The Mormon Review. Books and culture from an LDS perspective. Recovering Truth: A Review of Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method

Similar documents
THE CRISIS OF THE SCmNCES AS EXPRESSION OF THE RADICAL LIFE-CRISIS OF EUROPEAN HUMANITY

1/12. The A Paralogisms

The Scholar as Celebrant

INVESTIGATING THE PRESUPPOSITIONAL REALM OF BIBLICAL-THEOLOGICAL METHODOLOGY, PART II: CANALE ON REASON

Qué es la filosofía? What is philosophy? Philosophy

PART ONE: HANS-GEORG GADAMER AND THE DECLINE OF TRADITION

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Edmund Husserl s Transcendental Phenomenology by Wendell Allan A. Marinay

ST 501 Method and Praxis in Theology

PART FOUR: CATHOLIC HERMENEUTICS

Wilhelm Dilthey and Rudolf Carnap on the Foundation of the Humanities. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

BCC Papers 5/2, May

On the Relation of Philosophy to the Theology Conference Seward 11/24/98

Theories of the mind have been celebrating their new-found freedom to study

The title of this collection of essays is a question that I expect many professional philosophers have

Strange bedfellows or Siamese twins? The search for the sacred in practical theology and psychology of religion

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Monday 4:15 6:00; Wednesday 1-3; Thursday 2-3

How Trustworthy is the Bible? (1) Written by Cornelis Pronk

Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

Mistaking Category Mistakes: A Response to Gilbert Ryle. Evan E. May

Admin Identifying ethical issues Ethics and philosophy The African worldview Ubuntu as an ethical theory

Foreword to Where s Wilber At? Ken Wilber s Integral Vision in the New Millennium. by Brad Reynolds

A RESPONSE TO "THE MEANING AND CHARACTERISTICS OF AN AMERICAN THEOLOGY"

Response to Gregory Floyd s Where Does Hermeneutics Lead? Brad Elliott Stone, Loyola Marymount University ACPA 2017

Introduction to Philosophy

Lincoln-Douglas: The Inquistive Debate of Philosophy

How to Teach The Writings of the New Testament, 3 rd Edition Luke Timothy Johnson

THE UNITY OF THEOLOGY

Philosophical Traditions and Educational Research

Dave Elder-Vass Of Babies and Bathwater. A Review of Tuukka Kaidesoja Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

ETHICS AND THE FUTURE OF HUMANKIND, REALITY OF THE HUMAN EXISTENCE

Reading Engineer s Concept of Justice in Islam: The Real Power of Hermeneutical Consciousness (A Gadamer s Philosophical Hermeneutics)

CONSTRUCTIVE ENGAGEMENT DIALOGUE SEARLE AND BUDDHISM ON THE NON-SELF SORAJ HONGLADAROM

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

Hume on Ideas, Impressions, and Knowledge

ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis

Some Notes Toward a Genealogy of Existential Philosophy Robert Burch

What one needs to know to prepare for'spinoza's method is to be found in the treatise, On the Improvement

Phenomenology: a historical perspective. The purpose of this session is to explain the historical context in which

Are Miracles Identifiable?

The CopernicanRevolution

INTRODUCTION: CHARISMA AND RELIGIOUS LEADERSHIP DOUGLAS A. HICKS

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

In this lecture I am going to introduce you to the methodology of philosophy logic and argument

PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY

Kevin Liu 21W.747 Prof. Aden Evens A1D. Truth and Rhetorical Effectiveness

The Ground Upon Which We Stand

Keywords: Knowledge Organization. Discourse Community. Dimension of Knowledge. 1 What is epistemology in knowledge organization?

BOOK REVIEW. Jeffrey Mishlove, Ph.D. University of Philosophical Research

Tokai University / The University of Tokyo Tadashi TAKENOUCHI

MODELS CLARIFIED: RESPONDING TO LANGDON GILKEY. by David E. Klemm and William H. Klink

PHILOSOPHY AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES

Chapter 15. Elements of Argument: Claims and Exceptions

Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

[MJTM 17 ( )] BOOK REVIEW

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

Jacob Martin Rump, PhD Symposium: Contemporary Work in Phenomenology Boston Phenomenology Circle Boston University, 1 April 2016

Heidegger s Unzuhandenheit as a Fourth Mode of Being

Religious belief, hypothesis and attitudes

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Tuesday 1-3, Wednesday 1-3, and by appointment

Book Review: Badiou, A. (2007). The Century, Oxford, UK: Polity Press.

Christian Evidences. The Verification of Biblical Christianity, Part 2. CA312 LESSON 06 of 12

Markie, Speckles, and Classical Foundationalism

UNITY IN BIBLICAL UNDERSTANDING

The Ethics of Self Realization: A Radical Subjectivism, Bounded by Realism. An Honors Thesis (HONR 499) Kevin Mager. Thesis Advisor Jason Powell

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

Religious Instruction, Religious Studies and Religious Education

Consciousness might be defined as the perceiver of mental phenomena. We might say that there are no differences between one perceiver and another, as

The Quest for Knowledge: A study of Descartes. Christopher Reynolds

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Class #13 - The Consciousness Theory of the Self Locke, The Prince and the Cobbler Reid, Of Mr. Locke's Account of Our Personal Identity

[JGRChJ 9 (2013) R28-R32] BOOK REVIEW

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Reference, mimesis, and application: An examination of Gadamer's rehabilitation of allegory

William Meehan Essay on Spinoza s psychology.

Interpreting Scripture/Interpreting Law

Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules

II. THE SACRAMENT OF PENANCE THE SOCIAL ASPECT OF THE SACRAMENT OF PENANCE

Ethics in a Historical View & A Framework for Ethical Decision Making

! Jumping ahead 2000 years:! Consider the theory of the self.! What am I? What certain knowledge do I have?! Key figure: René Descartes.

Class 33 - November 13 Philosophy Friday #6: Quine and Ontological Commitment Fisher 59-69; Quine, On What There Is

LIMPOPO BIBLE INSTITUE SETH MEYERS 1

Journal of Religion & Film

The Holy See PASTORAL VISIT IN NEW ZEALAND ADDRESS OF JOHN PAUL II TO THE BISHOPS. Wellington (New Zealand), 23 November 1986

Method in Theology. A summary of the views of Bernard Lonergan, i taken from his book, Method in Theology. ii

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

A Church for Every People and the Gospel for Every Person by the year 2000

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

Syllabus. Primary Sources, 2 edition. Hackett, Various supplementary handouts, available in class and on the course website.

VIEWING PERSPECTIVES

By submitting this essay, I attest that it is my own work, completed in accordance with University regulations. Minh Alexander Nguyen

The Human Science Debate: Positivist, Anti-Positivist, and Postpositivist Inquiry. By Rebecca Joy Norlander. November 20, 2007

WHY SHOULD ANYONE BELIEVE ANYTHING AT ALL?

Transcription:

Books and culture from an LDS perspective Recovering Truth: A Review of Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2 nd, revised ed, translation revised by Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (New York: Continuum, 2004), 584 pages; subject index, author index. By James E. Faulconer A German philosophy book written under the influence of Heidegger. In fact, a long German philosophy book written under the influence of Heidegger. The result has the difficulties attendant on German philosophy (page after page of long sentences, learned references to works that almost no English speaker has read) as well as those attendant on Heidegger s influence (page after page of abstruse thought, invented vocabulary). Nevertheless, every scholar in the human sciences (the arts, the humanities, philosophy, history, the social sciences) should take the time and energy to read the book. Perhaps those in the natural sciences should also read it. Why? Because it gives us an alternative theory of understanding that offers to take the place of the theories of knowledge on which we have come too heavily to rely. Those theories have made aesthetics into mere aesthetics, mere expression of feeling rather than claims of truth. They have made morality into a matter of deciding right and wrong (often relative only to the feelings of some human group), but an endeavor in which the question of truth is irrelevant. And they have made practical questions into decisions about efficiency irrespective of truth. Modern epistemology has robbed the humanities and social sciences of truth; Gadamer s hermeneutics gives it back again. Natural science is the model for modern epistemology: That which the sciences know is that which is truly known. The natural sciences necessarily rely on method: they reduce Editor-in-Chief Richard Lyman Bushman Managing Editor Rosalynde F. Welch Assistant Managing Editors Kaimipono Wenger Benjamin Huff Editorial Board Richard Bushman James Faulconer Daniel Fairbanks Terryl Givens Benjamin Huff Nathan B. Oman Jana Riess Jonathan Stapley Kaimipono Wenger Margaret Blair Young The Mormon Review publishes reviews of all aspects of contemporary culture from a Mormon perspective. Back issues are available online at: www.mormonreview.org Unsolicited submissions are welcome. Please see our website for submission guidelines or email us at: mormonreview@gmail.com www.mormonreview.org September 27, 2010 vol.2 no.2, page 1

the objects of their investigation to what is constant and measurable in those objects, they use theories and empirical rules to order their objects into sets of observations, and they test their observations with methods that guarantee them (relatively) invariable outcomes. Obviously the human sciences have no comparable method, and in light of the importance of natural science in our culture, the absence of such a method with its outcomes and their certainty has resulted in the aforementioned claims. If natural science is the model for knowledge, then our response to art is nothing but subjective feeling. If we agree that the natural sciences are the ideal model for all human knowledge, then such results are unavoidable. But Gadamer saves the human sciences from that inevitability. So how does Gadamer perform this rescue of art, philosophy, history, praxis, and human selfunderstanding? By reminding us that we have long had, but forgotten, a different model, a model that does not rely on method, a model of understanding found in the arts and the interpretation of texts rather than in the knowledge of abstract objects. Gadamer s argument is that the human sciences are interpretive sciences. Just as a musical score must be interpreted / enacted by the performer and a play has to be interpreted / enacted by the actors, a text (including a social text) must be interpreted / enacted by its readers. The reader doesn t report what the text invariably says each and every time it is read, something that could be methodologically verified. There is no such thing to be reported; that is not how we know the truth of a text. Rather, the reader produces what the text says, its truth, by reading it and making sense of it. It is tautologically true that without readers texts say nothing, and Gadamer reminds us of that tautology. It follows that we know the truth of a text only through what happens when we read it, where reading is a matter of enactment. To say that I understand something is to say that I can make sense of it in my situation. One could say that I can translate it into that which I understand. I cannot do so arbitrarily or I am not translating any more than the musical artist or the actor can make just anything out of the score or the script and still be playing this particular music or acting in that particular play. Likewise, I may feel something with regard to what I translate, but that feeling is not the same as my understanding, nor does it give rise to my understanding. The good reader uses the score of the text to produce a reading that others can hear, appreciate, or argue with. The text / score stands as an arbiter of our interpretations, but the truth of the score exists only in our productions of it. Without the production by a reader, the text says nothing at all. What do the musician, the actor, the translator, and the reader produce from their texts? The truth of those texts, a truth that is not objective, but is also not merely subjective since we can make informed judgments about good, better, and best. Truth is central to interpretation and, Gadamer argues, legal and homiletic interpretation give us models that have the question of truth at their heart. According to Gadamer, if we look to the law and www.mormonreview.org September 24, 2010, vol.2 no.2, page 2

preaching for our models of understanding, we will discover that they are always embedded in a tradition and history that go beyond that of which we are conscious, and we will see that the enactment or production of a text necessarily depends on tradition. But tradition doesn t mean doing the same thing that has always been done. It means having a body of understanding and practice on which one can draw in coming to an understanding and into which one intends to fit the interpretation that shows that understanding. To interpret within the tradition is to continue it and to make it anew. It is to place oneself in relation to the tradition by remaking the tradition. It is to allow the possibilities inherent in the tradition to show themselves through the interpretation and, thereby, to create new possibilities. The common law judge must take account of previous judgments. He need not conform to those previous decisions in some lock-step fashion, but he must be able to give an account of how his decision fits with those that were previously rendered, even if his decision is at odds with some previous decisions. Even if his decision overturns the previous decisions. His judgment must also take his audience into account, not only those on whom he renders judgment, but the public at large and future judges facing similar cases. But none of that prevents him from ruling decisively and in a way that continues the flow of tradition. Indeed, such judgments are the essence of that continued flow. Likewise, a good preacher can give her sermon only if she knows not only the verses of scripture for the sermon, but also the ways in which others have understood those verses, the way the church has used them, how they have been important to the ecclesial tradition, and so on. And the preacher must know the audience: what they know, what they need to know, what kinds of people they are, how they will hear what she says,. The truth of the text appears in preaching that takes these things into account, and it doesn t appear to the degree that they are ignored. Also at play in every interpretation are our prejudices, a word that Gadamer uses quite literally: pre-judgments rather than unfounded judgments. Those prejudgments are substantially formed, consciously or unconsciously, by the tradition in which we find ourselves. They may, unbeknownst to us, influence our understanding. Or we can use reason to question them and reject or refine them and, in the process, create new prejudgments. What we cannot do is avoid them, and we ought not to seek to do so since it is only by means of them that we can make our interpretations and it is only by making interpretations that we discover some of our prejudgments, making it possible for us to make decisions concerning them. Gadamer asks us to understand that pronouncing legal judgments or preaching sermons in the context of one s tradition is a matter of application (not that interpretation is the same as application, but that one does not occur without the other). The judge applies the ruling to those against whom the case was brought; the preacher applies the verses of the homily to the members of the congregation. But when Gadamer speaks of application, he isn t talking www.mormonreview.org September 24, 2010, vol.2 no.2, page 3

only about consciously applying a principle to a case at hand. That would too narrowly construe what application means. A reader who applies the text applies the meaning to herself, understands what it means to her and by extension to others as well. But when done well that is not a merely subjective judgment, any more than the judge s application of the common law to the defendant is a merely subjective judgment. As these elements of interpretation (historical context or tradition, prejudice or pre-judgment, and application) show, full human understanding is unavoidably temporal. Full human understanding and the truth of that understanding is historical in character. In contrast, natural science must remove history from consideration to do its work. It must abstract from the historical world. That is a criticism of neither natural science nor its methods, but it means that natural science is an abstraction from full human understanding rather than the model of that understanding. It means that there are truths, historically situated and determined ones, that natural science is illequipped to deal with. Humanists in general should read Truth and Method, but even nonhumanist Mormons with an interest in things scholarly or intellectual should. We should consider Gadamer s thinking about understanding because as a group we are as much under the sway of scientism as anyone. One result is the sometimes pseudo-scientific way we talk about such things as faith, conversion, and covenant. Another, the mirror image of the first, is the tragic rejection of faith, conversion, or covenant because they turn out not to be amenable to scientific method. Both those relations of people to their faith explicitly but mistakenly take natural science as the fundamental model for human understanding. Gadamer gives us a philosophical alternative to that mistake. A third result of our scientism is the too-often shallow way that we understand scripture and prophecy, thinking of them as a poorly-written or at least cryptic manuals of instruction, seldom finding in them the depth of knowledge that is possible and that would enrich our faith. We look for a method for interpreting scripture when we should be asking how to enact its truth. Gadamer helps us see that we have long had better ways of reading scripture. The person who has done the most thinking about how a Gadamerian understanding of truth applies to scripture reading is Paul Ricoeur in, for example, Figuring the Sacred or The Self in the Mirror of Scripture (in John McCarthy, ed., The Whole and Divided Self). And Ricoeur has written thoughtful responses to scripture in Thinking Biblically: Exegetical and Hermeneutical Studies, with André LaCoque. Most of the essays in the various seminars of the Mormon Theology Seminar (http://www.mormontheol ogyseminar.org/) are excellent examples of Latter-day Saints thinking about scripture in ways that are coherent with Gadamer s understanding of truth and understanding, which is not to say that the participants are consciously exemplifying that connection. By providing an antidote to modernism s insistence that natural science is the model for all real knowledge, showing an alternative way of understanding knowledge that doesn t throw scientific www.mormonreview.org September 24, 2010, vol.2 no.2, page 4

knowledge out with the alternative bathwater, Gadamer opens the possibility for Mormons to understand the Latter-day Saint movement more genuinely as a restoration rather than merely a peculiar instantiation of modern self-consciousness. Richard Bushman: My question is why call Gadamer's way of reading an approach to truth? Gadamer has systematically explored what happens when we read texts closely, but he offers no more hope of bringing us to a consensus of meaning that we can call truth than the other hermeneutics we employ in humanistic studies. Every tradition will read the texts differently and even readers within a tradition will disagree. Why call this truth? As it is presented here, Gadamer's method seems mainly to give us courage to repel scientism. It codifies and lends dignity to what humanists do. That is a worthy project indeed, but applying the word truth to the outcome implies that humanistic readings should command the same authority as scientific conclusions do. I doubt that will happen. Response to Richard: Gadamer isn't presenting a theory of reading, but a theory of truth in the human sciences. That requires that we revise our understanding of truth and its relation to reason, objectivity, and so on. He begins doing that by criticizing the history of philosophy, particularly Kant and the Romantics. His argument is that in response to the 18 th -century rationalists exclusion of art from the realm of knowledge, Kant and the Romantics reasserted the importance of art, but they did so in a way that, in spite of their intentions, ultimately devalued it. They said that art puts us in touch with some higher reality. Unfortunately, that turned out to mean that aesthetic understanding lost all content and determinacy. Instead of understanding art in terms of content (truth), Kant and the Romantics took it to be a matter of subjective consciousness. By the middle of the 19 th century that became the most common understanding of aesthetic meaning and it remains the most common understanding today: the content of art is a matter of merely subjective consciousness, a matter of individual preference. Gadamer's alternative (which depends explicitly and heavily on Heidegger s thought, as well as, less obviously, the work of Willhelm Dilthey) is to argue that the understanding of art is always a matter of historical understanding. The truth of art is historical, and as historical it is also a matter of self-understanding, a coming-to-know that is not the result of objective method and the certainty it produces: Self-understanding always occurs through understanding something other than the self, and includes the unity and integrity of the other. Since we meet the artwork in the world and encounter a world in the individual artwork, the work of art is not some alien universe into which we are magically transported for a time. Rather, we learn to understand ourselves in and through it. (83) Self-understanding has public, shareable content. It has truth. The performer does something that others can see, understand, discuss, and judge. But that truth cannot be reduced to any www.mormonreview.org September 24, 2010, vol.2 no.2, page 5

constant or objectively measurable principle or set of characteristics. Descartes' "I think therefore I am" is not a moment of selfunderstanding, and the certainty for which Cartesian thought searches has nothing to do with selfunderstanding. (As Jean- Luc Marion points out in The Erotic Phenomenon, Descartes explicitly omits love from the list of things that characterize the ego, though surely love is essential to selfunderstanding. For more on the absence of selfunderstanding in the Cartesian cogito, see Ricoeur s The Course of Recognition.) The search for objective certainty that follows from the Cartesian foundation is irrelevant to areas of human endeavor, such as art or history, where self-understanding is the goal. Looking for certainty, or something like it, in the human sciences is a category mistake. Subjectivity doesn t follow from the fact that the truth of the human sciences is found in selfunderstanding rather than certainty. One cannot ignore the temporal / historical dimension of the content of selfunderstanding, though one must ignore that dimension of objective (natural science) understanding. There is truth in both arenas, but they are not the same kinds of truth, so it is a mistake to try to understand matters in one of those arenas using the standards for truth of the other, though that is what we have most often done, using the standards for truth in science to judge the truth claims of art and the other human sciences, such as history. That means that the answer to whether Gadamer's theory gives us a method for deciding with certainty between the claims of different traditions is emphatically, no. In fact, the demand for such a method is an instance of the very thing he is arguing against. It is a demand that takes objective science as its model of understanding. But Gadamer s theory does not preclude us from deciding between traditions: different traditions are not cut off from each other. Does this historicism mean that we are reduced to sheer relativity? No (first) because for the most part we stand within the same broad tradition. There is more overlap between most of our traditions, if we are North Americans or Western Europeans, for example, than there is difference. Because we are human beings there is considerable overlap between any two traditions. And no (second) because languages and therefore traditions are translatable. That I can understand Korean means that it is in principle possible for me to "fuse" my historic-temporal horizon with a Korean one. (See Gadamer s discussion on pages 303-306.) We can understand other traditions, and if we can, we can judge them. In fact, we cannot avoid doing so. Our judgments will have the status of temporal knowledge real knowledge, knowledge of truth but not the status of objective certainty, another kind of truth, abstract abstracted truth. Should humanistic readings command the same authority as scientific conclusions? Yes and no. Since they concern the ground of what make natural scientific conclusions possible (they take account of the material from which natural science makes its abstractions), they should command more rather than the same or less authority. But the authority they claim is the authority of self-understanding rather than the authority of www.mormonreview.org September 24, 2010, vol.2 no.2, page 6

objective certainty. They should claim authority only in the realm to which they are relevant, which is not the realm of the natural sciences but is the realm of human existence. James E. Faulconer is a professor of philosophy and a Richard L. Evans Professor of Religious Understanding at Brigham Young University. He is the husband of one, the father of four, and the grandfather of eleven. When he s not doing philosophy, he likes to cook and eat. www.mormonreview.org September 24, 2010, vol.2 no.2, page 7