Proof of the Necessary of Existence

Similar documents
Avicenna, Proof of the Necessary of Existence

Summer Preparation Work

Spinoza, Ethics 1 of 85 THE ETHICS. by Benedict de Spinoza (Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata) Translated from the Latin by R. H. M.

Concerning God Baruch Spinoza

Aristotle and Aquinas

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII

The Creation of the World in Time According to Fakhr al-razi

Aquinas, The Divine Nature

On Being and Essence (DE ENTE Et ESSENTIA)

The cosmological argument (continued)

WHAT ARISTOTLE TAUGHT

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

The Divine Nature. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 3-11) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian J.

Thomas Aquinas The Treatise on the Divine Nature

The Five Ways. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Question 2) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006) Question 2. Does God Exist?

From Aristotle s Ousia to Ibn Sina s Jawhar

The Ethics. Part I and II. Benedictus de Spinoza ************* Introduction

Five Ways to Prove the Existence of God. From Summa Theologica. St. Thomas Aquinas

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

The Cosmological Argument

Monday, September 26, The Cosmological Argument

The Five Ways THOMAS AQUINAS ( ) Thomas Aquinas: The five Ways

Topics and Posterior Analytics. Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey

Ibn Sina on Substances and Accidents

Critique of Cosmological Argument

Thomas Aquinas on the World s Duration. Summa Theologiae Ia Q46: The Beginning of the Duration of Created Things

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

exists and the sense in which it does not exist.

Aquinas s Third Way Keith Burgess-Jackson 24 September 2017

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

Baruch Spinoza. Demonstrated in Geometric Order AND. III. Of the Origin and Nature of the Affects. IV. Of Human Bondage, or the Power of the Affects.

What one needs to know to prepare for'spinoza's method is to be found in the treatise, On the Improvement

P. Weingartner, God s existence. Can it be proven? A logical commentary on the five ways of Thomas Aquinas, Ontos, Frankfurt Pp. 116.

The Five Ways of St. Thomas in proving the existence of

John Buridan on Essence and Existence

St. Thomas Aquinas Excerpt from Summa Theologica

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY

PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE LET THOMAS AQUINAS TEACH IT. Joseph Kenny, O.P. St. Thomas Aquinas Priory Ibadan, Nigeria

On Interpretation. Section 1. Aristotle Translated by E. M. Edghill. Part 1

Individual Essences in Avicenna s Metaphysics

Aquinas' Third Way Modalized

Descartes, Leibniz, Spinoza: Concept of Substance Chapter 3 Spinoza and Substance. (Woolhouse)

St. Thomas quotes the opening lines of Avicenna s Metaphysics: ens and essentia are what is first conceived by the intellect. 2

Cartesian Aseity in the Third Meditation

c Peter King, 1987; all rights reserved. WILLIAM OF OCKHAM: ORDINATIO 1 d. 2 q. 6

Sufficient Reason and Infinite Regress: Causal Consistency in Descartes and Spinoza. Ryan Steed

First Treatise <Chapter 1. On the Eternity of Things>

First Principles. Principles of Reality. Undeniability.

Aquinas, The Five Ways

The question is concerning truth and it is inquired first what truth is. Now

ST. THOMAS AQUINAS SUMMA THEOLOGICA

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Peter L.P. Simpson December, 2012

On The Existence of God Thomas Aquinas

Questions on Book III of the De anima 1

FREEDOM OF CHOICE. Freedom of Choice, p. 2

1 Concerning distinction 39 I ask first whether God immutably foreknows future

The Cosmological Argument: A Defense

Peter L.P. Simpson December, 2012

What Must There be to Account for Being?

THE LOGICAL ROLE OF THE ARGUMENT FROM TIME IN THE TAHAFUT S SECOND PROOF FOR THE WORLD S PRE-ETERNITY

There Must Be A First: Why Thomas Aquinas Rejects Infinite, Essentially Ordered, Causal Series

Dartmouth College THE DIVINE SIMPLICITY *

QUESTION 47. The Diversity among Things in General

William Ockham on Universals

Secular Thought in the Islamic Golden Age

MEDITATIONS ON THE FIRST PHILOSOPHY: THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

The Solution to Skepticism by René Descartes (1641) from Meditations translated by John Cottingham (1984)

Aquinas Cosmological argument in everyday language

Aquinas 5 Proofs for God exists

GOD AND THE PRINCIPLE OF SUFFICIENT REASON

Quaerens Deum: The Liberty Undergraduate Journal for Philosophy of Religion

Al-Ghazālī on the Incoherence of Substance Boris Hennig Pittsburgh / Hamburg / Saarbrücken


Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

The Principle of Sufficient Reason in Spinoza

QUESTION 54. An Angel s Cognition

Cartesian Rationalism

Henry of Ghent on Divine Illumination

Cartesian Rationalism

The Problem with Complete States: Freedom, Chance and the Luck Argument

AQUINAS: EXPOSITION OF BOETHIUS S HEBDOMADS * Introduction

The Cosmological Argument

1/8. Descartes 3: Proofs of the Existence of God

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres

On Finitism and the Beginning of the Universe: A Reply to Stephen Puryear. Citation Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 2016, v. 94 n. 3, p.

An Analysis of the Proofs for the Principality of the Creation of Existence in the Transcendent Philosophy of Mulla Sadra

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

One of the many common questions that are asked is If God does exist what reasons

5 A Modal Version of the

QUESTION 44. The Procession of Creatures from God, and the First Cause of All Beings

On Truth Thomas Aquinas

The Names of God. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 12-13) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006)

The Quality of Mercy is Not Strained: Justice and Mercy in Proslogion 9-11

QUESTION 3. God s Simplicity

Thomas Aquinas The Existence of God can be proved in five ways.

Jean Jacques Rousseau The Social Contract, or Principles of Political Right (1762)

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

The Neo-Platonic Proof

Being and Meaning: Fakhr al-dın al-razı and His Followers on the Identity of Knowledge and the Known. Ömer Türker *

Transcription:

Proof of the Necessary of Existence by Avicenna (Ibn Sīnā), various excerpts (~1020-1037 AD) *** The Long Version from Kitab al-najat (The Book of Salvation), second treatise (~1020 AD) translated by Jon McGinnis and David Reisman (2007) 1. Explaining the Senses of Necessary and Possible The necessarily existent is the existent, which when posited as not existing, an absurdity results. The possibly existent is the one that when posited as either existing or not existing, no absurdity results. The necessarily existent is the existence that must be, whereas the possibly existent is the one that has no must about it in any way, whether in terms of its existence or nonexistence. Next, the necessarily existent may exist through itself or not through itself. What is necessarily existent through itself is that which is owing to itself, not to any other thing The necessarily existent not through itself is that which becomes necessarily existent if something other than it is set down. For example, four exists necessarily not through itself but only when positing two plus two; and burning exists necessarily not through itself but only when positing contact between the natural active power and the natural passive power, I mean what causes burning and what is burned. 2. The Necessary through Itself Cannot Be Necessary through Another, and the Necessary through Another Is What Is Possible One thing cannot exist simultaneously as necessary through itself and necessary through another. For if the other is removed or its existence not considered, it must be the case that either the necessity of its existence remains unchanged, and so the necessity of its existence is not through another, or the necessity of its existence does not remain, and so the necessity of its existence is not through itself. Whatever exists necessarily through another exists possibly in itself. This is because the necessity of the existence of whatever exists necessarily through another is a consequence of a given association and relation, but consideration of the association and relation is different from consideration of the thing itself that has an association and relation.

In terms of the thing [that exists necessarily through another] itself on its own, it is something that must exist necessarily, possibly or impossibly. Now it cannot be something that must exist impossibly, because anything whose existence is impossible through itself is neither through itself nor through another. Nor is it something that must exist necessarily, for we have already said that whatever exists necessarily through itself simply cannot have the necessity of its existence through another. So it remains that with respect to the thing itself, it exists possibly; with respect to introducing an association with that other, it exists necessarily; and with respect to disrupting the association with that other, it exists impossibly. It itself, however in itself without condition exists possibly. 3. Whatever Is Not Necessary Does Not Exist It is now clear that what exists necessarily through another exists possibly through itself. This is convertible. Thus, everything existing possibly in itself if indeed its existence has occurred exists necessarily through another. This follows because its existence is either necessary or not necessary. If its existence is not necessary, and so it is still possible existence, then its existence is not distinguished from its nonexistence and there is no difference between this state in it and the first state. This follows because before existing it was possible existence, and its present state is the same as it was. If one posits that a new state comes to be, then concerning that state [i]f it is possible, and that state before was itself also possible, then nothing new came to be, whereas if the existence of the new state is necessary that new state is nothing other than the emergence of the thing into existence, so it is its emergence into existence that is necessary. Finally, the existence of whatever exists possibly is either through itself or through some given cause. If it is through itself, then it itself exists necessarily not possibly. If it is through a cause, then either its existence is necessary together with the existence of the cause, or it would stay the way it was before the existence of the cause, which is absurd. It must be the case, then, that its existence is simultaneous with the existence of the cause. [4] Now everything that exists possibly in itself has a cause for its existence that is prior to it, because every cause is prior to the effect with respect to its own existence, even if it is not prior with respect to time. Again, in the case of anything that is necessary through another, its very existence is posterior to the existence of that other and is dependent upon it.

from Kitab al-shifa: Ilāhiyyāt (The Metaphysics of the Book of Healing), ch. 6 (~1020 AD) translated by Michael Marmura (2005) That which in itself is a necessary existent has no cause, while that which in itself is a possible existent has a cause. That the Necessary Existent has no cause is obvious. For if in [its] existence the Necessary Existent were to have a cause, [its] existence would be by that cause. But whatever exists by something else, if considered in itself, apart from another, existence for it would not be necessary. And everything for which existence is not found to be necessary if the thing is considered in itself, apart from another is not a necessary existent in itself. It is thus evident that if what is in itself a necessary existent were to have a cause, it would not be in itself a necessary existent. Thus, it becomes clear that the Necessary Existent has no cause. From this it is also clear that it is impossible for a thing to be both a necessary existent in itself and a necessary existent through another. This is because, if its existence is rendered necessary through another, it cannot exist without the other. But if anything whatsoever cannot exist without another, its existence as necessary in itself is impossible. Moreover, whatever is possible in existence when considered in itself, its existence and nonexistence are both due to a cause. This is because, whatever exists after nonexistence has been specified [by] something possible other than itself. This is because the thing s quiddity is either sufficient for this specification or not. If its quiddity is sufficient for [its own existence] to obtain, then that thing would be [necessary in itself in its own essence], when the thing has been supposed not to be necessary in itself. And this is contradictory. If on the other hand the existence of its quiddity is not sufficient for [its own existence but is], rather, something whose existence is added to it then its existence would be necessarily due to some other thing. This, then would be its cause. Hence, it has a cause. In sum, then, [its existence] would obtain necessarily, due, not to itself, but to a cause. We thus say: The possible in itself must become necessary through a cause and with respect to it. For, if it were not necessary, then with the existence of the cause and with respect to it, it would still be [merely] possible. It would then be possible for it to exist or not to exist, being specified with neither of the two states. Once again, from the beginning this would be in need of

the existence of a third thing through which either existence as distinct from nonexistence or nonexistence as distinct from its existence would be assigned for the possible when the cause of its existence with this state of affairs would not have been specified. This would be another cause, and the discussion would be extended to an infinite regress. And, if it regresses infinitely, the existence of the possible, with all this, would not have been specified by it. As such, its existence would not have been realized. This is impossible, not only because this leads to an infinity of causes for this is a dimension, the impossibility of which is still open to doubt in this place but because no dimension has been arrived at through which its existence is specified, when it has been supposed to be existing. Hence, it has been shown to be true that whatever is possible in its existence does not exist unless rendered necessary with respect to its cause. from Kitab al-najat (The Book of Salvation), second treatise (~1020 AD) translated by Jon McGinnis and David Reisman (2007) 12. The Proof of the Necessarily Existent Undoubtedly there is existence, and all existence is either necessary or possible. If it is necessary, then in fact there is a necessarily existent being, which is what is sought. If it is possible, then we will show that the existence of the possible terminates in a necessarily existent being. Before that, however, we will advance some premises. These include that at any one and the same time there cannot be for anything that is possible in itself a cause that is itself possible ad infinitum. This is because all of them exist either all together or they do not. If they do not exist all together but rather one after another, there is no infinite at one and the same time but let us defer discussion of this for now. As for their existing all together, and none is a necessarily existent being, then either the totality, insofar as it is that totality, whether finite or infinite, exists necessarily through itself or possibly in itself. If, on the one hand, the totality exists necessarily through itself, but each one of its members is something possible, then what exists necessarily subsists by means of things that exist possibly, which is absurd. On the other hand, if the totality is something existing possibly in itself, then the totality needs for existence something that provides existence, which will either be external or internal to the totality. If it is something internal to it, then one of its members is something existing necessarily, but each one of them exists possibly so this is a contradiction.

Or it is something existing possibly and so is a cause of the totality s existence, but a cause of the totality is primarily a cause of the existence of its members, of which it is one. Thus, it would be a cause of its own existence, which is impossible. Despite this impossibility, if it is correct, it is in a certain way the very thing that is sought; for anything that is sufficient to necessitate itself is something existing necessarily, but it was assumed not to exist necessarily, so this is a contradiction. The remaining option is that what gives existence to the totality is external to it, but it cannot be a possible cause, since we included every cause existing possibly in this totality. So since the cause is external to it, it also is something existing necessarily in itself. Thus, things existing possibly terminate in a cause existing necessarily, in which case not every effect that exists as something possible will have simultaneously with it a cause that exists as something possible, and so an infinite number of causes existing at a single time is impossible. The Short Version Al-Isharat Wa l-tanbihat (Remarks and Admonitions) (~1037 AD) translated by Shams Inati (2014) Part Three: Metaphysics; Fourth Class: On Existence and Its Causes 5. Admonition: Concerning the Difference Between the Causes of Quiddity and Those of Existence A thing may be caused in relation to its quiddity or reality, and it may be caused in its existence. You can consider this in the triangle, for example. The reality of the triangle depends on the surface and on the line which is its side. Both the surface and the line constitute the triangle inasmuch as it is a triangle and has a reality of triangularity, as if they are its two causes: the material and the formal. But inasmuch as a triangle exists, it may also depend on a cause other than these two, which is not a cause that constitutes its triangularity and is not a part of its definition. This is the efficient cause or the final cause that is an efficient cause of the causality of the efficient cause. 1 1 The idea that final causality has some causal priority over efficient causality is an Aristotelian concept more fully worked out in Ibn Sina. See Aristotle, De Partibus Animalium, 639b: The causes concerned in the generation of the works of nature are, as we see, more than one. There is the final cause and there is the motor cause. Plainly, however, the cause is the first which we call the final

6. Admonition: Regarding the Difference Between Essence and Concrete Existence You must know that you understand the concept of triangle while in doubt as to whether or not concrete existence is attributed to triangle. This is after triangle is represented to you as constituted of a line and a surface and is not represented to you as existing. 2 7. Remark: Causality of the Efficient and Final Causes The cause of the existence of a thing, which has causes constitutive of its quiddity, is a cause of some of those causes, such as the form, or of all of them 3 in existence this is the cause of the union of those causes. The final cause, for whose sake a thing is, is in quiddity and idea, a cause of the causality of the efficient cause; whereas in existence it is an effect of it. The efficient cause is a certain cause of the existence of the final cause, if the latter is among the ends that occur in actuality, but it is not a cause of the causality or idea of the final cause. 8. Remark: If There is a First Cause, it Must Be an Efficient Cause for Everything Else That Exists Thus, if there is a first cause, it is a cause of every existence and of the cause of the reality of every concrete existence. 9. Admonition: The Necessary in itself and the Possible in itself Every being, if considered from the point of view of its essence and without consideration of other things, is found to be such that either existence necessarily belongs to it in itself or it does not. If existence belongs to it necessarily, then it is the truth in itself and that whose existence is necessary from itself. This is the Independent Reality. If, on the other hand, existence one. For this is the Reason, and the Reason forms the starting-point, alike in works of art and in works of nature. For consider how the physician or builder sets about his work. He starts by forming for himself a definite picture... and this he holds forward as the reason and explanation of each subsequent step that he takes, and of his acting in this or that way as the case may be. 2 As is well known, Ibn Sina s distinction between a thing s essence and its existence had a direct influence on Aquinas. See Thomas Aquinas, De Ente et Essentia, esp. ch. 4: But every essence or quiddity can be understood without understanding anything about its existence: I can understand what a man is or what a phoenix is and nevertheless not know whether either has existence in reality. Therefore, it is clear that existence is something other than the essence or quiddity, unless perhaps there is something whose quiddity is its very own existence, and this thing must be one and primary. 3 i.e., of both the form and the matter.

does not belong to it necessarily, it is not permissible to say that it is impossible in itself after it was supposed existing. But if, in relation to its essence, a condition is linked to it, such as the condition of the nonexistence of its cause, it becomes impossible or, such as the condition of the existence of its cause, it becomes necessary. If no condition is linked to its essence, neither existence nor nonexistence of a cause, then there remains for it in itself the third option, that is, possibility. Thus, with respect to its essence, it would be a thing that is neither necessary nor impossible. Therefore every existent either has necessary existence in essence or has possible existence in essence. 10. Remark: The Possible in itself Cannot Exist Except Due to a Cause Other Than itself That to which possibility belongs in essence does not come into existence by its essence, for, inasmuch as it is possible, existence by its essence is not more appropriate than nonexistence. Thus, if its existence or nonexistence becomes more appropriate [than the other], that is because of the presence or absence of a certain thing [respectively]. It follows that the existence of every possible thing is from another. 11. Admonition: An infinite Chain of Possibles is Possible and Cannot Become Necessary Except Through Another If that [other] goes on to infinity, every one of the units of the chain will be possible in essence. [But] the whole chain depends on these units. Thus the chain too will not be necessary and becomes necessary through another. Let us clarify this further. 12. Explication Every totality having every one of its units as caused requires a cause external to its units. This is because either (1) it does not require a cause at all; hence it is necessary and not possible. But how could this be so when it is only necessitated by its units? (2) It requires a cause that is all its units; hence it is caused by itself [which is obviously impossible. A thing cannot cause itself]. That totality and all its units are one thing. (3) It requires a cause that is some of its units. But if every one of its units is caused, then some of its units are not more deserving of being the cause than some others. The reason is that the cause of the caused is more deserving of being the cause. Or (4) it requires a cause external to all its units. This is the remaining [truth].

13. Remark: The Cause of a Totality of Units is First the Cause of Every One of the Units Every cause of a totality that is something other than its units is, first of all, a cause of the units and then of the totality. If this is not so, then let the units not be in need of this cause. Then, if the totality is completed by its units, it will not need this cause either. Rather, a certain thing may be a cause of some of the units to the exclusion of some [others]. Such a thing is not a cause of the totality in an absolute manner. 14. Remark: If a Chain of Consecutive Causes and Effects includes an Uncaused Cause, That Cause Must Be an Extremity Every totality organized of causes and effects consecutively, including a non-caused cause, has this uncaused cause as an extremity; for if this cause were an intermediate, it would be caused. 15. Remark: since That Uncaused Cause Must Be a Limit, it Must Be a Necessary Being in itself It has become clear that every chain organized of causes and effects, be it finite or infinite, is in need of a cause external to it if it does not include anything save effects. It is necessary that this external cause be linked to it as an extremity. It has also become clear that if this chain includes an uncaused thing, then this thing is an extremity and a limit. Therefore every chain terminates in that whose existence is necessary in itself. 17. Remark: The Existence of a Thing Cannot Be Caused by That Thing s Quiddity, Which is Not Existence It is permissible that the quiddity of a thing is a cause of one of the attributes of that thing and that one of the attributes of that thing is a cause of another attribute, as the specific difference is a cause of property. 4 However, it is not permissible that existence, which is an attribute of a thing, be verily caused by that thing s quiddity, which is not existence, or by another attribute. This is because the cause is prior in existence, and nothing is prior in existence to existence. 4 As rational is a cause of laughter.

18. Remark: Proof for the Unity of the Necessary in Existence That whose existence is necessary is something specific. If its specificity is due to the fact that it is that whose existence is necessary, then there is nothing else whose existence is necessary. If, on the other hand, its specificity is not due to this but to something else, then it is caused. This is because (1) if the existence of that whose existence is necessary necessarily attaches to its specificity, then existence necessarily attaches to the quiddity or to an attribute of something other than it. But this is impossible. (2) If the existence of that whose existence is necessary is an accident [to its specificity], then it is more appropriate that this existence be due to [an external] cause. (3) If that which specifies that whose existence is necessary is an accident of its specificity, then that which specifies is also due to a cause. If its specificity and that by means of which it is specified are one quiddity, then the cause is a cause of the singularity of that whose existence is necessary by essence. But this is impossible. (4) Finally, if its occurrence as an accident is posterior to the specificity of a prior first thing, then our discourse is about that prior thing and the remaining divisions are impossible. The REALLY Short Version from Al-Risāla Al- Arshiyya (The Treatise of the Throne) translated by George Hourani (1972) The First Principle: Establishment of the Necessary of Existence Know that every existent either has a cause for its existence or has no cause. If it has a cause it is something possible If it has no cause in any way for its existence it is necessary of existence. If this doctrine is accepted as true, the proof that there is in existence an existent having no cause for its existence is as I shall state. This existent is either possible of existence or necessary of existence. If it is necessary of existence our problem concerning it is settled at once. If it is possible of existence, the possible of existence enters into existence only by a cause which makes its existence outweigh its non-existence. But if its cause too is possible of existence, and in like manner there is a series of possibles dependent on one another, then there will be no existent at all, because this existent which we supposed does not enter into existence unless it is proceeded by an infinite series of existents, and that is impossible. Therefore possibles terminate in something necessary of existence.