is the edification of Christians. Clark asks some very penetrating questions, such as: Is it necessary to have saving faith?

Similar documents
Chapter Summaries: Three Types of Religious Philosophy by Clark, Chapter 1

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Delton Lewis Scudder: Tennant's Philosophical Theology. New Haven: Yale University Press xiv, 278. $3.00.

WEEK 3 IMPUTATION OF SIN AND RIGHTEOUSNESS ROMANS 3:21-4:25

True and Reasonable Faith Theistic Proofs

A Studying of Limitation of Epistemology as Basis of Toleration with Special Reference to John Locke

THE INTERNAL TESTIMONY OF THE HOLY SPIRIT: HOW DO YOU KNOW THAT THE BIBLE IS GOD S WORD?

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

[1938. Review of The Philosophy of St. Bonaventure, by Etienne Gilson. Westminster Theological Journal Nov.]

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

The Rationality Of Faith

Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008

Doctrine #2: The Bible: Inspired of God

The Sermons of Dan Duncan. James 2:14-26

God has a mind- Romans 11:34 "who has known the mind of the Lord

The Trinity Review / January, February 2004

Christians have no idea of many of the doctrines of the Christian religion, and are

spring 05 topics in philosophy of mind session 7

I John Intro. Purpose Author Date Key Verse Outline

VERIFICATION AND METAPHYSICS

A Wesleyan Approach to Knowledge

PHIL 480: Seminar in the History of Philosophy Building Moral Character: Neo-Confucianism and Moral Psychology

How to Mistake a Trivial Fact About Probability For a. Substantive Fact About Justified Belief

Nearly everyone, at one time or another, has an incredible

THE SPIRIT OF ANTICHRIST: DECOUPLING JESUS FROM THE CHR- IST*

PROLOGUE TO PRISON. Paul's Epistle to the ROMANS. by Richard C. Halverson Cowman Publishing Company, Inc. Chapter 12 THE FREE GIFT OF GOD

Cajetan, On Faith and Works (1532)

A Historical and Ecumenical Look at Baptism

Task 1: Philosophical Questions. Question 1: To what extent do you shape your own destiny, and how much is down to fate?

Notes on Bertrand Russell s The Problems of Philosophy (Hackett 1990 reprint of the 1912 Oxford edition, Chapters XII, XIII, XIV, )

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Building Systematic Theology

DALLAS BAPTIST UNIVERSITY THE ILLOGIC OF FAITH: FEAR AND TREMBLING IN LIGHT OF MODERNISM SUBMITTED TO THE GENTLE READER FOR SPRING CONFERENCE

SOLA FIDE FAITH ALONE Sermon preached by Pastor C. John Steer Autumn Ridge Church October 14-15, 2017

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo

Illustrating Deduction. A Didactic Sequence for Secondary School

THE FORM OF REDUCTIO AD ABSURDUM J. M. LEE. A recent discussion of this topic by Donald Scherer in [6], pp , begins thus:

Atone: To make amends for.

JUSTIFICATION, JUDGMENT AND THE JUDGE

THE APOLOGETICAL VALUE OF THE SELF-WITNESS OF SCRIPTURE

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

How to Write a Philosophy Paper

Chapter Summaries: Language and Theology by Clark, Chapter 2. on secular philosophies of language. Many religious writers, he states, deny the

First Treatise <Chapter 1. On the Eternity of Things>

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

Building Systematic Theology

The Fourth Commandment According to the Westminster Standards

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

Belief Ownership without Authorship: Agent Reliabilism s Unlucky Gambit against Reflective Luck Benjamin Bayer September 1 st, 2014

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Evidence and Transcendence

1/5. The Critique of Theology

356 THE MONIST all Cretans were liars. It can be put more simply in the form: if a man makes the statement I am lying, is he lying or not? If he is, t

1 Ted Kirnbauer Romans 4: /3/17. a. Abraham received the promise of that he would inherit the world by faith (4:13 16)

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

UNLESS YOU REPENT Matthew 3:2 Matthew 4:17 Matthew 11:20 Luke 5:32 Matthew 6:12 Acts 2:38

The Spirituality Wheel 4

Advent Sermon Transcript December 18, The Amen of Christmas Jesus: The Truth of God John 8:31-59

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Presuppositional Apologetics

Scripture: Authority, Canon & Criticism Final Exam Sample Questions

Reason and Argument. Richard Feldman Second Edition

Defend Your Faith Lesson 1

THE REFUTATION OF PHENOMENALISM

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2009

Two Approaches to Natural Law;Note

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE

Salvation The Sovereign Grace of our Triune God In Adam All Died Romans 5:12-21 Lesson 3 Trinity Bible Church Sunday School June 20, 2010

THE TRINITY REVIEW. What Is It to Believe on the Lord Jesus Christ? By Luke Miner

STUDY QUESTIONS. 1. What biblical and theological arguments oppose the origin of the human race by Darwinian evolution? (5)

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII

Being a Disciple. Ted Kirnbauer 1

PHILOSOPHY ESSAY ADVICE

An Inferentialist Conception of the A Priori. Ralph Wedgwood

The Biblical Doctrine of the Trinity W. Gary Crampton. knowledge of God. But the God of Scripture is Triune and to know God is to know him as Triune.

Cartesian Rationalism

PHILOSOPHY EPISTEMOLOGY ESSAY TOPICS AND INSTRUCTIONS

GREAT PHILOSOPHERS: Thomas Reid ( ) Peter West 25/09/18

Why Do People Reject Jesus Christ? John 5:40-47 Introduction

As your group time begins, use this section to help get the conversation going.

Karl Barth and Neoorthodoxy

Now consider a verb - like is pretty. Does this also stand for something?

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 5

WHERE ARE WE KNOW NOW?

Interest-Relativity and Testimony Jeremy Fantl, University of Calgary

Thinking Outside the Box

Lecture 4.2 Aquinas Phil Religion TOPIC: Aquinas Cosmological Arguments for the existence of God. Critiques of Aquinas arguments.

Comments on Scott Soames, Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, volume I

Knowledge is Not the Most General Factive Stative Attitude

Predicate logic. Miguel Palomino Dpto. Sistemas Informáticos y Computación (UCM) Madrid Spain

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

[1968. In Encyclopedia of Christianity. Edwin A. Palmer, ed. Wilmington, Delaware: National Foundation for Christian Education.]

Hume on Ideas, Impressions, and Knowledge

JOHN STUDIES. Bible Studies in the Gospel of John (4 lessons) Lesson #1: MAN Personal Discovery. Why should you...be interested in the Word of God?

Transcription:

Book Report: Faith and Saving Faith by Gordon H. Clark Gordon Clark s book Faith and Saving Faith, is a short monograph on a topic that is as pertinent now as it was when Clark wrote it. The motivation for this study for Clark is the edification of Christians. Clark asks some very penetrating questions, such as: Is it necessary to have saving faith? Must we know what saving faith is? Does one have to read the Bible or listen to sermons? What is the relation between faith and knowledge? In an example given by Clark using the thief on the cross next to Jesus, it is clear that he did not know much, but he knew more than most people give him credit for. For instance, he knew: The charge of Christ The charge on himself That his condemnation was just God That Jesus had done nothing wrong He himself would die soon He didn t know much, but he obviously knew enough. However, Clark states specifically that, To suppose that ignorance is sufficient for a Christian life is to be ignorant of what a Christian life requires. Clark begins his monograph by exploring the nature of Generic Faith before he explores the meaning and extent of saving faith. Faith can be Christian or non-christian, religious or secular. Firstly, Clark looks at secular philosophy of faith. 1

According to Brand Blanshard, as quoted in Clark, Belief, as central as it is in the life of thought, and perhaps because it is so essential, is indefinable and probably indescribable. Many Christians and non-christians and some secular philosophers, consider belief to be an emotion or a feeling. Blanshard, on the other hand, does not at least consider faith or believing to be sensing, emotional, or a desire. People can have no sensation of blue, for instance, without the intellectual interpretation of it. Clark looks at the writings of H.H. Price. He states that believing something for many years may not be an instantaneous act, but there must have been some point at which a person passes from ignorance, inattention, or even disbelief to a conscious acceptance of the proposition in question. Price also distinguished between believing in something or someone and believing that something or someone. Pilate believed that Jesus was innocent, but did not believe in Jesus. Price also discussed a distinction between knowledge by acquaintance and knowledge by description. However, to define and describe this difference can be complex at best and unintelligible at worst. Price also notes that in religious circles, belief in is more important than belief that. However Clark notes an objection to Price, that the difference between various beliefs lies in the objects or propositions believed, not in the nature of belief. Clark an Price agree somewhat that belief is not merely a cognitive attitude. There is the possibility that belief is a volitional act. Clark moves on to Roman Catholic views of faith or belief in the early Christians. For Augustine, faith was a voluntary assent to the truth. For Thomas Aquinas, faith concerns a reality, not a proposition. However, Clark argues that it is hard to credit the 2

idea that truth can be non-propositional. The single word cat is neither true nor false. The proposition, This cat is black may be true. But how can a subject minus a predicate be true all alone by itself? Thomas also stated that nothing can come under faith except God s truth. Nothing false has any place and nothing false can be an object of faith. Clark, however, shows that this is not true, because many people believe in false propositions all the time. However, Clark does note that saving faith must be belief in something God said, as opposed to something someone else said. Therefore the object of saving faith must be true and not a falsehood, because no one can be saved through believing a falsehood. Thomas, at length, considers that faith is assent to an understood proposition. It should be clear, notes Clark, that no one can believe what he does not know or understand. If the people do not know, then how can they say, amen? The Biblical writers constantly emphasize doctrine, knowledge, wisdom, and edification. Matthew 28:20 states to teach disciples all that Jesus commanded. A person cannot observe a doctrine or obey a command unless he knows it. Faith is strictly limited to knowledge. Clark discusses another catholic writer, D Arcy. He defines faith as the act whereby we believe without doubting whatever God has revealed. However, he confuses the definition of assent. Clark in section 5 discusses the Biblical data. He reviews both the Old Testament and the New Testament verses that use the term faith or a derivative of believe. The role of faith in the OT, he states, should not be minimized. Abraham, Jacob, Joseph, Moses, Gideon, David, and Daniel are all examples. Clark warns us that faith has two 3

distinct meanings in the Scriptures. One meaning is the mental act of believing, and the other, prominent in the pastoral epistles, means namely the set of propositions to be believed. A person can indeed hear words without understanding them, but he cannot believe them. Some theologians contrast faith and knowledge, but the contrast should not be between faith and knowledge but the different objects known or believed. Clark also reviews a number of other theologians that have something to say on faith. One is John Calvin. Calvin emphasizes knowledge, in particular the knowledge of God s promises. Hence, the object of belief is a proposition. Calvin denies in many places that the fall of man made man an irrational being. Calvin does much to expose the fallacy of the Romanist view of implicit faith (that one may believe the proposition that what the church teaches is true without actually knowing or believing in the content of that teaching), and supports explicit faith. He states that one actually has to know something to believe in it. Thomas Manton has an excellent commentary on James, but flounders on a few points, according to Clark. Dead faith, it is true, cannot save someone. This faith that James mentions is merely the belief in monotheism, and even the Muslims believe this. For salvation, men must not only accept the monotheistic position, but as well other propositions relating to the atonement. However, Manton marks that it was a mistake of the reformation age to make the promise rather than the person of Christ to be the formal object of faith. Clark asks, which Christ? A person can only be identified by a set of propositions. Manton makes the popular assertion that faith consists of notia, assensus, 4

and fiducia, but he doesn t define his terms, and makes faith consist of understanding, assent, and faith! John Owen, a tower of reformed theology, states that justifying faith is a subset of general faith, asserts that if one does not know what general faith is, then one cannot know what faith that justifies is. According to Clark, Owen does not make sufficiently clear the distinction between the two. Owen seems to say that all faith is assent, but justifying faith is a different variety of assent. Clark asserts that all of the evidence that Owen puts forth seems to show that it is not a different nature of faith, but a different object of faith, that matters. Justifying faith also seems to be the assent to some truths, but not all. Owen also says that faith is faith in Christ. But Clark states that if we substitute the word believe for faith, when we believe in a man, we actually believe what he says. Owen does state that believing is voluntary assent to an understood proposition. Charles Hodge also states that faith is assent to the truth. However, Hodge, according to Clark, is confused on some points because of his empirical epistemology. He seems to put too much dependence on sense and reason. Hodge seems to limit reason to the deduction of physical laws from sensory perceptions, but Clark would rather define it as the deduction of conclusions from premises. Some anti-christian writers have taken advantage of this vagueness to say that faith is irrational or unreasonable. Clark, however, holds that it is rational to believe what God reveals. However, Hodge is still orthodox, and states, Faith is not blind irrational conviction. In order to believe, we must know what we believe, and the grounds upon which our faith rests. 5

Clark then breaks and discusses an important topic, especially in today s church, the Biblical definitions of the head and the heart. Because so many theologians and pastors seem to differentiate between the head and the heart, Clark pauses to look at the Biblical use of the two terms, specifically to show as clearly as possible what the term heart means. Clark shows extensively through Scriptures that the heart is connected with thinking, non-emotional, propositional, and intellectual activity. There is ample Scriptural evidence that the term heart means the mind, intellect, the understanding. The NT uses the term heart about 160 times, and the basic meaning of the word is mind or intellect. Volition, usually the assent to intellectually understood propositions, is also a meaning, and emotion is rarely the point of the passage. B.B. Warfield begins his study of faith with word studies of believe. However, Warfield, while not denying the object of the verb believe can be a theological proposition, stresses the personal object more than Hodge. However, even Warfield acknowledges that any study of the OT cannot avoid the idea of promise, and that requires the object of faith to be a proposition. Other people that Clark discusses are John Anderson and J.H. Bavinck. Anderson seems to hold, after some discussion, that the object of faith is propositional. Bavinck, on the other hand, believes that language itself is inadequate to speak about God, and Clark then shows that if this were true, then why talk about God at all. The words of Jesus would have no meaning nor give us any knowledge. Clark also reviews the writings of John Theodore Mueller, a Lutheran theologian. He agrees that saving faith is always an explicit faith rather than the Romanist implicit faith. 6

After this extensive historical review of faith and what it means, Clark then moves to a discussion where he attempts to assemble together the data and show that faith is necessary to salvation. Clark reviews many Scriptures to show that without faith, salvation is impossible. Clark briefly discusses the issue of infants, and how can faith be necessary for salvation if infants can t understand or believe in anything? He does not come to a conclusion about this but stresses the fat that John the Baptist was filled with the Spirit while in his mother s womb. Clark spends several pages explaining the need to be precise in our definition of theological terms. After some examples of the use of the term pisteuo, it is clear that the proper translation is to believe. It would have been much better, Clark states, had the noun pistis been translated belief. Verses that Clark cites show that the object of belief is usually the truth. To believe in and to believe that are used interchangeably, in John especially. Understanding the words of the evangelist is an intellectual act and it does not save; believing those words after having understood them saves. The object of each of those propositions differs greatly. One may understand that the evangelist thinks and is saying that Christ died for my sins. A second act is that one believes that it is true Christ died for my sins. Both are cases of volitional assent, but the objects differ immensely. Clark then sums up the question of person, or proposition. To believe in the person of Christ is still to believe certain things, propositions, truths, about Christ are true. So what is the object of saving faith? If the object of saving faith is a proposition, then what is that proposition? There are obviously a number of combinations of 7

propositions, and Clark shows that it is neither commanded, encouraged, or permitted to be satisfied with a bare minimum number of propositions or a half a dozen doctrines. In Matthew 28:20, Jesus commands his disciples to teach people all that he had commanded. In conclusion, Clark defines saving faith as assent, truth as propositions, the inerrancy of Scripture, with the outright rejection of all rationalism, are integral parts of the system. Faith by definition is assent to understood propositions. Not all cases of assent, even assent to Biblical propositions, are saving faith. But all saving faith is assent to one or more Biblical propositions. 8