps). It would seem, in short, that a conjecturalist would naturally lapse into humor. It would also seem that in order to engage in conjectures, you have to have something to start from; you cannot just start conjecturing from nowhere. In Kant s case, it is the Bible; and one can of course poke fun at this material. But this might well be a mistake; and I would venture that in order to engage in conjectures, you have to find just the right kind of material. What would that material be like? Well, it would seem to have the following two qualities: it cannot be so tight or dense that it makes the mind switch into some rigorous

6 form of thinking. But neither can it be so uninspiring that it does not lend itself to conjectures. In brief, it has to have the quality to inspire conjectures. What such a quality is like, is not so obvious; and it may well have more to do with the result than than with some formal qualities (or what is evident at first sight). The same goes for conjecturing as a whole and here comes what I consider to be the most interesting and central fact about conjecturing as a method. It is a method that is mainly valid for the results is produces, not for the formal qualities it displays in getting to these results, as is the case with logical forms of thinking. There is also something else about these results of conjecturing that is interesting, to my mind. This is that they all seem to be characterized, to some degree, by conflict, contradiction or something that simply does not add up, according to formal logic. Here are some examples: Inequality is (and I quote) an abundant source of so much evil but also of everything good. The risk of war is the only thing which keeps despotism in check. The history of nature begins with goodness but the history of freedom begins with evil. And more daringly! the element of refusal between men and women may be linked to love, and the use of the fig leaf linked to reason!!! Some of Kant s examples are quite sociological in nature and could be used in SOC 101. Introduction to Sociology. This goes, for example, for the argument that certain problems in modern society are caused by the disconnection of sexual maturity (which takes place at puberty) from that of social maturity (which takes place about ten years later; and even later, if the person wants to be an academic). The idea that threat of war undoes despotism is equally sociological in nature. Indeed, Max Weber would later use the same example in Economy and Society. Weber contrasts China, where the emperor was in a position to control everything, with Europe, which consisted of many small states. By competeting with one another, these small states opened up the space for the bourgeoisie and for bourgeois freedoms to emerge and for despotism to be kept in check. What makes some of Kant s examples sociological is that they deal with society; and Kant uses terms such as civil society and social classes in his article, which are sociological enough. But what makes them into good sociology is something else and

7 harder to pinpoint. I would say that it resides in the acute sense for contradictions that Kant has, and which in some cases are reminiscent of Mandeville s paradoxes along the lines of private vices and public benefits. At one point in his essay Kant refers to restless reason, and this is a good expression for the type of mind that the conjecturalist has. At another point Kant refers to uncertainty, and that is another quality that the conjecturalist should be open to. More generally, it seems to me that the method of conjectures is an excellent tool for laying bare some of the ambiguity and contradictions that are central to human and social existence. Normal reasoning, and more formal types of logic, must not be seen as excluded from the exercises that the conjecturalist engages in but (as the example of Max Weber shows) they may come in at a later stage of the development, when you have to pin down exactly what it is that causes something, and, of course, also when you have to present the results of your work to a thinking audience. But to state the case for the method of conjectures (and I will end on this note): at an early stage of thinking, before all the evidence has been gathered and the logic has been fixed (and, I should add sad to say - the jokes have been eliminated), you may well need conjectures, and you may well need to be a bit of a conjecturalist if you want to produce something worthwhile.