The Coherence of Kant s Synthetic A Priori

Similar documents
A Priori Knowledge: Analytic? Synthetic A Priori (again) Is All A Priori Knowledge Analytic?

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

Kant s Critique of Pure Reason1 (Critique) was published in For. Learning to Count Again: On Arithmetical Knowledge in Kant s Prolegomena

Kant s Freedom and Transcendental Idealism

Immanuel Kant, Analytic and Synthetic. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics Preface and Preamble

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

The CopernicanRevolution

WHAT IS HUME S FORK? Certainty does not exist in science.

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

In The California Undergraduate Philosophy Review, vol. 1, pp Fresno, CA: California State University, Fresno.

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

1/5. The Critique of Theology

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

Philosophy 3100: Ethical Theory

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Lecture 4: Transcendental idealism and transcendental arguments

Kant s Transcendental Exposition of Space and Time in the Transcendental Aesthetic : A Critique

TWO CONCEPTIONS OF THE SYNTHETIC A PRIORI. Marian David Notre Dame University

1/9. The First Analogy

Dumitrescu Bogdan Andrei - The incompatibility of analytic statements with Quine s universal revisability

Kant s Misrepresentations of Hume s Philosophy of Mathematics in the Prolegomena

Accessing the Moral Law through Feeling

A Defence of Kantian Synthetic-Analytic Distinction

Excerpt from J. Garvey, The Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books (Continuum, 2007): Immanuel Kant s Critique of Pure Reason

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first.

Varieties of Apriority

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

SWINBURNE ON THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA. CAN SUPERVENIENCE SAVE HIM?

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2014

PH 1000 Introduction to Philosophy, or PH 1001 Practical Reasoning

5 A Modal Version of the

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 7 : E P I S T E M O L O G Y - K A N T

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2011

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

Class 4 - The Myth of the Given

4/30/2010 cforum :: Moderator Control Panel

Class #9: Kant Our in class discussion of these notes will be lamentably abbreviated, focused on the first three sections.

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 7 : E P I S T E M O L O G Y - K A N T

Kant and his Successors

Overview. Is there a priori knowledge? No: Mill, Quine. Is there synthetic a priori knowledge? Yes: faculty of a priori intuition (Rationalism, Kant)

FIL 4600/10/20: KANT S CRITIQUE AND CRITICAL METAPHYSICS

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphsics [Selection] Immanuel Kant

Absolute Totality, Causality, and Quantum: The Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason. Kazuhiko Yamamoto, Kyushu University, Japan

PRACTICAL REASONING. Bart Streumer

1/12. The A Paralogisms

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

Is Kant's Account of Free Will Coherent?

Logical Mistakes, Logical Aliens, and the Laws of Kant's Pure General Logic Chicago February 21 st 2018 Tyke Nunez

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Ever since W. V. O. Quine wrote his famous Two Dogmas of

CHAPTER III KANT S APPROACH TO A PRIORI AND A POSTERIORI

Some remarks regarding the regularity model of cause in Hume and Kant

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010).

The Copernican Shift and Theory of Knowledge in Immanuel Kant and Edmund Husserl.

Course Description and Objectives:

Hume, skepticism, and the search for foundations

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Immanuel Kant. Great German philosophers whose influence was and continues to be immense; born in Konigsberg East Prussia, in 1724, died there in 1804

PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE OVERVIEW FREGE JONNY MCINTOSH 1. FREGE'S CONCEPTION OF LOGIC

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

Defending A Dogma: Between Grice, Strawson and Quine

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

PH 329: Seminar in Kant Fall 2010 L.M. Jorgensen

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Absolute Totality, Causality, and Quantum: The Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason

Phil/Ling 375: Meaning and Mind [Handout #10]

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

Kant On The A Priority of Space: A Critique Arjun Sawhney - The University of Toronto pp. 4-7

Analyticity, Reductionism, and Semantic Holism. The verification theory is an empirical theory of meaning which asserts that the meaning of a

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Modern Philosophy II

Online version of this review can be found at:

Quine on Holism and Underdetermination

Some Notes Toward a Genealogy of Existential Philosophy Robert Burch

An Empiricist Theory of Knowledge Bruce Aune

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

Transcription:

The Coherence of Kant s Synthetic A Priori Simon Marcus October 2009 Is there synthetic a priori knowledge? The question can be rephrased as Sellars puts it: Are there any universal propositions which, though they are not true by virtue of the meaning of their terms, hold of all possible objects of experience? 1 Kant s project is immense; it is that of answering the question affirmatively in virtue of the dependence between us, our cognitive powers or our language, and the world of our experience. 2 It would not be misleading to characterise the synthetic a priori as the cornerstone in the epistemic framework of Kant s metaphysic. Central to Kant s argument is the appearance of the synthetic a priori in mathematics. As one may expect of a revolutionary thesis, Kant s doctrine has its detractors it has done since the publication of the first edition of the Critique. In this paper, I will explicate the concept of the synthetic a priori, focusing predominantly on definition and application in mathematics, and will in turn evaluate some of the claims of Kant s critics. Having the benefit of considering the successes and inadequacies of both rationalism and empiricism, 3 Kant concludes that metaphysics has until now 4 remained in such a vacillating state of uncertainty and contradictions. 5 He contends that our metaphysical woes derive from epistemic oversight, and presents the synthetic a priori as a beacon. Some justification is of course required, as this conception (although familiar in current philosophy thanks to Kant) represents two epistemic concepts often thought to be in tension with each other. I will briefly consider first Kant s concept of the a priori, and then turn to the novel distinction between synthetic and analytic judgments. 1 Sellars, W. (1953). Is There a Synthetic a Priori? Philosophy of Science, 20 (2), p123 2 Bird, G. (2006). Kant's Analytic Apparatus. In G. Bird (Ed.), A Companion to Kant. Oxford: Blackwell, p129, emphasis in the original 3 Scruton (2002): It was Kant s principal contribution to show that the choice between empiricism and rationalism is unreal, that each philosophy is equally mistaken, and that the only conceivable metaphysics that could commend itself to a reasonable being must be both empiricist and rationalist at once. 4 Buroker, J. V. (2006): It is no exaggeration to say that the precise motivation for Kant s Copernican revolution is his conviction that no predecessor had explicitly recognized this kind of knowledge. 5 Kant, I. (2000). Critique of Pure Reason. (P. Guyer, & A. Wood, Eds.) Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, B19. (Hereafter referred to as CPR.)

Kant argues that we require a priori knowledge because reason, the faculty by which we wish to do metaphysics, desires knowledge of universals and necessity and is not satisfied by knowledge of mere particulars. 6 A priori knowledge is contrasted with empirical knowledge, in that it does not depend for its justification on experience. Kant proleptically spells out the relationship that a priori knowledge bears to experience when he notes that although all our cognition commences with experience, yet it does not on that account all arise from experience. 7 Kant here is at pains to demarcate the scope of this dependence: although all cognition is temporally dependent on experience, it does not follow that it is logically dependent on it. 8 Thus, while it is true that I would never have known that (a) all bachelors are unmarried if I had never been born (i.e. had no experiences), the truth of (a) does not depend logically on my (or anyone s) experience. Let us turn now to the analytic-synthetic distinction. Regarding analytic cognitions, Kant suggests that they are judgments of clarification, 9 that is, they do nothing more than represent clearly and assert as belonging to it, what was already really thought and contained in the given concept. 10 This squares quite well with the way we frequently describe analytic cognitions as trivial, though Kant couches the idea in terms of covert containment of concepts 11 not a notion typically endorsed today. Kant appears at first glance to be committed to the idea that only statements in subject-predicate form can be analytic. We naturally would wish to repudiate this narrow conception, since we think that (e.g.) conditional statements like if A is longer than B, and B is longer than C, then A is longer than C are analytic. 12 However Kant does occasionally seem to concede that a non subject- 6 C.f. CPR A1, and B4 necessity and strict universality are therefore secure indications of an a priori cognition. It will do here to recognise that we typically distinguish the metaphysical role of necessity and the epistemic (justification) role of the a priori. Kant sees these as connected, as Hanna (2004) notes: Kant s idea, by sharp contrast, is that semantic, epistemic, and metaphysical considerations cannot be wholly disentangled from one another and are ultimately fused in the more basic and comprehensive notion of cognition or objective mental representation (p246). 7 CPR, B1, emphasis in the original 8 Buroker, J. V. (2006), p27 9 CPR, B11 10 Kant, I. (1790). On a Discovery whereby Any New Critique of Pure Reason Is to Be Made Superfluous by an Older One. In H. Allison, & P. Heath (Eds.), Theoretical Philosophy after 1781 (2002 ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 8:228, emphasis in the original 11 In Kant s words, a statement A is B is analytic where the the predicate B belongs to the subject A as something that is (covertly) contained in this concept A. (CPR, B10) 12 Cf. Pap, A. (1950). Logic and the Synthetic A Priori. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 10 (4), p501 1

predicate proposition could be analytic 13 as in: that equals added to or subtracted from equals give an equal are analytic propositions. 14 Synthetic judgments, on the other hand, extend our knowledge. They are statements of amplification (rather than clarification ) in that they add to the concept of the subject a predicate that was not thought in it at all. 15 Kant here provides an example to evoke the distinction. If I say: All bodies are extended, then I have not in the least amplified my concept of body, but have merely resolved it, since extension, although not explicitly said of the former concept prior to the judgment, nevertheless was actually thought of it; the judgment is therefore analytic. By contrast, the proposition: Some bodies are heavy, contains something in the predicate that is not actually thought in the general concept of body; it therefore augments my cognition, since it adds something to my concept, and must therefore be called a synthetic judgment. 16 The suggestion here is that since the concept of extension is (covertly) contained in the general concept of a body, while the concept of weight is not so contained, we correctly call the first cognition analytic and the other synthetic. Kant adds a facility to his epistemic apparatus here the principle of contradiction which elicits an alternative assessment of synthetic a priori cognitions. Kant says that All analytic judgments rest entirely on the principle of contradiction and are by their nature a priori cognitions, whether the concepts that serve for their material be empirical or not. For since the predicate of an affirmative analytic judgment is already thought beforehand in the concept of the subject, it cannot be denied of that subject without contradiction. 17 Synthetic judgments, on the other hand depend on principles in addition to that of contradiction; as Buroker puts it, In synthetic judgments, there is no identity between the subject and predicate, and so the principle of non-contradiction is not sufficient for determining their truth values. 18 13 Dicker, G. (2004). Kant s Theory of Knowledge: An Analytical Introduction. New York: Oxford University Press, p12 14 CPR, A164/B204 15 CPR, B11 16 Kant, I. (1783). Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics That Will Be Able to Come Forward as Science. In H. E. Allison, & P. L. Heath (Eds.), Theoretical Philosophy After 1781 (G. Hatfield, Trans., 2002 ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 4:266-267 (Hereafter referred to as Prolegomena.) 17 Prolegomena 4:267 18 Buroker, J. V. (2006), p29 2

There is, however, a difficulty concealed here. Graham Bird points out helpfully that a little reformulation will be of assistance at this point in order to accommodate a conflict between applying the classifications to judgments... or to true judgments. 19 We wish to say that a judgment like some humans are not mammals is an analytic judgment, even though its denial does not yield a contradiction but an analytic truth. This matter can be easily ironed out by suggesting rather that A judgment is analytic (synthetic) if and only if either it or its denial (neither it nor its denial) is a contradiction. 20 With this tool in hand, let us turn to Kant s famed proposal, which appears to have completely escaped the observations of analysts of human reason, 21 namely, that mathematical truths are synthetic and a priori. If we can come up with examples which are incontrovertibly both synthetic and a priori, it will succeed in establishing the coherence of the synthetic a priori. Kant urges us to consider the sum 7 + 5 = 12, and to apply to it the definitions he has expounded. It is plain that it is a priori, for it in no way depends on experience for its justification. 22 I think Kant is successful too in showing that the sum, when considered in terms of covert conceptual containment (CCC), comes out synthetic; that is, upon closer inspection, one finds that the concept of the sum of 7 and 5 contains nothing further than the unification of the two numbers into one, through which by no means is thought what this single number may be that combines the two. 23 Kant notes correctly that this can be seen all the more plainly in the case of somewhat larger numbers: 24 it is a fortiori clear that (e.g.) the concept of 26589 + 56421 is not thought to contain the concept of 83010. But what of the second criterion, the contradiction test (CT)? If we apply CT to the aforementioned sum, we are placed in a difficult position. It seems that supposing that the sum turned out otherwise (say, 7 + 5 = 13) renders the equation incomprehensible, maybe as incomprehensible as trying to imagine a married bachelor. Kant at this point urges upon us a principle to resolve our confusion, similar to that distinction between truths 19 Bird, G. (2006), p127 20 Bird, G. (2006), p128 21 Prolegomena 4:268 22 Prolegomena 4:268, Properly mathematical propositions are always a priori and not empirical judgments, because they carry necessity with them, which cannot be taken from experience. But if this will not be granted me, very well, I will restrict my proposition to pure mathematics, the concept of which already conveys that it contains not empirical but only pure cognition a priori. 23 Prolegomena 4:268, CPR B15 24 Prolegomena 4:269 CPR B16 3

that arise in and those that depend on experience. In considering CT, Kant suggests that we distinguish those inferences that merely accord with CT and those which can be derived through CT. The inferences of mathematics, according to Kant, certainly all proceed in accordance with the principle of contradiction (which, by nature, is required of any apodictic certainty). 25 Yet Kant argues that mathematics falls on the synthetic side of this division: for a synthetic proposition can of course be discerned in accordance with the principle of contradiction, but only insofar as another synthetic propositions is presupposed from which the first can be deduced, never however in itself. 26 The last point has come under some attack, notably from Ayer, since Kant does not ever show precisely how CT is to be applied successfully to arithmetic, but focuses rather on conceptual containment (CCC). Ayer suggests that these two tests can produce conflicting results that is, e.g., something could turn out to be synthetic a priori according to CCC but analytic according to CT. Ayer says But, in fact, a proposition which is synthetic according to the former criterion may very well be analytic according to the latter... one can think of the sum of seven and five without necessarily thinking of twelve, [but] it by no means follows that the proposition "7 + 5 = 12" can be denied without self-contradiction. 27 I think, however, that Ayer has misinterpreted Kant s distinction, and that his comments incline towards a conflation of judgments which accord with the principle of contradiction and those which are derived through the principle of contradiction. Furthermore, I wish to argue that Kant could contend successfully that CCC entails CT. 28 I will use examples to illustrate my contentions. It is plain that the denial of an analytic truth like all bachelors are unmarried results in a contradiction. Why? Because we have the relevantly conflicting concepts immediately in mind. That is, some unmarried men are married men is contradictory at face value, because the concepts stand in perfect opposition to each other: we have [U and not-u], generating a contradiction. However, in considering the sum 26589 + 56421, we are simply not presented with the concept 83010, covertly or otherwise. But if we are not presented with such a concept, then though it is indeed false to deny the equation, it is just not a contradiction. It is correct to advance, then 25 Prolegomena 4:268, CPR B14 26 Prolegomena 4:268, CPR B14 27 Ayer, A. (1952). Language, Truth, and Logic. New York: Dover Publications, p78 28 Bird, G. (2006), p128, also adheres to this formulation. 4

that genuine contradiction arises only where the concepts in the cognition have opposing truth values; in other words, we can conclude that a cognition which comes out as synthetic a priori on CCC will necessarily come out as synthetic a priori on CT. As alluded to earlier, I have attempted to satisfy the question Is Kant s conception of synthetic a priori propositions defensible? by showing that we in fact have instances of such propositions what is actual is of course possible. So, by way of conclusion, I will evaluate two additional mathematical examples which count as synthetic a priori cognitions on Kant s terms. The first is Kant s, proposing that the straight line between two points is the shortest 29 is a synthetic a priori proposition. How does it fare with CCC and CT? Well, on CCC it is clear that the concept of a straight line does not contain anything of magnitude, 30 that is, we cannot by considering the concepts alone derive the concept of the shortest distance. And by this token since wholly distinct concepts figure in the subject and predicate terms we see that the denial of the statement does not result in contradiction. So on CT it is similarly synthetic a priori. A neat example from the proliferation of literature on the subject in the fifties comes from Langford, who proposes that any cube has twelve edges is both synthetic and a priori. 31 Without labouring the point, it should be clear that the concept solid whose faces were squares 32 does not contain the concept of having twelve edges. And similarly (indeed consequently), while patently false to be sure, it is not contradictory to suppose otherwise. While Kant s project proceeds into murkier territories hereafter, I contend that his groundwork that of establishing the coherence of synthetic a priori cognitions provides a solid foundation for setting metaphysics along the secure course of a science. 33 29 Prolegomena 4:269, CPR B16 30 Prolegomena 4:269 31 Langford, C. (1949). A Proof That Synthetic A Priori Propositions Exist. The Journal of Philosophy, 46 (1), p21 32 Langford, C. (1949), p22 33 CPR, Bxiv 5

Bibliography Ayer, A. (1952). Language, Truth, and Logic. New York: Dover Publications. Bird, G. (2006). Kant's Analytic Apparatus. In G. Bird (Ed.), A Companion to Kant. Oxford: Blackwell. Buroker, J. V. (2006). Kant s Critique of Pure Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Copi, I. M. (1949). Modern Logic and the Synthetic A Priori. The Journal of Philosophy, 46 (8), 243-245. Davidson, D. (2001). Mental Events. In Essays on Actions and Events (2nd ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press - Oxford. Dicker, G. (2004). Kant s Theory of Knowledge: An Analytical Introduction. New York: Oxford University Press. Hanna, R. (2004). Kant and the Foundations of Analytic Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hatfield, G. (2002). Translator's Introduction to Kant's 'The Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics'. In I. Kant, Theoretical Philosophy After 1781. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hodgson, S. H. (1877). Kant's Analytic and Synthetic Judgments, and his question, How synthetic a priori judgments are possible. Mind, 2 (5), 118-122. Kant, I. (2000). Critique of Pure Reason. (P. Guyer, & A. Wood, Eds.) Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kant, I. (1790). On a Discovery whereby Any New Critique of Pure Reason Is to Be Made Superfluous by an Older One. In H. Allison, & P. Heath (Eds.), Theoretical Philosophy After 1781 (2002 ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kant, I. (1783). Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics That Will Be Able to Come Forward as Science. In H. E. Allison, & P. L. Heath (Eds.), Theoretical Philosophy After 1781 (G. Hatfield, Trans., 2002 ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Langford, C. (1949). A Proof That Synthetic A Priori Propositions Exist. The Journal of Philosophy, 46 (1), 20-24. Miller, A. (2007). Sense and verificationism: Logical positivism. In Philosophy of Language (2nd ed.). Oxford: Routledge. Pap, A. (1950). Logic and the Synthetic A Priori. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 10 (4), 500-514. Quine, W. (1951). Two Dogmas of Empiricism. The Philosophical Review, 60 (1), 20-43. Scruton, R. (2002). A Short History of Modern Philosophy (2nd ed.). New York: Routledge. 6

Sellars, W. (1953). Is There a Synthetic a Priori? Philosophy of Science, 20 (2), 121-138. Senderowicz, Y. M. (2005). The Coherence of Kant's Transcendental Idealism. The Netherlands: Springer. Watkins, E. (2005). Kant and the Metaphysics of Causality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 7