Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 5d God

Similar documents
Aquinas Cosmological argument in everyday language

Hume s Critique of Miracles

Betting on God: Pascal, Probability Theory and Theology. nevertheless made surprising contributions to the field of religious philosophy.

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 1b Knowledge

= (value of LEAVE if rain x chance of rain) + (value of LEAVE if dry x chance of dry) = -20 x x.5 = -9

Introductory Matters

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 6a Reasoning

175 Chapter CHAPTER 23: Probability

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7b The World

232 Infinite movement, the point which fills everything, the moment of rest; infinite without quantity, indivisible and infinite.

1/8. Descartes 3: Proofs of the Existence of God

Does God exist? The argument from miracles

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World

Kant and his Successors

approach to God, as was proposed by René Descartes, deists, and some modern

2014 THE BIBLIOGRAPHIA ISSN: Online First: 21 October 2014

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 4b Free Will/Self

Simplicity and Why the Universe Exists

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 2b Mind

Dualism: What s at stake?

How probability begets belief

Contents. How to Use This Book Preface Acknowledgments

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 6b Reasoning

IDHEF Chapter 2 Why Should Anyone Believe Anything At All?

Assessment: Student accomplishment of expected student outcomes will be assessed using the following measures

Philosophy 107: Philosophy of Religion El Camino College Summer, 2016 Section 4173, Online Course

What is Faith? Meanings from the Oxford English Dictionary (1) a set of propositions that one believes. I believe that God exists on faith alone

Suicide. 1. Rationality vs. Morality: Kagan begins by distinguishing between two questions:

William Clifford and William James on sufficient evidence for belief

Today we begin our discussion of the existence of God.

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 3e Free Will

Blaise Pascal

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

EPISTEMOLOGY for DUMMIES

HAS DAVID HOWDEN VINDICATED RICHARD VON MISES S DEFINITION OF PROBABILITY?

The significance of faith proven by decision theory Pascal s wager game is correct and refutes atheism completely

Chapter 2--How Do I Know Whether God Exists?

Well, how are we supposed to know that Jesus performed miracles on earth? Pretty clearly, the answer is: on the basis of testimony.

Kierkegaard is pondering, what it is to be a Christian and to guide one s life by Christian faith.

foundationalism and coherentism are responses to it. I will then prove that, although

! Jumping ahead 2000 years:! Consider the theory of the self.! What am I? What certain knowledge do I have?! Key figure: René Descartes.

Nested Testimony, Nested Probability, and a Defense of Testimonial Reductionism Benjamin Bayer September 2, 2011

NEW YORK CITY COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY THE CITY UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK DIVISION OF LIBERAL ARTS AND GENERAL EDUCATION DEPARTMENT OF SOCIAL SCIENCES

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Do we have knowledge of the external world?

Theories of epistemic justification can be divided into two groups: internalist and

Naturalism and is Opponents

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

Skepticism is True. Abraham Meidan

Philosophy 107: Philosophy of Religion El Camino College Spring, 2017 Section 2664, Room SOCS 205, MW 11:15am-12:40pm

Metaphysics & Consciousness. A talk by Larry Muhlstein

True and Reasonable Faith Theistic Proofs

I. Plato s Republic. II. Descartes Meditations. The Criterion of Clarity and Distinctness and the Existence of God (Third Meditation)

Cosmological Argument

Welcome back to week 2 of this edition of 5pm Church Together.

PL-101: Introduction to Philosophy Fall of 2007, Juniata College Instructor: Xinli Wang

The Rationality of Religious Beliefs

Getting To God. The Basic Evidence For The Truth of Christian Theism. truehorizon.org

Table of x III. Modern Modal Ontological Arguments Norman Malcolm s argument Charles Hartshorne s argument A fly in the ointment? 86

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

The cosmological argument (continued)

CHAPTER 7: RATIONALITY & RELIGIOUS BELIEF

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

OBSTACLES TO HAPPINESS EXTERNAL OBSTACLES INTERNAL OBSTACLES INNER TOOLS FOR HAPPINESS 1. THE TRUTH OF

REPUGNANT ACCURACY. Brian Talbot. Accuracy-first epistemology is an approach to formal epistemology which takes

The Foolishness Of God

Is the Existence of Heaven Compatible with the Existence of Hell? James Cain

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

Five Ways to Prove the Existence of God. From Summa Theologica. St. Thomas Aquinas

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first.

Descartes Meditations

Introduction to Christian Apologetics June 1 st and 8 th

Introduction to Philosophy. Instructor: Jason Sheley

Either God wants to abolish evil and cannot, or he can but does not want to, or he cannot and does not want to, or lastly he can and wants to.

Definitions of Gods of Descartes and Locke

Is this how we decide what to believe? Do I choose a belief system based on what I already want?

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

John Locke. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding

On Breaking the Spell of Irrationality (with treatment of Pascal s Wager) Selmer Bringsjord Are Humans Rational? 11/27/17 version 2 RPI

AN ACTUAL-SEQUENCE THEORY OF PROMOTION

Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory.

Pascal s wager: tracking an intended reader in the structure of the argument 1

Against Coherence: Truth, Probability, and Justification. Erik J. Olsson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xiii, 232.

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Ideas Have Consequences

Engaging Moderns & Postmoderns. Engaging Moderns. The Fine-Tuning Argument. The Fine-Tuning Argument. The Fine-Tuning Argument

A Compatibilist Account of Free Will and Moral Responsibility

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

Descartes to Early Psychology. Phil 255

Our very Sstrange situation

SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5)

some of the questions that Blaise Pascal and John Locke seek to address. The two great

The St. Petersburg paradox & the two envelope paradox

LA Mission College Mark Pursley Fall 2016 Note:

Reasons for Belief Session 1 I Struggle With Doubt. Is That OK?

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action

Transcription:

Think by Simon Blackburn Chapter 5d God

No clickers today. 2 quizzes Wednesday. Don t be late or you will miss the first one! Turn in your Nammour summaries today. No credit for late ones.

According to Peter Millican, David Hume showed us that the mechanistic view of the world provided by science: A. us true insight into the ultimate nature of reality. B. provides no insight into the ultimate nature of reality.

The free will defense Another common strategy for dealing with the problem of evil is to argue as follows. A world in which humans have free will is vastly better than a world in which they do not. So, in order to grant humans freedom, God had to grant them the power to do evil.

Problems with the free will argument There are several basic problems with this argument. The main three are: 1. It is based on an incoherent dualist notion of free will. 2. Most evil is not actually due to human free will. Pestilence, natural disasters, predators, etc., are all part of nature. 3. Even granted free will, why couldn t God at least protect the innocent from people who used their free-will in evil ways?

According to the free will defense A. God granted us free will so that we could do evil. B. Evil is more powerful than freedom. C. Nobody is in a position to judge God s plans. D. In order to give humans free will God had to permit them to cause suffering.

Which of the following is not a criticism of the free will defense: A. There is no way to now whether God gave us free will or not. B. The free will defense is based on dualism, which is incoherent. C. God could still have found ways to protect the innocent from humans exercising their free will. D. In order to give humans free will God had to permit them to cause suffering.

Miracles Many people believe in miracles. There is no universally accepted definition of a miracle, but the core idea is that a miracle is something that is impossible from a scientific perspective. If miracles occur, then it might seem reasonable to attribute them to divine agency. But the real question is whether they actually do occur.

Miracles 2 One problem here is with the idea of something being physically impossible from a scientific perspective. Contemporary science doesn t have much use for the concept of something being physically impossible. Most of the things that we normally think of as being impossible (turning water into wine, walking on water, resurrection, virgin birth, etc.) are extremely improbable, but not physically impossible.

Impossibility vs. Improbability Something that is very improbable at any given time, may still be quite probable given enough time. For any given person winning the state lottery is extremely unlikely. But people win all the time. The winners might call it a miracle, but it s not. (The other day a man shot his wife in the middle of the forehead with a.38 caliber pistol and the bullet came out the back of her head. He then shot himself dead. The woman got up, made herself some tea, and called the police. She is going to be fine.)

One problem with thinking of miracles as events that are impossible from a scientific perspective is: A. No physical event is actually impossible from a scientific perspective. B. This would make every event a miracle. C. This would mean miracles didn t occur before the existence of science. D. It denies the role of God.

No ridicule Before going on, it s important to say here that people who believe they have been on the receiving end of miracles aren t to be ridiculed. Imagine a parent whose child is restored to perfect health after being unconscious at the bottom of a pool for several hours (which has happened). It is almost difficult to understand how such a person could refuse to believe in God s mercy after something like that.

Testimony Still, the philosophical problem is whether we should ever believe that a truly miraculous event occurred, rather than one that is very surprising, but still possible from a scientific point of view. David Hume provided what is perhaps the most famous critique of miracles by asking when it is rational to believe testimony that a miracle occurred. He focuses on testimony because those who believe in the miracles spoken of in the Bible. We never saw them ourselves.

Hume s criterion Hume points out that human beings are highly fallible sources of information. We re often wrong about what we think we have seen. Criminologists, e.g., know that if 10 people are present at the same crime, they will get 10 different accounts of the facts. Psychologists have established that people who express absolute 100% confidence in the truth of what they have seen are correct only about 80% of the time. Hume proposes the following principle for assent to a miracle (p.178) No testimony is sufficient to establish a miracle, unless the testimony itself be of such a kind, that its falsehood would be more miraculous.

Miracles 4 This statement can take a while to process, but Blackburn clarifies it nicely. The basic idea is that when you hear or read a report of a miraculous event- call it M- then you have a choice to make. (1) You can believe M happened as described. (2) You can believe the person reporting M is mistaken. Hume asks us this: Which is more likely (1) that a miracle actually happened or (2) that the person reporting the miracle is mistaken in some way? Hume says it is never miraculous for someone to be mistaken.

Miracle 5 To back up this claim, Hume points out several things that people need to take into account before believing a miracle. 1. Most people really want to believe in miracles, and there is nothing easier to convince people of than things they already want to believe. 2. People really want to be the messengers of miracles. It makes them feel powerful and the center of attention. 3. Almost all religions report miracles of one kind or another. For example, miracles inform Christian beliefs about the significance of Christ s teachings and miracles also inform Islamic beliefs about the significance of Muhammad s teachings. But Christians do not accept Islamic miracles and Muslims do not accept Christian miracles because they are espoused in the service of contrary teachings. The thing to appreciate here is that even people who believe in the miracles of their own religion reject the vast majority of testimony to miracles in the service of other religions.

According to Hume we should believe that a miracle occurred only if: A. We saw it with our own eyes. B. The person reporting it is generally regarded as reliable. C. It would be more of a miracle if the event in question did not occur. D. We actually witnessed the laws of physics being broken.

Pragmaticism The last argument for belief in God is what we call a pragmatic argument. It does not attempt to prove the existence of God, or even to supply evidence for God s existence. Rather, it attempts to show that it is reasonable to believe in God regardless of the fact that we can provide neither proof nor evidence. The proof is due to a famous mathematician, named Pascal. Descartes and Pascal were contemporaries, and in fact had deep disagreements about the status of scientific reasoning and evidence. Pascal was an empiricist, and a pioneer of probability theory, which Descartes rejected vehemently for it s inability to demonstrate any conclusion with certainty. Pascal was also a mystic, and he ultimately abandoned mathematics and science and converted to Christianity as a result of several profound experiences he interpreted as miracles.

Pascal s wager Pascal s argument is not probabilistic in nature, but it is inspired by the reasoning that is typical of probability theory, and specifically uses the language of betting. Pascal points out that when we make decisions under conditions of uncertainty, we must look at all the possible outcomes, and assess them in terms of their value, positive or negative. When deciding whether it is best to believe in God, we have two options: (1) Believe in God; (2) Don t believe in God. There are also two possible states of the world: (1) God exists; (2) God doesn t exist. This means that there are four possible outcomes that can be represented in the following table.

Pascal s Wager 2 God exists God doesn t exist Believe in God Got exists and you believe. Value = + infinity God doesn t exist and you believe Value = 0 Don t believe in God God exists and you don t believe. Value = - infinity God doesn t exist and you don t believe. Value = 0

Pascal s wager 3 Pascal s argument is formulated in terms of Christian belief, which promises eternal bliss for belief and eternal damnation for disbelief. Hence, given God s existence he attaches a value of + infinity to belief and infinity to non belief. Pascal appreciates the fact that, given God s non existence, belief in God may be a net negative, and disbelief a net positive. But he argues that because the amount of time we spend in this world is finite, both the negative and positive values in this case are essentially 0 in comparison to infinity. Pascal s wager then, basically comes down to the claim that with belief you stand to gain everything and lose practically nothing, but with disbelief you stand to lose practically everything and gain practically nothing. So from a practical point of view belief is a no-brainer.

Pascal s wager is best understood as an attempt to A. Prove the existence of God. B. Prove that we should believe in God even though we have no evidence for God s existence. C. Prove that if we believe in God we will experience the benefits of eternal bliss. D. Prove that all past argument for the existence of God are equally right and wrong.

Pascal s wager 4 Many people find Pascal s argument very compelling, but it is actually a very poor argument. It s main problem is that we have no reason to think of our choices in such a limited way. Christianity is just one of many religions you might consider accepting. Suppose you think of it as a choice between Christianity and Islam. Both religions belief in eternal damnation and eternal bliss in connection with their respective views. So, on a very simple reading, deciding to accept Christianity is the same as rejecting Islam. Hence, the positive infinite benefit one receives from choosing the correct religion is balanced by the infinite negative of getting it wrong.

Pascal 5 Of course you still might think that Pascal has given a solid argument for believing in some religion rather than nothing at all. After all, there is no upside to atheism on Pascal s wager. But as Blackburn points out that, too, is not clear. For all we know God is the sort of being who punishes people for basing their religious beliefs on crass, self-interested calculations and rewarding those who do their best to reason toward the truth, even when they come to the wrong conclusions. So while Pascal s wager is predicated on uncertainty about the existence of God, it is based on the completely unjustified assumption that Christianity supplies the only relevant options. Once we see that alternative, contrary beliefs systems are equally strong candidates from the betting perspective, Pascal s calculus implodes.

Faith Fideism is the belief that religion is strictly a matter of faith, and that reasoning really has nothing to do with it. This attitude is appealing in its simplicity, especially after slogging through a bunch of inconclusive arguments for the existence of God. But belief in the absence of any requirement to produce or examine the evidence for or against that belief is incredibly dangerous. It is easy to admire a person s faith when the things they believe in are conducive to our own aims, or at least not hostile to them. But many people practice religions in which they accept on faith that people who do not practice that religion need to die. As Blackburn says pointedly (p.190): "If I check into the Mysterious Mist and come back convinced that God's message is to kill young women, or people with the wrong-colored skins, or people who go to the wrong church, or people who have sex the wrong way, that is not so good." Ultimately no sensible person thinks faith itself is a good thing. You must have faith in the right things, and the only way to determine right from wrong is with the use of reason. Nobody gets a free pass here.