Afraid of the Dark: Nagel and Rationalizing the Fear of Death

Similar documents
The Problem of Identity and Mereological Nihilism. the removal of an assumption of unrestricted mereological composition, and from there a

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Death by Thomas Nagel (1979)

True Empathy. Excerpts from the Workshop held at the Foundation for A Course in Miracles Temecula CA. Kenneth Wapnick, Ph.D.

Section overviews and Cameo commentaries are from Robert Perry, editor of the Complete & Annotated Edition (CE) of A Course in Miracles

Intellect and Faith in Tanya: The Never-Ending Circle. us to question, to doubt, to re-examine. Our faith causes us to do the exact opposite to

MORALITY OR SPIRITUALITY Ishwar Puri March 18, 1985

No one special to be. Escaping the prison of your own self-image Ezra Bayda

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan

Greetings in the Name of the Lord. Blessings for all of you, my friends.

Lesson 17 Romans PRESENT SUFFERINGS TO FUTURE GLORY (ROMANS 8:18-30) Imagine. The Cost of Glory (Romans 8:18-25) Study Notes

Nancey Murphy, Bodies and Souls, or Spirited Bodies? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006). Pp. x Hbk, Pbk.

Dolores Cannon s Quantum Healing Hypnosis Technique. Procedure Notes Supplemental Procedure Notes

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships

Introduction. Steven Luper

Jesus: The Manifestation of the Holy Spirit. Excerpts from the Workshop held at the Foundation for A Course in Miracles Temecula CA

Morally Adaptive or Morally Maladaptive: A Look at Compassion, Mercy, and Bravery

THESIS HOW DOES DEATH HARM THE PERSON WHO DIES? Submitted by. Andrew John Bzdok. Department of Philosophy. In partial fulfillment of the requirements

Thich Nhat Hanh HAPPINESS AND PEACE ARE POSSIBLE

Table of Contents. Advantages & Disadvantages Page 3. Team Strategy Page 4. Opening Statement (Brooke Young) Pages 5-6

DALLAS BAPTIST UNIVERSITY THE ILLOGIC OF FAITH: FEAR AND TREMBLING IN LIGHT OF MODERNISM SUBMITTED TO THE GENTLE READER FOR SPRING CONFERENCE

Exploring the Unconscious by Going Within: A Book Review of Inner Work by Robert A. Johnson. Nathaniel S. Prentice, MSW, LCSW, CAS PC

Are Things Right With God? Hebrews 2:14-17

Theories. It might be true. Think about it. Cohmi Coh

What It Means to Be a Teacher of God. Excerpts from the Workshop held at the Foundation for A Course in Miracles Temecula CA. Kenneth Wapnick, Ph.D.

Overcoming Fear and Rejection. Midweek Instruction Reid Temple AME Church Pastor Washington

21-Day. Clearing Process

The Question of Predestination

Nagel, T. The View from Nowhere. New York: Oxford University Press, 1986.

Nagel, Naturalism and Theism. Todd Moody. (Saint Joseph s University, Philadelphia)

The Nature of Death. chapter 8. What Is Death?

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

Korsgaard and Non-Sentient Life ABSTRACT

Evangelism For the Purpose of Godliness Chapter 6

Evaluating Arguments

Kant s Copernican Revolution

PHIL-176: DEATH. Lecture 15 - The Nature of Death (cont.); Believing You Will Die [March 6, 2007]

BonJour Against Materialism. Just an intellectual bandwagon?

PHIL 176: Death (Spring, 2007)

The Rescuing Hand Matthew 14:22-33

The Cosmological Argument: A Defense

IA Metaphysics & Mind S. Siriwardena (ss2032) 1 Personal Identity. Lecture 4 Animalism

The Comparative Badness for Animals of Suffering and Death Jeff McMahan November 2014

A COURSE IN MIRACLES STUDY GROUP

Belief Audit. 5 Basic Types of Beliefs

Ethical Issues at the End of Life Copyright 2008 Richard M. Gula, S.S., Ph.D.

1/5. The Critique of Theology

From Our Appointment with Life by Thich Nhat Hanh

Sounds of Love Series. Human Intellect and Intuition

One of the central concerns in metaphysics is the nature of objects which

DO YOU KNOW THAT THE DIGITS HAVE AN END? Mohamed Ababou. Translated by: Nafissa Atlagh

Good evening. And welcome to everyone who s joining us on the Internet.

Identity: Who Art Thou? August 17, 2016 Hymns 20, 436, 19

Antigone plays with the notion that we often want our systems of

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

An Epistemological Assessment of Moral Worth in Kant s Moral Theory. Immanuel Kant s moral theory outlined in The Grounding for the Metaphysics of

The Value of the Life of Reason ( ) Alonzo Fyfe

On Dispositional HOT Theories of Consciousness

Psyc 402 Online Survey Question Key 11/11/2018 Page 1

LIFE IN HIS NAME A RESURRECTION MIRACLE. John 5:1-29. After this there was a feast of the Jews, and Jesus went up to Jerusalem.

Anselm of Canterbury on Free Will

Debbie Homewood: Kerrybrook.ca *

Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, Pp $90.00 (cloth); $28.99

LEIBNITZ. Monadology

Russell Delman June The Encouragement of Light #2 Revised 2017

The Spiritual Journey Formation in the Contemplative Christian Life

Chapter 1. VortexHealing Divine Energy Healing

Kant The Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes. Section IV: What is it worth? Reading IV.2.

SECOND LECTURE. But the question is, how can a man awake?

Inner Journey. Welcome to the Voices In Your Head! Michael Schiesser Creator, Inner Journey

A Rejection of Skeptical Theism

Facing Our Fear of the Future Psalm 23:6 Douglas Scalise, Brewster Baptist Church This past Christmas Jill s parents gave me a couple of

T h o u g h t l i n e March 2016

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Mill and Bentham both endorse the harm principle. Utilitarians, they both rest

Class #13 - The Consciousness Theory of the Self Locke, The Prince and the Cobbler Reid, Of Mr. Locke's Account of Our Personal Identity

Commandment Who knew the 10 Commandments were going to be this much fun! OK, at least I am having a really good time researching and exploring

HOBBES S DECEIVING GOD: THE CORRESPONDENCE BETWEEN THOMAS HOBBES AND RENE DESCARTES. Gabriela Gorescu. Thesis Prepared for the Degree of

Greetings in the name of God. I bring you God's blessings.

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Augustine s famous story about his own theft of pears is perplexing to him at

Epistemology. Theory of Knowledge

What It Means to Be a Teacher of God. Excerpts from the Workshop held at the Foundation for A Course in Miracles Temecula CA. Kenneth Wapnick, Ph.D.

Six ways to stand firm: prepare for Christ s return 1 Thess

CONSCIOUSNESS IS NOT THE HUMAN MIND

EMOTIONAL QUOTIENT QUESTIONNAIRE

ACQUIRING THE MIND OF CHRIST

Overflowing With Joy

Personal Identity and the Jehovah' s Witness View of the Resurrection

Shieva Kleinschmidt [This is a draft I completed while at Rutgers. Please do not cite without permission.] Conditional Desires.

A Course In Miracle Workbook For Dummies

Journal of Cognition and Neuroethics

First Sunday of Lent

Series: Who is Who. Lesson 3 The Sheep and the Shepherd. Consider what the idea of a God being a Shepherd means.

The Incomprehensible Agony of Death

pantheists, panentheists, and process theologians. There are those who believe Eternity takes the form of reincarnation, or the continuation of the pe

SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5)

Nietzsche s Philosophy as Background to an Examination of Tolkien s The Lord of the Rings

Every simple idea has a simple impression, which resembles it; and every simple impression a correspondent idea

Transcription:

Afraid of the Dark: Nagel and Rationalizing the Fear of Death T homas Nagel, in his article Death (1994) sets out to examine what it is about death that a person finds so objectionable. He begins by assigning value statements to life and death, those being good and evil respectively, and determines that death is no evil for the person who dies and therefore is nothing to fear. He contends that what one objects to when thinking about death is not death itself, but rather the loss of life. In a short paragraph, with an almost dismissing tone, Nagel touches on the idea that many people fear death because of a misunderstanding of what it is like to be dead, in that many people view death as a state, where Nagel, like Epicurus, sees death as a non-state. This is an idea very closely related to Nagel s inquiry yet he gives it short-shrift. In the course of this paper I examine this neglected concept of a misunderstanding of the experience of death, showing that this misunderstanding is in fact, a rational, if not the most fundamental cause of our fear of death. Throughout, I draw on both Nagel and Green s response (1982) response to Nagel. To understand the position being taken by myself and that being held by Nagel and Green we must first define what we mean by death and show how it is distinct from dying. Both Nagel and Green use the Epicurean idea of death, that being death as the end of existence. When one dies, they no longer are; they cease to be. Death is a non-state where one does not exist. There is no afterlife, no heaven or hell, not even a mind trapped in a decaying corpse in a box. When one dies, s/he ends. Kaput! However, this non-state of death is different from the experience or state of dying. For when one is dying they are still alive, no matter how close to death s/he is. Life and death are distinct opposites, like black and white, either one exists or one does not exist. But when dying, one is still existing and experiencing and feeling pleasure and pain. Essentially then, the difference is that dying is a state while death is a non-state.

AFRAID OF THE DARK 21 Nagel begins his article by trying to discover what is evil in or about death. 1 Note, he is examining death, not dying. He begins this way because he feels that if something is being feared, it must be because there is something evil or objectionable about it. For instance, one may fear bees because s/he is allergic to them and being in the presence of a bee could cause extreme displeasure. Thus, according to Nagel, this possibility for displeasure is what is evil about the bee. Therefore, it is rational for this person to fear that which may cause him/her evil, that being the bee. But what is evil about death? What in death, a non-state, can cause displeasure to the person who is dead to the point where s/he would be justified in fearing it? In death one cannot experience or opine about things. One is neither capable of feeling displeasure or having an experience which could cause displeasure. Since there is nothing for the dead person to feel or experience that would be in any way evil, then there is nothing, according to Nagel, for him/her to fear. If one does not exist then no harm can come to him/her. Why would one fear something that could not cause him/her harm? (Nagel 1994) Nagel comes to the conclusion that it is not death, the non -state, that one objects to, but rather the deprivation of life. He uses the example of non-existence prior to birth. One does not typically object to his/her not existing before birth but one does object to not existing after life. This is because, before birth nothing was lost, but after death there is the deprivation of life. Because there is something in life to compare to non-existence, death becomes objectionable, because existing is clearly better than not existing. He points out that when value is attached to life experiences, such as eating is good, jogging is bad, and the bad outweighs the good, one would still choose to live for the small amount of good s/he was experiencing, because the alternative would be no experience at all. The idea of ceasing to experience is that which is objectionable for Nagel, not the prospect of nonexistence, because there would be no subject to opine about that state (or rather, non-state). (Nagel 1994) It is important to distinguish here that the objection to the loss of life is still an objection related to death, not dying. Nagel

22 is not saying that one objects to the process or experience of losing life, such as how one might object to being suffocated as a process for losing life. He is saying that, since death is the absence of life, and being in the dead non-state (in as much as a subject or object can be in a non-state) deprives someone of life, then that deprivation of life is that which is objectionable. O.H. Green argues that since being dead deprives someone of life then death and the loss of life are the same. (Green, 1982) Nagel rejects this notion, arguing that the loss of life is a mere side-effect or byproduct of death. It just so happens that one must lose life to be dead, in the same way that one must be injected with a needle in order to get a vaccination. One may fear vaccinations because of the pain involved in the shot, but it is not the vaccination that s/ he fears but rather the pain of being injected. The pain is a byproduct of the injection, and the injection is only necessary as a vehicle for the vaccination. The loss of life is a by-product of becoming dead (note becoming dead, not dying; becoming dead is the disappearance from the live state, the ceasing to exist), and becoming dead is what must happen in order to be dead. Green, as I ve already stated, disagrees with Nagel on this point. He argues that the fear of the loss of life, which Nagel accepts as rational, translates to a fear of death. Green begins also with the idea of good and evil as a way to examine the fear of death. He embraces the Epicurean notion, as does Nagel, that death is not an evil for the one who dies. He argues that there are two kinds of good and evil, subjective and objective. Subjective good and evil requires consciousness of the good and evil. Because the dead are not conscious, clearly death is not a subjective evil. Objective good and evil are things which temporally impede normal function. It can be said that death is the ultimate impediment of normal function and therefore must be an objective evil. But Green argues that objective good and evil must have a spatio-temporal subject to affect, and since death deprives one of his/her status as a subject, there is nothing for the objective good or evil to affect. But death s status as something not good or evil does not mean it is not something to fear. (Green 99-105)

AFRAID OF THE DARK 23 Green defines fear as an emotional response to expected disutility under conditions of subjective uncertainty. (Green 105) Since death is the ultimate expected disutility, and certainly it can be said that there is a subjective uncertainty surrounding death and one s meditations on death, then by Green s definition death is most definitely something to fear. But, he notes, that the fear of death is rational only as the desirability to live, not as the undesirability to die. He argues that men fear not living longer, and since death is that which causes someone to not live longer, then it is death that one fears, not just the deprivation of life. It is only when one examines death and its relation to life, discovering that death is the end of life, that one begins to fear this thing called death. (Green 105) Both Nagel and Green discuss the experience of death as a reflection of the loss of life. The only difference is that Green argues that the two are the same. Yet I feel Green s overall argument is weak, and that he occasionally misinterprets Nagel, but he presents an interesting, methodical approach to defending the Epicurean good and evil argument. His article actually doesn t even deal with rationalizing the fear of death until the last page. Because of the compelling arguments presented by Nagel and Green, I find no justifiable way to argue that death, in the Epicurean sense, is an evil. But, I do not see Green s argument that it is rational to fear death solely because it is a loss of life to be sufficient. I am inclined to agree with Nagel that the loss of life is merely a by-product of death, so therefore they cannot be equated. I am now charged with the lofty task of justifying the rationale behind fearing death. The key to this is in the Nagel passage I mentioned earlier, where he dismisses the notion of fearing death due to a misunderstanding of it as a state. Because I will be focusing so closely on this passage, I feel it is necessary to quote it: The point that death is not regarded as an unfortunate state enables us to refute a curious but very common suggestion about the origin of the fear of death. It is often said that those who object to

24 death have made the mistake of trying to imagine what it is like to be dead. It is alleged that the failure to realize that this task is logically impossible (for the banal reason that there is nothing to imagine) leads to the conviction that death is a mysterious and therefore terrifying prospective state. But this diagnosis is evidently false, for it is just as impossible to imagine being totally unconscious as to imagine being dead Yet people who are averse to death are not usually averse to unconsciousness (so long as it does not entail a substantial cut in the total duration of waking life). (Nagel 23) Here Nagel acknowledges the common suggestion that many fear death because they cannot logically comprehend what it is like to be dead. One is incapable even of comprehending the reality of unconsciousness. Thus, when thinking about what it would be like to be unconscious, what s/he is really doing is imagining what it would be like to be conscious while one s body was in a state similar to that of an unconscious person. Perhaps it would be that the mind would function but the body would be in paralysis, without any functioning sensing faculties, thereby trapping the mind in a dark box for all of eternity. This prospect alone is terrifying, yet the uncertainty and mystery of the myriad of possibilities after death amplifies that terror. For Nagel, this is absurd. Obviously, since death is not a state, then this idea of fearing the state of death is foolish and should be cast aside. He feels that this misunderstanding causes the common suggestion to be evidently false because it is impossible to imagine being totally unconscious. (Nagel 23) One s failure to realize that this task is logically impossible (Nagel, 23) leads them to fear death because it is mysterious. So, Nagel argues that because one does not realize that imagining oneself dead is logically impossible that is why s/he sees death as mysterious, and therefore, terrifying. Nagel does not reject the notion that things that are mysterious are terrifying, rather he feels that if one understood the logical impossibility of under-

AFRAID OF THE DARK 25 standing the situation then it would no longer be mysterious. But isn t the logical impossibility of understanding something the very root of its mystery? People tend to be at the very least wary of things they do not understand. For instance, let s say a human went to another planet, in a far distant galaxy. When she reached this planet she found that the entire civilization lived under water. She was greeted upon arrival by a creature from the planet who looked human. From her studies before arriving she knew that their physiological make-up was exactly the same as a humans. She saw no gills or breathing apparatus to aid the creature in breathing underwater. Upon asking how it was that the entire civilization breathed underwater the creature seemed confused and said that they breathed the same way as they did on land, through their mouths and noses and into their lungs. The human could not understand this, because on earth, if you breath water into your lungs you will drown. The creature invited the human to the Capitol of the city to meet their mayor but the only way to get there was by a long, tubular elevator that ended at the bottom of the sea. Were the human to take the elevator she would be so far below the surface that she would likely not be able to withstand the pressure, and if she found that she couldn t breath, she would be too deep to reach the surface before the air in her lungs ran out. It would seem that this would be a frightening concept to the human. Logically, she knows that her body is not made to breath water, but the creatures on this planet, who are physiologically identical to humans, seem to have no problem. The human is aware that she is logically incapable of understanding how these creatures breath underwater. But that does not make the situation any less mysterious. If anything, it makes it more mysterious. The mystery, in conjunction with the frustration of being logically incapable of understanding something, will likely result in the human being too afraid to go to the Capitol building at the bottom of the sea. If the human were not aware that the situation was logically impossible to understand, then perhaps she would decide to follow the creature, since it seemed from observation that he

26 was physiologically identical to her, and he could breath underwater, so maybe she could too. Perhaps there was something about the functioning of the lungs that she did not understand. The mere possibility of a logical explanation would be, at least, something. This failure to realize the logical impossibility of the situation would, in a way, provide a possible explanation for the situation. It would create a reasonable solution to help alleviate the fear of the human. So, Nagel s contention that the common suggestion is evidently false because one cannot logically comprehend true unconsciousness or death is itself evidently false because it is this logical impossibility that causes one to fear death. So, the fear of death comes from a fear of not understanding, a fear of the unknown. This is quite different from a fear of the loss of life. I would not even go so far as to call the objection to the loss of life a fear as much as simply, an objection. The loss of life is lamentable, not terrifying. One is not frightened of not existing and not experiencing, s/he is angry and sad. It does not scare me that, once dead, I will no longer be able to eat chocolate; it depresses me, sincerely depresses me. The thing that is frightening is the unknown state that will replace the state that I know, that I live in, that allows me to eat chocolate. Not only do I not know what that state is, but I cannot even imagine what it could be. This holds regardless of whether one believes in an afterlife or not. Whether death is a non-state or some sort of metaphysical existence, it is still entirely different from anything one has ever even remotely experienced. In that we are existing, physical beings, the idea of not-existing is not even within the realm of things our mind can comprehend. How can I, sitting here at my keyboard, existing, possibly understand what it would be like to not exist? It isn t like being asleep or unconscious, it is not being. The very idea violates the law of noncontradiction. I cannot be and not be; and since I have always been, and only know what it is like to be, I cannot know what it is like to not be. And if our death is something metaphysical, I cannot know that metaphysical being in the same way that I can-

AFRAID OF THE DARK 27 not know not being. Since my pre-natal existence I have been a physical creature. I have lived and experienced the world through a body that smells and touches and sees. I have no idea what it is like to be not physical. A metaphysical existence would not be a glorified physical existence, up in the sky, sitting on a cloud, eating all that you want without gaining weight, which is a common misunderstanding of the metaphysical afterlife, as expounded by multiple religions. It would be something beyond the comprehension of my physical brain in the same way that not existing is beyond my comprehension. Since the state or non-state of death is completely incomprehensible it is uncomfortable to try to make sense of it. And once one realizes that it is logically impossible to make sense of, but also completely inevitable that it will occur, there is a panic and fear associated with making that leap. So, unlike fearing merely the implications of death, that being the loss of life, death itself, the experience or non-experience of death, is actually justifiably feared. Nagel contends that at the time one is dead s/he will have no opinion of it so one should not fear it, but that does not stop one from fearing it before hand. Not all things must be feared in the moment. They can be feared in anticipation. Nagel acknowledges this and says that one fears in anticipation the loss of life. But the loss of life is not what one is fearing, lost life is merely being lamented. It is the unknown, logically incomprehensible death state (or non-state) that incites fear. So many of life s fears are rooted in a fundamental fear of the unknown, like being afraid of the dark, or afraid of strange places and people, or of the boogieman. In childhood many fears result from fearing the unknown, because one hasn t experienced enough to know what to expect of different experiences. As we grow older and experience more we replace magic and mystery with science and fact and our fears are alleviated. Death is not something we can try or test and then know about. We will never have the benefit of other s experience to Shepherd us through the valley of darkness. And that is what is frightening; That unknown, incomprehensible abyss beyond the light of life. In the end we are still afraid of the dark.

28 Notes 1 Note here that Nagel is discussing what is wrong with death. By the term evil he is referring to that which causes the objection or harm of death. Bibliography Nagel, Thomas, Death, Language, Metaphysics, and Death, NY, Fordham University Press, 2 nd ed., 1994, pp. 21-29. Green, O.H., Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 43, No. 1. (Sep., 1982), pp. 99-105.