Content and Modality: Themes from the Philosophy of Robert Stalnaker, edited by

Similar documents
Coordination Problems

Theories of propositions

Objections to the two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Presupposition and Rules for Anaphora

On David Chalmers's The Conscious Mind

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Why the Traditional Conceptions of Propositions can t be Correct

Contextual two-dimensionalism

Ambitious Two-Dimensionalism

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports. Stephen Schiffer New York University

A Review of Neil Feit s Belief about the Self

Varieties of Apriority

Subjective Character and Reflexive Content

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work on

This is a collection of fourteen previously unpublished papers on the fit

Primitive Concepts. David J. Chalmers

Millian responses to Frege s puzzle

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

BOOK REVIEWS. The Philosophical Review, Vol. 111, No. 4 (October 2002)

IN his paper, 'Does Tense Logic Rest Upon a Mistake?' (to appear

APRIORITY AND MEANING: A CASE OF THE EPISTEMIC TWO-DIMENSIONAL SEMANTICS

Conceivability, Possibility and Two-Dimensional Semantics

Skepticism and Internalism

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS

Comments on Lasersohn

Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body

Against the Contingent A Priori

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

IN THIS PAPER I will examine and criticize the arguments David

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

Understanding Assertion

Understanding, Modality, Logical Operators. Christopher Peacocke. Columbia University

The Phenomenal Concept Strategy

Presuppositions (Ch. 6, pp )

A set of puzzles about names in belief reports

INTERPRETATION AND FIRST-PERSON AUTHORITY: DAVIDSON ON SELF-KNOWLEDGE. David Beisecker University of Nevada, Las Vegas

Chalmers, "Consciousness and Its Place in Nature"

Chadwick Prize Winner: Christian Michel THE LIAR PARADOX OUTSIDE-IN

Week Eleven: Objections to Jackson 1. The Objection From Linguistic Ignorance

Draft January 19, 2010 Draft January 19, True at. Scott Soames School of Philosophy USC. To Appear In a Symposium on

Epistemic two-dimensionalism

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Some proposals for understanding narrow content

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

Review of Torin Alter and Sven Walter (eds.) Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New Essays on Consciousness and Physicalism

xiv Truth Without Objectivity

Puzzles of attitude ascriptions

Physicalism and Conceptual Analysis * Esa Díaz-León.

KNOWING WHERE WE ARE, AND WHAT IT IS LIKE Robert Stalnaker

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection.

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

The Myth of Factive Verbs

Is mental content prior to linguistic meaning?

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Propositions as Cognitive Event Types

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Comments on Saul Kripke s Philosophical Troubles

Phil 435: Philosophy of Language. P. F. Strawson: On Referring

NON-COGNITIVISM AND THE PROBLEM OF MORAL-BASED EPISTEMIC REASONS: A SYMPATHETIC REPLY TO CIAN DORR

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pp. i-ix, 379. ISBN $35.00.

Kevin Scharp, Replacing Truth, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013, At 300-some pages, with narrow margins and small print, the work

Is anything knowable on the basis of understanding alone?

Philosophical Zombies Don t Share Our Epistemic Situation. John Curtis Wright

Propositions and Same-Saying: Introduction

Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester

To Appear in Philosophical Studies symposium of Hartry Field s Truth and the Absence of Fact

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE

Analyticity and reference determiners

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Semantic Externalism, by Jesper Kallestrup. London: Routledge, 2012, x+271 pages, ISBN (pbk).

Metaphysical Necessity: Understanding, Truth and Epistemology

Comments on Carl Ginet s

Understanding and its Relation to Knowledge Christoph Baumberger, ETH Zurich & University of Zurich

STEWART COHEN AND THE CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION

Philosophy 125 Day 13: Overview

Two-dimensional semantics and the nesting problem

Timothy Williamson: Modal Logic as Metaphysics Oxford University Press 2013, 464 pages

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

To appear in J. Greco, ed., Philosophers and their Critics: Ernest Sosa, Oxford: Blackwell. Sosa on Abilities, Concepts and Externalism

ILLOCUTIONARY ORIGINS OF FAMILIAR LOGICAL OPERATORS

Can logical consequence be deflated?

VAGUENESS. Francis Jeffry Pelletier and István Berkeley Department of Philosophy University of Alberta Edmonton, Alberta, Canada

On possibly nonexistent propositions

Chalmers on Epistemic Content. Alex Byrne, MIT

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

Externalism, Self-Knowledge and Transmission of Warrant

Transcription:

Content and Modality: Themes from the Philosophy of Robert Stalnaker, edited by Judith Thomson and Alex Byrne. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2006. Pp. viii + 304. H/b 40.00. The eleven original essays in this collection competently cover a wide range of Robert Stalnaker s philosophical work, and Stalnaker s replies to them are clear, well-thought out, and informative. Anyone interested in Stalnaker s philosophy or the areas covered in this volume is well advised to read it. 1. Daniel Stoljar ( Actors and Zombies ) considers Stalnaker s response to the conceivability argument for dualism. The crux of the response is that a world in which my c-fibers are firing but I am not in pain should be distinguished from a dualist world considered as actual in which my c- fibers are firing but I am not in pain [Stalnaker 2002]. Stoljar argues that this response is too strong, for a parallel response would undermine Putnam s perfect actor argument against behaviorism. Stalnaker replies that the a posteriori physicalist s rebuttal of the conceivability argument is to accept the truth of the conceivability in question, which the a priori physicalist will not, but deny the validity of the argument, while construing conceivability as conceptual coherence. The conceivability relevant to Putnam s argument, Stalnaker continues, is envisionability of a possible situation, which assures validity. Stalnaker s construal of Putnam s argument seems to me forced, for it is legitimate to challenge the argument s validity by using the notion of conceivability as conceptual coherence. 2. Sydney Shoemaker ( The Frege-Schlick View ) argues against the Frege-Schlick view, which Stalnaker supports. The Frege-Schlick view is that qualitative similarity and difference relations are well defined only for experiences of the same subject. Shoemaker argues that the view should be resisted because the experiences of different subjects with the same physical and

functional properties will be qualitatively similar. The version of the view which says that qualia are determined by properties that can be instantiated only in the experiences of a single person, is incompatible with physicalism, and the version which says that qualia are relational is incompatible with functionalism. To this, Stalnaker says that an analogy with the relational theory of space clarifies the sense in which two experiences bearing the same relations to the other experiences may exhibit qualitative difference, and that representationism about qualia should allow experience to represent features of oneself, so the Frege-Schlick view is not clearly less friendly to representationism than Shoemaker s view. 3. Paul M. Pietroski ( Character Before Content ) argues for semantic internalism. According to him, since human natural languages are innately determined by human biology, they are unlikely to pair sentences with truth conditions. Stalnaker responds by saying that we have no need for concepts as detached from truth conditions, that innate determination by biology does not rule out truth conditions (cf. face-recognition capacity), and that it is at best compositional semantic rules, not lexical semantics, that can be formulated internalistically. Pietroski s arguments seem to me less than convincing and Stalnaker responds to them in exactly the right way. 4. Richard G. Heck, Jr. ( Idiolects ) argues that common language has no explanatory power for explaining communication and that idiolects are sufficient. But contrary to what Noam Chomsky says, the need for conformity with the others uses of expressions is not purely pragmatically driven but competence-driven. Stalnaker s response is that communication is not to be explained either by common language or by idiolects but by reference to what the audience takes the speaker, rather than the speaker s words, to mean. Tyler Burge s arthritis example illuminates the nature of the content of thought, not just the meanings of words. Heck s attempt

to defend the primacy of idiolects seems to me to be hampered by his desire to avoid Chomsky s way. Staknaker argues against Heck effectively. 5. Vann McGee ( There Are Many Things ) endeavors to sketch an ambitious ersatzist theory of possible worlds. He claims that mathematical models can perform the role of logically possible worlds and that metaphysically possible worlds are those logically possible worlds in which metaphysical necessities hold. In response, Stalnaker says that the fact that Socrates is human is false in a mathematical model in which Socrates refers to G. W. Bush and human means philosopher shows nothing about whether what Socrates is human actually says is possibly false. I find Stalnaker s response convincing. I have two further comments. First, the same kind of epistemic consideration McGee uses against a theory embracing only metaphysically possible worlds works against a theory, like his own, which includes only logically possible worlds, for our epistemic (or doxastic) states are not closed under logical entailment. Second, McGee uses as an example to illustrate the need for impossible worlds If Bruce Wayne were different from Batman, we would see them together sometimes and says that we may conclude that Bruce Wayne is Batman on the evidence that we don t see them together anytime. But we always see Bruce Wayne and Batman together! 6. Timothy Williamson ( Stalnaker on the Interaction of Modality with Quantification and Identity ) gives a technical discussion of the metaphysical implications of the logical results in [Stalnaker 1994]. Stalnaker responds by disclaiming commitment to a sharp or deep line between metaphysical and logical principles. 7. William G. Lycan ( Conditional-Assertion Theories of Conditionals ) criticizes both the conditional-assertion view that an utterance of an indicative conditional is an assertion of the consequent contingent on the truth of the antecedent, and the view that indicative conditionals

lack truth-conditions and truth-values. Contrary to Lycan, Stalnaker says that the dentist s sentence, If you don t undergo this treatment, you ll lose all your teeth, is true if the patient does not undergo the treatment but loses all his teeth in an automobile accident. Stalnaker finds Lycan s embedding arguments the most direct and convincing for his (Lycan s) propositional account. He also finds Lycan s arguments involving conditionals embedded within factive attitude verb-clauses (being sad, happy, embarrassed, ashamed, etc.) strong. Stalnaker, however, takes issue with Lycan s claim that the fact that Chapel Hill is in North Carolina entails that if Jones lives in Chapel Hill, then he lives in North Carolina. Stalnaker tentatively suggests that an indicative conditional is used to express a proposition that is in part about the speaker s epistemic situation, and says the following about Lycan s example: Suppose Nancy knows that Jones lives in Greensboro, North Carolina, or somewhere in Virginia and that Chapel Hill is not Greensboro, but does not know where Chapel Hill is. Then she knows that if Jones lives in Chapel Hill, Chapel Hill must be in Virginia, so she can say truthfully, If Jones lives in Chapel Hill, he does not live in North Carolina. This seems to me to be clearly wrong. The conditional, If Jones lives in Chapel Hill, then he does not live in North Carolina, as uttered by Nancy under the imagined circumstances will not be true, if it expresses a proposition. She will have grounds for believing it true but be in fact wrong. 8. Stephen Yablo ( Non-Catastrophic Presupposition Failure ) offers a general theory of the distinction between a failure of presupposition resulting in a non-truth-evaluable utterance and a failure of presupposition resulting in a truth-evaluable utterance. The king of France is bald and The king of France is sitting in this chair both presuppose that France has a unique king, but the falsity of this presupposition affects the two sentences differently; the first sentence says nothing true or false, whereas the second sentence says something false. This difference is explained as

follows: The first sentence implies France has a king, which is false but could not be false for the same reason if the presupposition were true (i.e., France had a unique king), whereas the second sentence implies This chair is occupied, which is false and could still be false for the same reason even if France had a unique king. Stalnaker points out that the aim of the pragmatic conception of presupposition is to separate questions of truth values from questions of presupposition, so naturally many cases of presupposition failure involve truth-evaluable assertions. Stalnaker also points out that some of the examples Yablo uses are cases in which a speaker fails to say what he means to say and for which Yablo assesses the truth value of what the speaker means to say, and not what the speaker says. Let me comment on the nominalistic agenda of Yablo s program. According to Yablo, The number of cats (in the yard) is 2 counts as true because of the yard s material contents and this has nothing to do with numbers, just as The king of France is sitting in this chair counts as false because of the chair s material contents and this has nothing to do with French royalty. But this seems to me unsatisfactory. The two sentences are not syntactically similar. The number of cats is 2 involves the identity predicate is and should be compared with, say, The king of France is Louis XVI. The number of cats is 2 may be paraphrased as There are two cats. This frees nominalists from the commitment to the existence of a number by eliminating the numeral 2. The parallel paraphrase of The king of France is Louis XVI will be something like Louis XVI rules France as a unique king. This does not eliminate Louis XVI, hence it does not frees us from the commitment to the existence of Louis XVI. 9. Frank Jackson ( The Story of Fred ) rehearses the case for his theory of A-intensions, using the example of an artificial predicate, fred, which is to be rigid and whose actual extension is fixed by the stipulation that it is true of x iff x has the shape of the smallest

homogeneous object (sho). Stalnaker agrees with Jackson s main claim about the content of thought expressed by the stipulators assertion The table is fred, but, unlike Jackson, Stalnaker endorses the claim conditionally on the assumption that the language including fred is one that the stipulators of the word can use. Jackson and Stalnaker both push their internalism with respect to thought and assertive content, but those who are externalistically inclined will find little that will move them. Jackson says that the stipulators of fred use fred to say that something is the same shape as the sho. They do not use it to say that something is round despite the fact that... x is sho iff x is round (194). It is not obvious to me that they do not use it to say that something is round. They may not realize fully what they are doing when they use it. Using a sentence to say that P does not entail knowing that the sentence means that P. This conception of use seems intuitive and coherent (although not all externalists would endorse it). For the same reason, many externalists will remain unconvinced by Stalnaker s claim that if the stipulated language is usable by the stipulators, then the assertive content of fred is the actual shape of the sho and not is round. Jackson also urges, that fred should be thought of as equivalent to the actual shape of the sho (196, emphasis his). But this goes against the supposed initial stipulation that fred is name-like and rigid (193), externalists may say. After expressing an opinion suggestive of the view that we, users of ordinary names, lack the cognitive capacity to speak the language containing them, Stalnaker quickly retreats to the position that knowledge of who or what an individual is is context-dependent, and so is semantic competence. This is a tantalizing suggestion in desperate need of elaboration. 10. John Perry ( Stalnaker and Indexical Belief ) elaborates on his own proposal concerning indexical belief, distinguishing between what is believed and how it is believed, and compares it with Stalnaker s proposal of diagonal propositions. Stalnaker concedes to Perry that

diagonalization does not solve the problem of self-locating belief by itself but insists that the difference between a self-locating belief and a non-self-locating belief is a difference in the content believed rather than in the manner of believing it. 11. Scott Soames ( Understanding Assertion ) agrees with Stalnaker s claim that what is asserted may be very different from what the uttered sentence semantically encodes. Soames s main disagreement with Stalnaker concerns Stalnaker s reliance on metaphysically possible worlds, propositions construed as functions from such worlds to truth values, and propositional concepts. Soames argues that considerations of belief de re show the need for metaphysically impossible worlds. Suppose one thinks of a wooden paperweight that it might be plastic. Then the paperweight is made of plastic, not wood, in some world that is epistemically possible to one. But, assuming necessity of constitution, such a world is metaphysically impossible. Stalnaker concedes, that for some purposes it is useful to take epistemic possibilities at face value without worrying about how to construe them as metaphysically possible (290), but this concession is outweighed by his insistence on the well-known views he holds: (1) One can explain some features of what is going on in [mathematical] discourses without worrying about what they are ultimately about (290). (2) His deflationary understanding of belief about possible worlds and propositions is the right way. (3) What an attribution of belief de re requires is not some intimate acquaintance relation, but only that there be a unique candidate. In the standard puzzle cases, there may be no fact of the matter about which of two distinct individuals in the world according to the believer is identical to a given individual in the actual world, or at least no fact of the matter that is independent of the context of attribution (293). This shows Stalnaker s commitment to internalism. He drives the same point home by representing the epistemic possibility concerning the paperweight by a metaphysically possible world in which some plastic

paperweight appears indistinguishable from how Soames s paperweight appears in the actual world. This resort to an epistemic counterpart of the res clearly shows that Stalnaker is simply rejecting Soames s externalist stance. Stalnaker s internalism here and also in his response to Jackson is not incompatible with his semantic externalism in his response to Pietrosky, but further elaborations on how they are supposed to dovetail together might be illuminating. References Stalnaker, R.1994 The Interaction of Modality with Quantification and Identity, W. Sinnott- Armstrong, D. Raffman, and N. Asher (eds.), Modality, Morality, and Belief (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press): 12-28. Stalnaker, R. 2002 What Is it Like to Be a Zombie? J. Hawthorne and T. S. Gendler (eds.), Conceivability and Possibility (New York: Oxford University Press): 385-400. Department of Philosophy TAKASHI YAGISAWA California State University, Northridge 18111 Nordhoff St Northridge, CA 91330-8253 USA