Mika Ojakangas. A Philosophy of Concrete Life. Carl Schmitt and the Political Thought of Late Modernity.

Similar documents
OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 8

Kant and his Successors

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Today Fall Dr. Evgenia Mylonaki & Dr Thodoris Dimitrakos

INVESTIGATING THE PRESUPPOSITIONAL REALM OF BIBLICAL-THEOLOGICAL METHODOLOGY, PART II: CANALE ON REASON

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY

P356 The Concept of Life in Ancient Greek Philosophy and its Relevance Today. Spring Dr. Evgenia Mylonaki

ETHICS AND THE FUTURE OF HUMANKIND, REALITY OF THE HUMAN EXISTENCE

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

Review: The sacredness of the person: a new genealogy of human rights

I recently read a small book by the American cultural theorist, Eric Santner,

Philosophies of Concrete Life: From Carl Schmitt to Jean-Luc Nancy

ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis

One of the many common questions that are asked is If God does exist what reasons

Timothy Peace (2015), European Social Movements and Muslim Activism. Another World but with Whom?, Basingstoke, Palgrave Macmillian, pp

Honours Programme in Philosophy

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

Précis of Democracy and Moral Conflict

COMMENTS ON SIMON CRITCHLEY S Infinitely Demanding

In Search of a Political Ethics of Intersubjectivity: Between Hannah Arendt, Emmanuel Levinas and the Judaic

Process Thought and Bridge Building: A Response to Stephen K. White. Kevin Schilbrack

University of Toronto Department of Political Science Department for the Study of Religion JPR 2057H /457H DEMOCRACY AND THE SECULAR SYLLABUS 2012

Thursday, November 30, 17. Hegel s Idealism

What Ethical Approach is Effective in the Evaluation of Gene Enhancement? Takeshi Sato Kumamoto University

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Philosophy. Aim of the subject

Ibn Sina on Substances and Accidents

Tuesday, November 11, Hegel s Idealism

What Happens When Wittgenstein Asks "What Happens When...?"

P. Weingartner, God s existence. Can it be proven? A logical commentary on the five ways of Thomas Aquinas, Ontos, Frankfurt Pp. 116.

Cover Page. The handle holds various files of this Leiden University dissertation.

Dave Elder-Vass Of Babies and Bathwater. A Review of Tuukka Kaidesoja Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

MAKING A METAPHYSICS FOR NATURE. Alexander Bird, Nature s Metaphysics: Laws and Properties. Oxford: Clarendon, Pp. xiv PB.

10. The aim of a theory of law is to reduce chaos and multiplicity to unity. legal theory is science and not volition. It is knowledge of what the

Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard

Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (abridged version) Ludwig Wittgenstein

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

Attendance and Absences I m not taking attendance at lecture. However, there will be a final exam that will draw from the reading and from lecture.

Cover Page. The handle holds various files of this Leiden University dissertation

UNIVERSITY OF MALTA THE MATRICULATION EXAMINATION ADVANCED LEVEL

God in Political Theory

On the Origins and Normative Status of the Impartial Spectator

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Realism and instrumentalism

Reactions & Debate. Non-Convergent Truth

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

GOD'S SILENCE IN THE DIALOGUE ACCORDING TO MARTIN BUBER

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Names Introduced with the Help of Unsatisfied Sortal Predicates: Reply to Aranyosi

The dangers of the sovereign being the judge of rationality

REVIEW THE DOOR TO SELLARS

The title of this collection of essays is a question that I expect many professional philosophers have

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

Secularization in Western territory has another background, namely modernity. Modernity is evaluated from the following philosophical point of view.

Descartes Theory of Contingency 1 Chris Gousmett

Is Innate Foreknowledge Possible to a Temporal God?

Programming Language Research

Neo-Confucianism: Metaphysics, Mind, and Morality

The Development of Laws of Formal Logic of Aristotle

Biopolitical Other. In the beginning of this short text, which will discuss the question of the postmodern Other, I will

EXAM PREP (Semester 2: 2018) Jules Khomo. Linguistic analysis is concerned with the following question:

Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

An Inquiry into the Diverse Articulations of Science & Religion in Contemporary Life

RECONSTRUCTING THE DOCTRINE OF THE SUFFICIENCY OF SCRIPTURE 1

The Causal Relata in the Law Page 1 16/6/2006

BIG IDEAS OVERVIEW FOR AGE GROUPS

NORMATIVITY WITHOUT NORMATIVISM 1

Understanding, Modality, Logical Operators. Christopher Peacocke. Columbia University

THE ETHOS OF INSECURE LIFE: SCHMITT, FOUCAULT, KUNDERA AND THE POINT OF THE POLITICAL

Violence as a philosophical theme

Non-naturalism and Normative Necessities

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

We recommend you cite the published version. The publisher s URL is:

Action in Special Contexts

Rationalist-Irrationalist Dialectic in Buddhism:

Andrei Marmor: Social Conventions

A theory of adjudication is a theory primarily about what judges do when they decide cases in courts of law.

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes

Impact Hour. May 15, 2016

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

1 Whereas the three conflicts of the faculties are relatively easy to notice in the first two essays, scholars have typically found it

General theory of education. an impossible but necessary project? Michael Uljens. Department of Education. University of Helsinki.

Anaximander. Book Review. Umberto Maionchi Carlo Rovelli Forthcoming, Dunod

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Templeton Fellowships at the NDIAS

ONE of the reasons why the thought of Paul Tillich is so impressive

Review: The Objects of Thought, by Tim Crane. Guy Longworth University of Warwick

A Review of Norm Geisler's Prolegomena

Educating for a World out of Joint : Challenging Orders and Borders for Religious Diversity in Liberal Education

The practical implication of an understanding of the 4 levels of. Kappeler Institute for the Science of Being, Inc.

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

COURSES THOUGHT IN ENGLISH FALL TERM 2012

Transcription:

Mika Ojakangas. A Philosophy of Concrete Life. Carl Schmitt and the Political Thought of Late Modernity. Stefan Fietz During the last years, the thought of Carl Schmitt has regained wide international attention. His ideas on The Concept of the Political, on The Crises of Parliamentary Democracy or on The Nomos of the Earth are now highly regarded as important contributions to discussions on several topics in the field of political theory. To read Carl Schmitt, many of today s left-wing political theorists claim, will help us to rethink democracy, to show up its internal paradoxes, 1 to point at its dark sides. 2 According to their readings, it will also provide us with a better theoretical understanding of war and other phenomena of violence in politics. And, last but not least, Carl Schmitt is viewed to help us developing a new understanding of political theory, which takes seriously the specific internal agonal logic of the political and does not mix political with ethical thought. In short: Carl Schmitt is presented as a theorist who helps us rediscovering politics in its purity. I. Taking these debates into account Mika Ojakangas study A Philosophy of Concrete Life. Carl Schmitt and the Political Thought of Late Modernity is a very important one. The book has two aims. At first, Ojakangas 251

STEFAN FIETZ offers a very rich and informative introduction into Carl Schmitt s thought as a whole. All of Carl Schmitt s central texts and concepts are precisely interpreted. His thought is not so much presented in a chronological, but more in a systematic way. Thus Ojakangas tries to show, that Schmitt s work is tied together by one single question: what are the concrete preconditions of order? This is the first and maybe the central thesis of the book: Ojakangas claims, that Carl Schmitt is a highly systematic and philosophical author. He thus contradicts other interpretations of Schmitt s work, which emphasise the unsystematic character of his thought. 3 Ojakangas second aim is not so obvious at the first sight. But I think, with his specific interpretation, he also aims at contradicting some assumptions, which have been put forward in the current discussions of Schmitt s work. In what follows, I first want to reconstruct Ojakangas central ideas (II.). Due to limited space I can only present the central lines of Ojakangas argumentation. Then, I want to present shortly some conclusions, what Ojakangas interpretation would mean for the current debate of Schmitt s thought (III.). II. Starting to read the book, one immediately gets the impression, that Ojakangas wants to read Schmitt like many of his current commentators. Ojakangas starts with some very short critical comments on the liberal theory of John Rawls and, as another type of current political thought, on Communitarianism, accusing them both for having forgotten the concrete essence of politics (p. 10). For Ojakangas, Carl Schmitt is the most promising (p. 10) author for developing a political theory, which takes the political seriously and thus turns away from ethical theories of politics formulated by liberals and communitarians as well. There are other hints in this book, which seems to indicate that Ojakangas wants to read Schmitt as a contributor to current discussion on developing a political political theory. Ojakangas wants to actualise (p. 11) Schmitt s thought. Out of this reason, he puts him in a context with authors like Hannah Arendt, Michel Foucault, Ulrich Beck and Gilles Deleuze, who are in favour of pluralism (Beck), who are suspicious concerning modern ethics and an ethical political theory (Foucault and Deleuze) and who are searching for a genuine concept of the political (Hannah Arendt). 252

But while continuing reading, one gets aware, that Ojakangas is not so much interested in an autonomous theory of the political. For him, Schmitt s concept of the political must be seen in its close connection with his search for the concrete preconditions of order. Schmitt was of the opinion, that in modernity this question was totally neglected. So he thought it to be his task to inveigh against the modern worldview and to point out its shortcomings. For this interpretation, Ojakangas applies Schmitt s method of the sociology of concepts to Schmitt s thought. Ojakangas is of the opinion, that all of Schmitt s central concepts like sovereignty, decision, the political or land-appropriation (pp. 151/152) are on the one hand counter-concepts against what Schmitt himself identified as the metaphysical image (p. 11) of modernity. On the other hand, all his concepts function as a kind of ground concept, formulating the preconditions of order (p. 26). Carl Schmitt thus tries to analyse what lies at the heart of our modern political order and what is its ultimate and thus extreme precondition for coming into existence. Speaking metaphorically, Schmitt always tries to think on the extreme border of order (p. 26). What is the metaphysical image of modernity, which has lead to a negligence of questions for preconditions of order? In the eyes of Schmitt, modernity is characterised by rationality, by technology and by absolute immanence. It seems, that the modern world runs automatically like a self-propelling machine (p. 24/25). Schmitt finds this kind of worldview especially expressed in the thought of Hans Kelsen, who searches for a science of law founded on a transcendental, highly abstract basic norm (p. 37). But the radical immanence of modern life also finds its expression in the practice of modern liberal democracy and its core institution, the parliament with its infinite debates and discussions (pp. 90/91). The problem of liberalism lies thus in the fact, that it is not aware of the concrete political institutions or actions, which alone are able to safe an political order s existence. In this sense, liberalism does not reflect and acknowledge its own preconditions. It does not transcendent itself. Schmitt introduces several concepts in order to polemicize against this immanent worldview while searching for an even more concrete precondition of order. The first one is the concept of the sovereign, which is directed against Kelsen s basic norm. For Schmitt, only the concrete instance or person of the sovereign can be the basis of a juridical or political order. (p. 39). The sovereign does not stand outside 253

STEFAN FIETZ the order, but is placed on its very border and is thus the core and the precondition for order or disorder. But in his search for concreteness, Schmitt goes even further. The concept of the sovereign is concretised in the concept of decision : Schmitt holds that every order rests thus on a decision: It is the decision that grounds both the norm and the order. The decision (Entscheidung) is the absolute beginning, the first cause and the ultimate origin, the arkhe of any political entity. (p. 40). And at the heart of decision lies the concept of the political with its precondition of identifying an enemy (p. 65). In Ojakangas interpretation, Carl Schmitt s work seems to be motivated by the desire of finding and conceptualising an even more concrete condition of political order. Carl Schmitt takes several conceptual steps from sovereignty to the political, in which every new conceptual step tries to concretise the former conceptual step. In this way every step brings us closer to the ultimate border, to the most extreme origin of order. But what about the later work of Carl Schmitt, where the concept of the political does not stand in the centre anymore, but is replaced by the concept of nomos? Has the later Schmitt given up his search for concrete origins of order? Ojakangas is of the opinion, that Schmitt s turn to the concept of nomos was again motivated by his search for concreteness. In 1934 he [Carl Schmitt, SF] merely reached the conclusion that reflection which overemphasises the act of decision does not fulfil the precondition of concreteness in the philosophy of concrete life but, on the contrary, floats like the normativist norm, freely in the air. (p. 115) Schmitt s theoretical turn is motivated by the self-critical insight, that his concept of decision and of the political was not concrete enough. In the end, it rather had at least some similarities with Kelsen s transcendental basic norm. A reformulation of Schmitt s theoretical project is necessary. The concrete condition of order must now be found in something different then in the decision and in the political. For Schmitt the nomos as the totality of the conditions prevailing in a political, social and religious order (p. 116) is the new term to conceptualise the concrete. At the heart of the nomos lies the first act of land-appropriation (p. 117), which makes the division of land between men necessary, being thus the precondition of formulating a judgement (Ur-teil) (p. 119) and the development of laws (p. 118/119) on the one hand. On the other hand, the act of dividing land establishes a concrete spatial order (p. 117), which leads to a localisation (Ortung). According to Ojakangas, localisation (Ortung) also 254

implies the possibility of orientation in the world (p. 118). In other words it implies the possibility of developing moral norms, which define a kind of standpoint in the world and attitudes towards the world and other people. Compared to his decisionist and political phase, however, Schmitt has obviously changed his idea of concreteness as a precondition of order. It does not so much rest on a rupture (p. 25) or on an event (p. 45) anymore. In the later work of Schmitt, concreteness finds its expression in the concrete institutional order and its historical development. (p. 115). But is the concrete nomos anything different from the concrete moral and juridical tradition of a certain community then? III. I do not want to discuss whether Ojakangas interpretation of Schmitt s texts is always correct. I sometimes have some doubts, especially concerning his interpretation of nomos and other topics of Schmitt s later work. As far as I know, the later Schmitt is more engaged in analysing problems of war and politics. Ojakangas himself writes a little bit on these questions in his chapter on The Nomos of the Earth (pp. 127-134), but it is not always clear, what his explanations have to do with the topic of concreteness then. In what follows, I would like to discuss what consequences Ojakangas interpretation might have for the current left-wing discussions of Schmitt s thought. From my point of view, Ojakangas has written a very interesting and lucid criticism of this reception of Schmitt s thought which is best represented in the book The Challenge of Carl Schmitt edited by Chantal Mouffe in 1999. As mentioned above, this approach is characterised by the attempt to redefine the political and to conceptualise it with the help of Carl Schmitt. Ojakangas obviously takes his starting point from these discussions. But while following Schmitt s thought he gets aware, that Schmitt himself saw some difficulties in his own concept of the political. According to Ojakangas, Schmitt tried to overcome this problem by pointing at aspects like morality (implied in the concept Ortung) and its historical development. In other words: Schmitt pointed at aspects of political tradition and culture. The reason for this development was, following Ojakangas, that the political was just not representable in a political order. For 255

STEFAN FIETZ Schmitt himself, it floated freely in the air. (p. 115). According to Ojakangas, there were only two ways of making the political in its borderline existence on the edge of order present and concrete in political and juridical processes. The first possibility of representing the political were states of exception (Ausnahmezustand), war or killing: Real killing reveals the concrete core of the political. (p. 71) However, following Ojakangas analyses, killing itself [...] cannot be included in the sphere of the political. Killing at war is merely the ultimate borderline of politics, the extreme case. Just like the state of exception, war is a borderline concept [...] (p. 71). That means that for Schmitt the attempt to represent the political through states of exception and war failed. It did not make the political in any case more concrete or visible. It did not make the political a factor in social life itself. The other possibility, which Ojakangas discusses, is a kind of symbolic representation of the political in its borderline existence, where the political gets present in dramas on theatre, in tragedies (pp. 72-77), in social myths (pp. 103-108) or in specific institutions (pp. 103-108). But trying to represent the political symbolically in social myths means nothing else then making it present in cultural memory and tradition. The consequences of this interpretation would be, that the later Schmitt either got aware that the political can only be a kind of social construct, which might exist in the cultural imagination of certain communities, but is not a concrete form of action. Or he came to the opinion, that the political as a concrete form of action needed to be integrated in the political culture and tradition, in the nomos of a certain community. But if this interpretation is correct, then all the current attempts of introducing Carl Schmitt as someone, who brings the political in its purity back into political theory, would be at least questionable. On the one hand, Carl Schmitt tries to conceptualise the political. But on the other hand he sees the problems of conceptualising (p. 152) and representing it and argues for an ethical or pre-political basis for the political or at least for a kind of mythological representation of it in the cultural memory of a society. Maybe, Carl Schmitt was even one step ahead of some of his current interpreters. In her introduction of the book on Carl Schmitt edited in 1999, Chantal Mouffe writes, that Schmitt s theory of the political and political antagonism would need an addition, namely the idea of a common symbolic ground existing between political rivals. In Ojakangas interpretation, the later Carl Schmitt has not only seen this need for a symbolic ground, he had already formulated some ideas, wherein this symbolic ground 256

could lie, while current interpreters of Schmitt s thought leave this idea quite open and just claim its necessity. The reader of Ojakangas study can thus learn that Carl Schmitt might be the wrong source of inspiration for all those left-wing theorists in search for a theory of the political. On the one hand, Schmitt did not see the political as something autonomous. He always conceptualised it together with the idea of order (p. 108). Carl Schmitt is more a philosopher of order than of the political according to Ojakangas. On the other hand, Schmitt himself became critical towards the political. This is not to say that a theory of the political is impossible. This is only to say that Carl Schmitt himself would certainly have criticised current attempts to formulate such a theory and that he would have felt himself misunderstood by some of his current interpreters. This, of course, does not make Carl Schmitt s thought any better. It only shows once more, that Carl Schmitt is a heavily right-wing theorist and that one should leave him in this corner, analysing his thought as critically as possible and avoid attempts of a new left-wing reception. NOTES 1. Mouffe, Chantal: Carl Schmitt and the Paradox of Liberal Democracy. In: Mouffe, Chantal (Ed.): The Challenge of Carl Schmitt. London/New York: Verso 1999, pp. 38-53 2. Agamben, Giorgio: Homo Sacer. Die souveräne Macht und das nackte Leben. Frankfurt/ Main: Suhrkamp 2002 3. For example, Reinhart Mehring presents Schmitt as an unsystematic thinker. See: Mehring, Reinhart: Carl Schmitt zur Einführung. Hamburg: Junius 2001, p. 7. 4. Mouffe, Chantal: Introduction: Schmitt s Challenge. In: Mouffe, Chantal (Ed.): The Challenge of Carl Schmitt. London/New York: Verso 1999, pp. 1-6, here: p. 5 257