The Philosophical Review, Vol. 110, No. 3. (Jul., 2001), pp

Similar documents
The Philosophical Review, Vol. 100, No. 3. (Jul., 1991), pp

Philosophical Review.

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Reply to Lorne Falkenstein RAE LANGTON. Edinburgh University

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Important dates. PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since David Hume ( )

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Philosophical Review.

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Kant Lecture 4 Review Synthetic a priori knowledge

7AAN2039 Kant I: Critique of Pure Reason Syllabus Academic year 2015/16

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism


The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 83, No. 5. (May, 1986), pp

Today we turn to the work of one of the most important, and also most difficult, philosophers: Immanuel Kant.

History of Education Society

Modern Philosophy II

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Today we turn to the work of one of the most important, and also most difficult, philosophers: Immanuel Kant.

Philosophy Courses-1

Philosophy Courses-1

Examining the nature of mind. Michael Daniels. A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000).

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

Wilhelm Dilthey and Rudolf Carnap on the Foundation of the Humanities. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Hume on Ideas, Impressions, and Knowledge

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought

Reading Questions for Phil , Fall 2016 (Daniel)

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Descartes and Schopenhauer on Voluntary Movement:

Immanuel Kant, Analytic and Synthetic. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics Preface and Preamble

FIL 4600/10/20: KANT S CRITIQUE AND CRITICAL METAPHYSICS

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

PHILOSOPHY IAS MAINS: QUESTIONS TREND ANALYSIS

Courses providing assessment data PHL 202. Semester/Year

The British Empiricism

THE CRISIS OF THE SCmNCES AS EXPRESSION OF THE RADICAL LIFE-CRISIS OF EUROPEAN HUMANITY

Under contract with Oxford University Press Karen Bennett Cornell University

ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis

Theories of the mind have been celebrating their new-found freedom to study

An Empiricist Theory of Knowledge Bruce Aune

Kate Moran Brandeis University

KNOWLEDGE OF SELF AND THE WORLD

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Kant s Transcendental Exposition of Space and Time in the Transcendental Aesthetic : A Critique

This paper serves as an enquiry into whether or not a theory of metaphysics can grow

COURSE GOALS: PROFESSOR: Chris Latiolais Philosophy Department Kalamazoo College Humphrey House #202 Telephone # Offices Hours:


Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Philosophy (PHILOS) Courses. Philosophy (PHILOS) 1

Copyright 2000 Vk-Cic Vahe Karamian

Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness

Philosophy 301L: Early Modern Philosophy, Spring 2011

Kant and his Successors

PH 329: Seminar in Kant Fall 2010 L.M. Jorgensen

George Berkeley. The Principles of Human Knowledge. Review

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2014

Journal of Philosophy, Inc.

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Critical Discussion of A. W. Moore s Critique of Kant

CONTENTS III SYNTHETIC A PRIORI JUDGEMENTS. PREFACE CHAPTER INTRODUCTldN

Descartes to Early Psychology. Phil 255

Dualism: What s at stake?

Kantian Realism. Jake Quilty-Dunn. Kantian Realism 75

PHILOSOPHY (PHIL) Philosophy (PHIL) 1. PHIL HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY Short Title: HIST INTRO TO PHILOSOPHY

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

PHILOSOPHY (PHIL) Philosophy (PHIL) 1. PHIL 56. Research Integrity. 1 Unit

7AAN2039 Kant I: Critique of Pure Reason 2012/13

UNIVERSITY OF CALICUT SCHOOL OF DISTANCE EDUCATION

Kant's philosophy of the self.

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

Chalmers, "Consciousness and Its Place in Nature"

Lecture 18: Rationalism

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

INVESTIGATING THE PRESUPPOSITIONAL REALM OF BIBLICAL-THEOLOGICAL METHODOLOGY, PART II: CANALE ON REASON

Department of Philosophy TCD. Great Philosophers. Dennett. Tom Farrell. Department of Surgical Anatomy RCSI Department of Clinical Medicine RCSI

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Tuesday 1-3, Wednesday 1-3, and by appointment

Previous Final Examinations Philosophy 1

Primary and Secondary Qualities. John Locke s distinction between primary and secondary qualities of bodies has

Nagel, Naturalism and Theism. Todd Moody. (Saint Joseph s University, Philadelphia)

Perspectival Methods in Metaphysics

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins

IN THIS PAPER I will examine and criticize the arguments David

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7b The World

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

Lecture 4: Transcendental idealism and transcendental arguments

1/9. The First Analogy

Today we turn to the work of one of the most important, and also most difficult, of philosophers: Immanuel Kant.

BonJour Against Materialism. Just an intellectual bandwagon?

History of Modern Philosophy

A note on Bishop s analysis of the causal argument for physicalism.

Transcription:

Review: [Untitled] Reviewed Work(s): Problems from Kant by James Van Cleve Rae Langton The Philosophical Review, Vol. 110, No. 3. (Jul., 2001), pp. 451-454. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0031-8108%28200107%29110%3a3%3c451%3apfk%3e2.0.co%3b2-y The Philosophical Review is currently published by Cornell University. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/sageschool.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers, and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. http://www.jstor.org Fri Jul 20 15:50:59 2007

BOOK REVLEWS?'he Philosophical Reuieu, Vol. 110, No. 3 Uuly 2001) PROBLEMS FROM KANT By JAMES VAN CLEW. New York: Oxford University Press, 1999. Pp. xii, 340. This book will be enjoyed not only by those philosophers interested in Kant, but by those interested in metaphysics and epistemology more generally. Van Cleve is fascinated both by Kant and by the problems that fascinated Kant; so in attending to Kant's arguments about space, substance, the a priori (for example), we learn much about space, substance, the a priori. He writes with directness, accessibility, and care; there can be few recent books on the problems of Kant's First Critiquethat treat so great a range of arguments with such seriousness and sophistication. (It is no accident they are often problems that the author himself has addressed effectively elsewhere). As to the seriousness, Kant's central doctrines (about synthetic a priori truths, transcendental idealism, things in themselves) are confronted and evaluated, without the least attempt to dilute them. Van Cleve is a sympathetic interpreter, often finding himself on Kant's side: Kant is right about synthetic a priori truths; more surprisingly, he is right about things in themselves. And while Kant's transcendental idealism is ultimately to be rejected (not prettified), we should reject it only after looking it clear in the eye and acknowledging its centrality. Clarity and rigor are among the book's notable virtues. There are commentators whose idea of doing Kant justice is to stay as close to him as possible; if Kant says "it follows from this...,"they too will loyally say "it follows from this...," without suggesting how the "it" could possibly "follow." Van Cleve is, thankfully, not among them. Arguments are displayed in numbered premise-and-conclusion format (using formalism where appropriate), setting an enviable standard of precision for ongoing discussion, without unduly compromising readability. One is reminded of Bennett in some aspects of style (the rigor, the engagingly personal sense of one philosopher arguing with another) and content (phenomena as "logical constructions" of conscious states). There is an impressive knowledge of the contemporary English-language Kant literature; a wide-ranging ability to draw upon relevant work in contemporary philosophy on, for example, supervenience and antirealism; and enlightening use of other texts (e.g., the Inaug.ural Dissertation and the Metaplzysical Foundations of Natural Science) and other figures (such as Leibniz, Lambert, Berkeley)-all of which make a book that is admirably comprehensive in scope. An unusual feature is a section of tiny, self-contained appendices, on questions as diverse as whether something could be red and green all over; why Kant once argued from incongruent counterparts to absolute space; whether Kant's "synthesis" is a solution to the "binding problem" identified by

BOOK REVLEWS experimental psychologists. In their precision, originality, and brevity, these are gems of analysis, which would prove as useful for introducing students to these topics as for shedding light on Kant. Disagreements of interpretation aside, my only complaint is that, in the course of one's journey through this expansive volume, one can occasionally lose sense of the overall narrative. I take up one theme, the distinction between phenomena and things in themselves. According to van Cleve, it is a fundamentally idealist distinction: Virtual us. Real: Phenomena are virtual objects (logical constructions of conscious states), things in themselves are real objects. On this distinction, we have a metaphysics of two worlds, two sorts of objects, virtual and real; and an epistemology that makes ignorance of things in themselves ignorance of the real. I focus on one argument, of special interest to me because it draws on Kant's idea that the phenomenal realm is one of "mere relations"-an idea that has not typically been credited with the importance it merits. Van Cleve asks us to consider the following passage: [Elverything in our knowledge which belongs to intuition... contains nothing but mere relations; namely of locations in an intuition (extension), of change in location (motion), and of laws according to which this change is determined (moving forces). What it is that is present in this or that location, or what it is that is operative in the things themselves apart from change of location, is not given through intuition. Now a thing in itself cannot be known through mere relations; and we may therefore conclude that since outer sense gives us nothing but mere relations, this sense can contain in its representation only the relation of an object to the subject, and not the inner properties of the object in itself. (B67) This suggests an interpretation of Kant's distinction that is not fundamentally idealist: Relational us. Int~insic: Phenomena are the relational aspects of things which have (in themselves) an intrinsic nature. (Similar passages from the Amphiboly, and elsewhere, suggest it, and I myself argue for it in detail elsewhere.)' On this distinction we have a metaphysics of one world with two classes of properties, relational and intrinsic, and an epistemology that says ignorance of things in themselves is not idealism, but epistemic humility: what is denied to us is not any access whatever to ihese things, but only knowledge of their intrinsic or non-relational features.... the phrase 'knowledge of things as they appear' contrasts not with 'knowledge of things as they real& are' but with 'knowledge of things as they intnnsical2y are'. (150) '~aelangton, Kantian Humility: Our Ignorance of Things in Themselves (Oxford: Oxford University Press, Clarendon Press, 1998).

BOOK REVIEWS We reach the Relational vs. Intrinsic interpretation, van Cleve says, if we interpret B67 epistemologically, like this (153): Syllogism 1 1. All we know about objects through outer sense is what relations they stand in. 2. To know how an object is in itself is to know how it is in nonrelational respects. 3. Therefore, we do not know through outer sense how objects are in themselves. (153) This commits Kant to one world of objects that have two classes of properties, relational and intrinsic, the latter unknown. (What of paradigm intrinsic properties, shape, solidity? Kant's answer is that such properties are ultimately relational-that bodies are constituted by (relational) forces of attraction and repulsion.) But van Cleve rejects Syllogism 1, preferring instead the metaphysical Syllogism 2 1. The only properties had by objects of outer sense are relational properties. 2. A thing in itself cannot have relational properties only. 3. Therefore, objects of outer sense are not things in themselves (but only appearances). He takes Syllogism 2 to favor the Virtual vs. Real interpretation. Why? Chiefly (though there are more reasons) because he takes Kant to assume that real things must have intrinsic properties (2); given that bodies have no intrinsic properties (I), they are not real (3). However, Syllogism 2 can be interpreted as entirely consistent with Syllogism 1: it states a metaphysical aspect of the Relational vs. Intrinsic distinction. Things in themselves must have intrinsic properties (2); given that bodies have no intrinsic properties (I), bodies are not things in themselves (3). It is compatible with this that bodies ("containing" only relational properties) are real; and that the relational properties belong to things that have an unknown intrinsic nature (Syllogism 1). Crucial to van Cleve's idealist interpretation is that the relations are not possessed by the things that have intrinsic properties. But B67 contradicts this. Kant says the something that presents itself in this or that location has unknown activities going on within it. He says outer sense represents only the relation of an object, not the intrinsic properties belonging to the object as it is in itself. The object bearing the relation is the object that has the intrinsic properties. So B67 undermines van Cleve's interpretation, and supports the idea of the in itself as the intrinsic. One can't hope to do justice here to either side, and the detail would take us through other arguments from van Cleve, and from Kant, about substance, 'van Cleve adds '(to us?)', querying whether Kant's thought concerns an object's relations to other things generally, or to us in particular-a question I haven't scope to go into here.

BOOK REVIEWS relations, and reducibility. For now, I shall simply stop with a reprise of my earlier verdict: this is a splendid book, to be enjoyed by anyone interested in Kant, or in the philosophical problems that gripped him. University ofedinburgh RAE LAUGTON The Philosophical Review, Vol. 110, No. 3 (July 2001) THE P m O X OF SiXj'JECTn/TTY: THE SELF IN THE TRANSCB~WEi\J-IM2 TRADITION. By DAVID CARR. New York: Oxford University Press, 1999.Pp. 150. David Carr's Paradox of Subjectivity is a brilliant and challenging defense of the legitimacy and distinctiveness of the transcendental tradition in modern philosophy. Carr's central claim is that the transcendental tradition is defined not by a metaphysical position, but rather by a methodological stance. Indeed, transcendentalism, he argues, involves no metaphysical commitments of any kind. He focuses this thesis by using it to address the later Heidegger's charge that modern philosophy, from Descartes through to Nietzsche, and maybe Husserl too, is essentially a metaphysics of the subject. Carr introduces his suggestion by appropriating the approach to Kant's transcendental idealism pioneered by Gerold Prauss and Henry Allison. Kant's transcendental and empirical standpoints are not rival factual perspectives, as perhaps psychology and physiology are. Rather, they are different methodological positions. The empirical standpoint, analogously with Husserl's "natural attitude," takes the world as given and explores it factually. The transcendental standpoint reflects on the subjective conditions that make it possible for the world to be an object for us. From the transcendental standpoint, we do not make, retract, or even epistemologically evaluate any ontic commitments we might make or be tempted to make. That is, we neither assert nor deny the existence of the world or anything in it, nor do we evaluate the cogency of the evidence we have for the existence of the world or anything in it. Using Husserlian language, Carr explains that transcendental philosophy "brackets" the actual existence of the world and instead focuses on, and investigates the structure of, the world as object, the meaning of the world. Carr contrasts this transcendental approach within philosophy with the metaphysical concerns of Kant's predecessors. Descartes posited a mental substance, as well as mysterious, purely subjective entities, "ideas," to explain how the world is an object of human consciousness. This turns philosophy into a poor cousin of psychology. Hume responded to Descartes with a healthy skepticism toward the entities posited and explanations offered within the Cartesian system. Descartes takes the self to be an odd sort of entity,