Plato s Euthyphro. G. J. Mattey. Winter, 2006 / Philosophy 1. Our first text will be from Plato and centered around his teacher Socrates ( BC).

Similar documents
Plato s Euthyphro. G. J. Mattey. Spring, 2017 / Philosophy 1. Our first text will be from Plato and centered around his teacher Socrates ( BC).

01. Pre-Socratic Cosmology and Plato I. Basic Issues

latter case, if we offer different concepts by which to define piety, we risk no longer talking about piety. I.e., the forms are one and all

GREAT PHILOSOPHERS series TRINITY COLLEGE DUBLIN

Early Greek Philosophy

Sophie s World. Chapter 4 The Natural Philosophers

HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY & PHILOSOPHERS. Presocratics-Aristotle

Shanghai Jiao Tong University. PI913 History of Ancient Greek Philosophy

DR. LEONARD PEIKOFF. Lecture 2 THE FIRST ANSWERS AND THEIR CLIMAX: THE TRIUMPH OF THE METAPHYSICS OF TWO WORLDS

Science. January 27, 2016

Any Philosophy that can be put in a nut shell belongs in one. - Hillary Putnam. Course Description

Lesson Plans 12: Argument and Piety in the Euthyphro e Civic Knowledge Project: Winning Words

THALES. The Project of Pre-Socratic Philosophy. The arch! is WATER. Why did Thales posit WATER as the arch!? PRE-SOCRATIC - Lecture Notes

CLAS 201 (Philosophy)

Euthyphro s Dilemma. What Could (a) God Have To Do With Morality?

3. So, what-is-not cannot be the reason for saying that what-is was, or will be [i.e., what what-is grew out of or will grow into].

Philosophy Quiz 01 Introduction

Lecture I.2: The PreSocratics (cont d)

SOCRATES, PIETY, AND NOMINALISM. love is one of the most well known in the history of philosophy. Yet some fundamental

Daniel W. Graham. Explaining the Cosmos. The Ionian Tradition of Scientific Philosophy. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton UP p.

Plato's Parmenides and the Dilemma of Participation

TB_02_01_Socrates: A Model for Humanity, Remember, LO_2.1

Overview Plato Socrates Phaedo Summary. Plato: Phaedo Jan. 31 Feb. 5, 2014

INTRODUCTION TO PRESOCRATICS

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 3 : N A T U R E O F R E A L I T Y

Development of Thought. The word "philosophy" comes from the Ancient Greek philosophia, which

Aristotle and Aquinas

Edinburgh Research Explorer

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 3

Introduction to Philosophy Practice Exam One. True or False A = True, B= False

From Being to Energy-Being: An Emerging Metaphysical Macroparadigm Shift in Western Philosophy. Preface

Philosophy and the art of questioning - Plato s Euthyphro

Euthyphro 1. by Plato. Persons of the Dialogue: SOCRATES EUTHYPHRO

Socrates ( BC) The unexamined life is not worth living

Ancient Philosophy. Instructor: Jason Sheley

Reading Euthyphro Plato as a literary artist

Topics and Posterior Analytics. Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey

Socrates Meets Jesus

Divine command theory

Socratic and Platonic Ethics

Contents. Introduction 8

INTRODUCTION. Historical perspectives of Naturalism

PHILOSOPHY 101 FROM PLATO AND SOCRATES TO ETHICS AND METAPHYSICS, AN ESSENTIAL PRIMER ON THE HISTORY OF THOUGHT

The Charges Against Socrates

TABLE OF CONTENTS. A. "The Way The World Really Is" 46 B. The First Philosophers: The "Turning Point of Civilization" 47

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

the PRE-SOCRATIC PHILOSOPHERS

Presocratics By James Warren Acumen, Pp. v ISBN: Pbk

Before the Court House

Plato's Doctrine Of Forms: Modern Misunderstandings

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institution of Technology, Madras

Ancient Greek Philosophy

Plato's Epistemology PHIL October Introduction

Socrates was born around 470/469 BC in Alopeke, a suburb of Athens but, located outside the wall, and belonged to the tribe Antiochis.

PLATO: PLATO CRITICIZES HIS OWN THEORY OF FORMS, AND THEN ARGUES FOR THE FORMS NONETHELESS (PARMENIDES)

Replies to Hasker and Zimmerman. Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, I.

1/13. Locke on Power

Dominican School of Philosophy and Theology PH/HS 1050 History of Philosophy: Ancient

Philosophy exit exam (Logic: 1-10; Ancient: 11-20; Modern: 21-30; Ethics: 31-40; M&E: 41-50)

Raphael The School of Athens. Hello Plato

The earliest Grecian philosophers confined themselves to the study of the external world,

Lecture 3 Parmenides and Anaxagoras

Today we turn to the work of one of the most important, and also most difficult, of philosophers: Immanuel Kant.

DEITY (PART II) * CHAPTER 8. Concepts of God/gods:

Ancient Greek Philosophy. Instructor: Dr. Jason Sheley

Downloaded by [stanbul ehir Üniversitesi] at 15:34 18 October 2012

Realism and anti-realism. University of London Philosophy B.A. Intercollegiate Lectures Logic and Metaphysics José Zalabardo Autumn 2009

PLATO. Five Dialogues. Second Edition. Euthyphro Apology Crito Meno Phaedo. Translated by G. M. A. GRUBE. Revised by JOHN M.

Does the Third Man Argument refute the theory of forms?

THE PRESOCRATIC PHILOSOPHERS AND SOCRATES

What is Freedom? Should Socrates be Set Free? Plato s Crito

THE MENO by Plato Written in approximately 380 B.C.

A Re-examination and Reinterpretation of the Records of the Presocratics and Earlier from an ATR (Argumentative Theory of Reason) Perspective

Can Excellence Be Taught?

Lists in the Meno and the Euthyphro

4AANA001 Greek Philosophy I Syllabus Academic year 2014/15

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT FALL SEMESTER 2009 COURSE OFFERINGS

Introduction to Philosophy

The Origins of Science

What conditions does Plato expect a good definition to meet? Is he right to impose them?

Shanghai Jiao Tong University. PI913 History of Ancient Greek Philosophy

Adapted from The Academic Essay: A Brief Anatomy, for the Writing Center at Harvard University by Gordon Harvey. Counter-Argument

Lecture 4. Athens and the Sophists 15/09/2010. Today s Lecture

DISPOSITIONS OF DESIRE NEEDED IN THE PURSUIT OF WISDOM REMOTE DISPOSITION: LOVE OF THE BEAUTIFUL

Honors Ethics Oral Presentations: Instructions

On the Object of Philosophy: from Being to Reality

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

Shanghai Jiao Tong University. History of Ancient Greek Philosophy

UNDERGRADUATE STUDIES CERTIFICATE IN PHILOSOPHY (CERTIFICATES)

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

Early Russell on Philosophical Grammar

QUESTION 19. God s Will

The Argument To The Hypotheses In Parmenides

H: Whatever name you give something is its right name, and you can change it, just as we change the names of our slaves.

By J. Alexander Rutherford. Part one sets the roles, relationships, and begins the discussion with a consideration

C. Exam #1 comments on difficult spots; if you have questions about this, please let me know. D. Discussion of extra credit opportunities

Philosophies without ontology

Relative and Absolute Truth in Greek Philosophy

One previous course in philosophy, or the permission of the instructor.

Illustration from Figures de la Bible (1728) 10/25/2012 1

Transcription:

Plato s Euthyphro G. J. Mattey Winter, 2006 / Philosophy 1 The First Principle Our first text will be from Plato and centered around his teacher Socrates (469-399 BC). Before Socrates (and during his life) the main outlines of philosophical inquiry had begun to take shape. The main question posed by the pre-socratic philosophers was metaphysical: What is the first principle (arche) of all reality? The question itself can be understood in two main ways: What is the material of which all things are composed? Water (Thales) Air (Anaximenes) Fire (Heraclitus) Solid, shaped atoms (Leucippus, Democritus) What is responsible for the organization of all things? Unity and Plurality Number (Pythagoras) Mind (Anaxagoras) The search for a first principle of all things is at bottom a search for a unified explanation of a plurality of things. An alternative approach, taken by Parmenides, is to deny that there is any plurality at all. According to Parmenides, all that is, is one (metaphysical monism). His student, Zeno of Elea, proposed several famous paradoxes to support Parmenides s monism. 1

Zeno used a distinctive argument form, reductio ad absurdum, that has been widely used by philosophers ever since. Assume that opposite of your view is true. Show that a contradiction or absurdity follows from the assumption. Conclude that the opposite of your view is false, in which case your view is true. Plato and Socrates Most of the writings of Plato (427-347 BC) consist of dialogues between Socrates and various residents of and travelers to Athens. In most of the dialogues, the words of Socrates apparently reflect the thoughts of Plato. One of Plato s chief concerns was with the metaphysical question of the basis of unity among different things. This is the key issue in his early dialogue Euthyphro. The Form We commonly think that distinct objects, acts, etc. (what we will call things ) are of the same kind. George W. Bush, Hillary Clinton, Tiger Woods, are all people. Observing religious holidays, making sacrifices, behaving virtuously, are all pious acts. According to Plato, things fall under the same kind because there is something the same and alike in every one of them. The form is what makes things the kind of things they are. The form is also the model that can be used to determine that a thing falls under a kind. A key task of metaphysics is to give a description of the form of things of various kinds. The Case of Piety One does not describe the form of piety by merely listing pious acts. Any description of the form of piety must at least give a necessary and sufficient condition for an act to be pious: For any act x, if x is pious, then x satisfies the condition (necessary), 2

For any act x, if x satisfies the condition, then x is pious (sufficient). Euthyphro proposes that being loved by the gods is a necessary and sufficient condition for the piety of an act, and being hated by the gods is necessary and sufficient for the impiety of an act. For any act x, x is pious if and only if x is loved by the gods. For any act x, x is impious if and only if x is hated by the gods. A Problem with the Proposal Socrates notes that there is anger and hostility in disagreements between the gods. Euthyphro agrees that the only subjects of disagreement that could provoke such a reaction would be what is: Just or unjust, Good or bad, Beautiful or ugly. If god x thinks that an act is just and god y thinks it is unjust, god x will love it and god y will hate it. Gods in fact disagree over which acts are just. It follows from Euthyphro s conditions that such acts are both pious and impious, which is absurd. So, the conditions given by Euthyphro are not necessary and sufficient for the piety or impiety of an act. A Revised Proposal Euthyphro chooses to give up the claim that being loved by some god is a sufficient condition for being a pious action. His new description of piety is being loved by all the gods. For any act x, x is pious if and only if x is loved by all the gods. Socrates allows that being loved by all the gods is the same and alike in every [pious] action. But this condition is only a quality of pious acts. It is not sufficient to describe the form, because it does not explain what makes a pious act pious. 3

An Explanatory Deficiency Why does Socrates claim that being loved by all the gods does not make a pious act pious? Socrates s argument depends on a general principle: Anything that is loved is loved because of a feature it has that makes it loveable. So, if all the gods love a pious act, it is because there is something about the act that makes it loveable. If being pious is what makes a pious act loveable to all the gods, then the fact that all the gods love it cannot explain why the pious act is pious; rather, it presupposes that the act is pious. So, we must look for some feature of the act other than piety to explain why a pious act is loveable, and hence why the gods love it. In that case, we cannot explain what piety is merely by the quality of pious acts that they are loved by all the gods. What Makes a Pious Act Pious? Following a suggestion of Socrates, Euthyphro takes piety to fall under the more general kind, the just. Piety is the part of the just that concerns the care of the gods. This account of piety remedies the problem with the proposal that what is pious is what is loved by all the gods: It shows what makes a pious act pious, without appealing to piety itself, It explains why all the gods love a pious act. Socrates attempts to refute the account by claiming that the gods cannot be cared for: The gods cannot be benefitted by a pious act, since they cannot be made better, The gods are not served by a pious act, since they need no help in attaining their ends. Socrates s conclusion is that there is no part of the just that concerns the care of the gods, so this attempt to explain what makes a pious act pious fails. 4

A Final Attempt at Accounting for Piety Euthyprho takes a last stab at giving an account of what makes pious acts pious. He proposes that pious acts are acts which are performed on the basis of piety. Piety itself is knowledge of how to give to, and beg from, the gods. Like the last one, this account would show what makes a pious act pious. It would also explain why the gods love a pious act, i.e., the act is loveable because it is performed in the proper way. Objections to the Final Attempt Socrates has two objections to the account of piety as knowledge of how to give to, and beg from, the gods. The first objection is similar in its structure to the objection to the previous account of piety. 1. To give correctly is to satisfy needs. 2. But the gods have no needs to satisfy. 3. So, there is no correct way to give to the gods, and so no knowledge of how to give to the gods. The second objection focuses on what it would be to give to, and beg from, the gods properly. 1. To give to, and beg from, the gods properly is to act in a way that is loved by all the gods. 2. So, a pious act is one which is performed in such a way as is loved by all the gods. 3. But being performed in a way such as is loved by all the gods does not explain what makes a pious act pious. 4. So, being performed based on knowledge of how to give to, and beg from, is not the form of piety. Must the Loved be Loveable? Euthyphro yields to all of Socrates s objections, but he did not have to. He might have rejected Socrates s general principle that something is loved only because of some feature it has that makes it loveable. Thus, he could have held that pious acts are loved by the gods simply because they are inclined to love them. 5

Then the fact that the gods find the acts pleasing can explain why they are pious: that is just what it means to be pious. Socrates might object that the gods would then be guilty of acting arbitrarily by loving something without having a reason for loving it (or even that they could not do so). And Euthyphro might reply that as gods, they do not have to have a reason for doing what they do. 6