Section 1 of chapter 1 of The Moral Sense advances the thesis that we have a

Similar documents
SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

The Pleasure Imperative

Kant The Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes. Section IV: What is it worth? Reading IV.2.

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

A Contractualist Reply

#NLCU. The Ethical Leader: Rules and Tools

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

Adam Smith and the Limits of Empiricism

Altruism. A selfless concern for other people purely for their own sake. Altruism is usually contrasted with selfishness or egoism in ethics.

a0rxh/ On Van Inwagen s Argument Against the Doctrine of Arbitrary Undetached Parts WESLEY H. BRONSON Princeton University

Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008

24.02 Moral Problems and the Good Life

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

Making Decisions on Behalf of Others: Who or What Do I Select as a Guide? A Dilemma: - My boss. - The shareholders. - Other stakeholders

ON THE INCOMPATIBILITY BETWEEN ARISTOTLE S AND KANT S IMPERATIVES TO TREAT A MAN NOT AS A MEANS BUT AS AN END-IN- HIMSELF

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism

Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning

CMSI Handout 3 Courtesy of Marcello Antosh

Duty and Categorical Rules. Immanuel Kant Introduction to Ethics, PHIL 118 Professor Douglas Olena

The title of this collection of essays is a question that I expect many professional philosophers have

THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1. Dana K. Nelkin. I. Introduction. abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory.

Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism

Are Humans Always Selfish? OR Is Altruism Possible?

PHD THESIS SUMMARY: Rational choice theory: its merits and limits in explaining and predicting cultural behaviour

PHIL%13:%Ethics;%Fall%2012% David%O.%Brink;%UCSD% Syllabus% Part%I:%Challenges%to%Moral%Theory 1.%Relativism%and%Tolerance.

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

Annotated List of Ethical Theories

what makes reasons sufficient?

Benjamin Visscher Hole IV Phil 100, Intro to Philosophy

THE MYTH OF MORALITY CHAPTER 6. Morality and Evolution

CHAPTER 2 Test Bank MULTIPLE CHOICE

MILL. The principle of utility determines the rightness of acts (or rules of action?) by their effect on the total happiness.

Q2) The test of an ethical argument lies in the fact that others need to be able to follow it and come to the same result.

Chapter 2 Normative Theories of Ethics

Deontology. Marianne Talbot University of Oxford Department for Continuing Education

Philosophical Ethics. Distinctions and Categories

Hello again. Today we re gonna continue our discussions of Kant s ethics.

145 Philosophy of Science

From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005)

PRESS DEFINITION AND THE RELIGION ANALOGY

MILL ON JUSTICE: CHAPTER 5 of UTILITARIANISM Lecture Notes Dick Arneson Philosophy 13 Fall, 2005

ETHICAL THEORIES. Review week 6 session 11. Ethics Ethical Theories Review. Socrates. Socrate s theory of virtue. Socrate s chain of injustices

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

In Concerning the Difference between the Spirit and the Letter in Philosophy, Johann

Lecture 12 Deontology. Onora O Neill A Simplified Account of Kant s Ethics

Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT


EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers

Is Morality Rational?

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

Ethical non-naturalism

Virtue Ethics. Chapter 7 ETCI Barbara MacKinnon Ethics and Contemporary Issues Professor Douglas Olena

The Role of Love in the Thought of Kant and Kierkegaard

When does human life begin? by Dr Brigid Vout

Holtzman Spring Philosophy and the Integration of Knowledge

There is a traditional debate in ethical theory about the relation between moral rightness

THE EIGHT KEY QUESTIONS HANDBOOK

CODE OF ETHICS AND MINISTRY PRACTICE

CODE OF ETHICS AND MINISTRY PRACTICE

Well, how are we supposed to know that Jesus performed miracles on earth? Pretty clearly, the answer is: on the basis of testimony.

OPEN Moral Luck Abstract:

Chapter 2 Ethical Concepts and Ethical Theories: Establishing and Justifying a Moral System

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Naturalism Primer. (often equated with materialism )

Thursday, November 30, 17. Hegel s Idealism

Two Kinds of Moral Relativism

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

CALVARY CHURCH

Suppose... Kant. The Good Will. Kant Three Propositions

Kant. Deontological Ethics

Deontological Ethics. Kant. Rules for Kant. Right Action

Tuesday, November 11, Hegel s Idealism

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Ethical Theory for Catholic Professionals

Responsibility and the Value of Choice

ETHICAL THEORY. Burkhardt - Chapter 2 - Ethical Theory

Rawlsian Values. Jimmy Rising

Three Types of Friendship Excerpt from The Nicomachean Ethics By Aristotle Roughly 340 BCE

Human Nature & Human Diversity: Sex, Love & Parenting; Morality, Religion & Race. Course Description

WHEN is a moral theory self-defeating? I suggest the following.

A CONTRACTUALIST READING OF KANT S PROOF OF THE FORMULA OF HUMANITY. Adam Cureton

DEONTOLOGICAL ETHICS

Hume s Is/Ought Problem. Ruse and Wilson. Moral Philosophy as Applied Science. Naturalistic Fallacy

The Biological Foundation of Bioethics

Pastoral Code of Conduct

Hume's Is/Ought Problem. Ruse and Wilson. Moral Philosophy as Applied Science. Naturalistic Fallacy

Compatibilist Objections to Prepunishment

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

Computer Ethics. Normative Ethics and Normative Argumentation. Viola Schiaffonati October 10 th 2017

Practical Rationality and Ethics. Basic Terms and Positions

[Note to readers of this draft: paragraph numbers will not appear in the printed book.]

FARMS Review 19/1 (2007): (print), (online)

Templates for Research Paper

ZAGZEBSKI ON RATIONALITY

Hoong Juan Ru. St Joseph s Institution International. Candidate Number Date: April 25, Theory of Knowledge Essay

Psychological Aspects of Social Issues

Kant, Deontology, & Respect for Persons

Transcription:

Extracting Morality from the Moral Sense Scott Soames Character and the Moral Sense: James Q. Wilson and the Future of Public Policy February 28, 2014 Wilburn Auditorium Pepperdine University Malibu, California Section 1 of chapter 1 of The Moral Sense advances the thesis that we have a moral sense that is the product our innate endowment and our earliest familial experience. Section 2 of chapter 1, entitled Morality vs. Philosophy, begins with these words: At one time, the view that our sense of morality shaped our behavior and judgments was widely held among philosophers. Aristotle said that man is naturally a social being that seeks happiness. Thomas Aquinas argued that man has a natural inclination to be a rational and familial being; the moral law is, in the first instance, an expression of a natural that is innate tendency. Adam Smith wrote that man is motivated by sympathy as well as by self-interest, and he developed a moral philosophy squarely based on the capacity for sympathy. But, says Wilson, modern philosophy represents a fundamental break with that tradition. He s right, the philosophy of the 20 th century did break with it. But he seems not to have understood why. Marx and Rorty, whom he cites, were irrelevant; Ayer s 1936 view that because moral statements are unverifiable they are merely ejaculations or commands, didn t last. Today I will sketch why the break between philosophy and morality occurred, how the break is connected to the larger cultural diminishment of morality Wilson decries, and how his social scientific approach addresses both the philosophical and the cultural diminishment of morality of the last 100 years. The tradition of Aristotle, Aquinas, and Smith recognized the existence of moral facts, knowledge of which provided reasons for action. The philosophers who broke with the tradition did so because they believed the questions, What are moral facts? and How do they provide us with reasons for action?, raised by the tradition, can t be answered. A

moral fact, these modern philosophers contended, must provide a reason for all relevantly situated rational agents to act in a certain way. The authority of morality is tied to the generality of these reasons. Many facts provide reasons for acting without themselves being moral facts. The fact that I can afford tickets to a sporting event gives me a reason to attend in order to support my local team, but only if I am interested in doing so. Since not everyone shares my interest, and there s no reason they should, this fact isn t a moral fact. A moral fact must provide reasons for action that aren t conditional in this way. If you are morally obligated to do something, your obligation isn t conditional on any renounceable interest, sentiment, or preference of yours. Do any facts provide categorical, rather than merely conditional, reasons for action? Consider three candidates: (i) the fact that lying or breaking a promise subverts the very trust that makes one s lie or promise possible, (ii) the fact that one who shirks one s share of the burden of a collective effort from which one benefits asks others to do something that one refuses to do oneself, (iii) the fact that securing a modest benefit to oneself may, in a certain case, harm others. These will all count as moral facts if they provide reasons for all agents to refrain from the behavior in question. Do they? Imagine a rational being who lacks concern for others, who expertly calculates benefits for himself, and who always acts accordingly. Because the three facts just mentioned are unconnected with this agent s goals, they won t, in and of themselves, count as reasons for him. To be sure, a race of relentless interest-maximizers might sometimes need to cooperate to achieve mutually beneficial ends. In such cases they may behave cooperatively. But they won t behave morally, because genuine affection, loyalty, trust, reciprocity, openness, and obligation will be absent. 2

This thought experiment shows that some facts we commonly take to be moral facts don t provide reasons for all conceivable rational beings to act. How then do they provide us with binding reasons to act? How do facts that can be known without one s taking any particular motivational stance toward them facts with no necessary connection to ultimate interests the knower -- count as genuinely moral? Couldn t you and I know my three facts, while understanding our individual interests perfectly well, without taking them to provide us with binding reasons to act? If the answer to this question is yes, then, the idea that we have genuine other-regarding duties in the sense of Aristotle, Aquinas, and Kant duties that can t be shirked by adopting different motivating interests -- is a fairy tale. That, more or less, is what many 20 th -century philosophers believed. But James Q. Wilson didn t. Instead, he set out to find, using social science, the basis in human nature from which duties do arise. But how, you might ask, could he possibly succeed? Since reasons for rational action must depend on motivating interests that can, in principle, vary from one rational agent to another, no mere facts can provide all such agents with reasons to perform otherregarding actions. In short, there is no objective morality that binds all possible rational agents. This conclusion was, I think, plausibly taken to be a conceptual truth by many 20 th -century philosophers. And if it is a conceptual truth, it can t be overridden by science. So, where, in moral philosophy, do we go from here? We start by recognizing that there is more to morality than rationality. We don t need an objective morality for all possible rational beings. We do need one for normal, rational human beings. If Wilson is right, our human genetic endowment, our early family experience, and the unalterable circumstances of the human condition provide us 3

with a motivational base that ties us by bonds of affection, social affiliation, and mutual interest to our fellows. This is the raw material that generates reasons for other-regarding action, the authority of which can, in principle, be recognized by normal human beings. To discern what these reasons are, and what specific actions they enjoin, is to construct a moral code, which goes beyond what Wilson attempted. His job was to show that the such a construction is possible by demonstrating a naturalistic basis, which he calls the moral sense, on which objective morality is founded. In doing his job, he repudiates Freud and embraces Darwin. Because cooperation promotes survival, we have been bred, by natural selection, to be social animals. It is not just that we need and want what others can provide, and so are forced by self interest to depend on them. We are also disposed to form powerful cognitive and emotional attachments to them. Parents are innately disposed to protect, nourish, and love their babies. Children naturally love, imitate, and emulate their parents and others with whom they are intimate. As children we form reciprocal bonds of affection and trust in which our well-being is intertwined with theirs. Entering into games and collective activities with others, we learn the rudiments of fairness, which involves adhering to common rules and earning rewards proportional to the value of our efforts. This fusion of natural sentiment with rational principle gives birth to morality. Sentiment infuses our participation in games and collective activities with those we like and admire, and whom we wish to be liked and admired by in return. Often these individuals will be models of the people we hope to become. The accepted rules governing our activities with them are impersonal principles that apply to anyone who occupies a given role in the effort. Because these rules define the commonly accepted 4

terms of participation in a mutually beneficial undertaking, it is in the self-interest of each participant to obey them. But they are much more than prudential directives. Because the participants are often comrades bound by ties of social affiliation, rule violations carry psychic risks beyond the loss of the purely self-interested benefits secured by participation. Violations of the rules governing interaction with one s socially affiliated fellows are affronts to one s comrades, to one s friendship with them, to one s image in their eyes, and to the person one wants oneself to be. With this, instrumentally useful rules obeyed to secure the benefits of group action become principles to be honored even when no one is looking. This is the crucial point at which sentiment, social affiliation, and recognition of mutual interest are incorporated into the broad principles of general application that constitute morality. This account of how Wilson s moral sense may generate embryonic moral principles defining obligations to family and friends is only the beginning. More is needed to explain how broader obligations are generated -- to one s community, to one s country, and even to all human beings. The task can be accomplished only by recognizing (i) that we are beings that construct our own identities in relation to others, (ii) that in doing this we often must rely on others for guidance about who we are and whom we wish to become, (iii) that the most successful way to secure this guidance requires being open to and caring about others, and trusting them to feel similarly about us, and (iv) that to build the relationships we need we must internalize, and be seen as internalizing, universal rules of reciprocity that encompass not only the ancient principle Do unto others as you would have them do unto you, but also its corollary, Be the kind of person that you want and expect others to be. 5

That, in a short space, is my sketch of a philosophically defensible construction of an objective morality based on Wilson s moral sense. But more is at stake than abstract philosophy. The cultural conception of morality, which changed drastically in the 20 th century, is also at stake. Today the leading transmitters of culture in the West -- the universities, the news media, and the entertainment industry among them have largely given up on morality as a domain of objective fact the knowledge of which can be advanced by reasoned argument informed by the empirical study of human nature. As my late colleague, Dallas Willard, put it, they have given up on the reality of moral knowledge. These cultural institutions haven t given up their moral passions. The passions are too deep for that. But because they no longer believe in moral knowledge, they don t subject our moral passions, or theirs, to the rational scrutiny they require. By removing reasoned argument and scientific inquiry from the equation, they have coarsened our passions, made them more unreasonable, generated intolerance where there should be civility, and deprived us of our best means of enhancing our moral sense. This cultural phenomenon is, I think, what concerned Wilson in the section of chapter 1 entitled Is everything permitted? Of course, everything isn t permitted, but it is important to know and explain why it isn t. I hope my elementary sketch of how genuine moral obligation can arise from the innate moral sense Wilson identifies illustrates how philosophers and social scientists together might use his work as a starting point for combating the cultural diminishment of morality he deplored. 6