THE revival of philosophy after the Dark Ages (roughly 525

Similar documents
THE RISE OF SCHOLASTIC LEGAL PHILOSOPHY

Moreshortcomingsofsyllogistics.

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres

John Scottus Eriugena: Analysing the Philosophical Contribution of an Forgotten Thinker

Early Medieval Philosophy

ON UNIVERSALS (SELECTION)

PHILOSOPHY AS THE HANDMAID OF RELIGION LECTURE 2/ PHI. OF THEO.

Excerpts from Aristotle

Thomas Aquinas on the World s Duration. Summa Theologiae Ia Q46: The Beginning of the Duration of Created Things

Introduction: reading Boethius whole

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

PL 407 HISTORY OF MEDIEVAL PHILOSOPHY Spring 2012

On Interpretation. Section 1. Aristotle Translated by E. M. Edghill. Part 1

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Building Systematic Theology

A Brief History of Classical Education Lecture 6. Christopher A. Perrin, M.Div., PhD

WHAT ARISTOTLE TAUGHT

What We Are: Our Metaphysical Nature & Moral Implications

EUTHYPHRO, GOD S NATURE, AND THE QUESTION OF DIVINE ATTRIBUTES. An Analysis of the Very Complicated Doctrine of Divine Simplicity.

The Pursuit of Divine Wisdom

The Appeal to Reason. Introductory Logic pt. 1

Contents. Introduction 8

Plato's Parmenides and the Dilemma of Participation

The evolution of the meaning of SCIENCE. SCIENCE came from the latin word SCIENTIA which means knowledge.

MENO. We must first define Platonic Dialogue and then consider the Meno.

Introduction to Ethics Summer Session A

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

QUESTION 54. An Angel s Cognition

Topics and Posterior Analytics. Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey

Catholic Encyclopedia (1913)/Scholasticism

The Ontological Argument

Categories and On Interpretation. Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey

Sep. 1 Wed Introduction to the Middle Ages Dates; major thinkers; and historical context The nature of scripture (Revelation) and reason

Aristotelian temporal logic: the sea battle.

Early Russell on Philosophical Grammar

ANSELM ON GOD'S EXISTENCE Translated by David Burr, History Department, Virginia Tech, Blacksburg, VA.

A dialogical, multi-agent account of the normativity of logic. Catarin Dutilh Novaes Faculty of Philosophy University of Groningen

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII

The Summa Lamberti on the Properties of Terms

Development of Thought. The word "philosophy" comes from the Ancient Greek philosophia, which

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

AVERROES, THE DECISIVE TREATISE (C. 1180) 1

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Henry of Ghent on Divine Illumination

- 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers

The Divine Nature. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 3-11) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian J.

Informalizing Formal Logic

Summer Institute Dallas Baptist University in Christian Scholarship Dr. Davey Naugle. Introduction to De Doctrina Christiana St. Augustine ( )

1/5. The Critique of Theology

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Anaximander. Book Review. Umberto Maionchi Carlo Rovelli Forthcoming, Dunod

Review of Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning: The Posterior Analytics by David Bronstein

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

The Paradigm of the Liberal Arts Tradition

Boethius, logic, and time: The story thus far

THE ORDINATIO OF BLESSED JOHN DUNS SCOTUS. Book Two. First Distinction (page 16)

Five Ways to Prove the Existence of God. From Summa Theologica. St. Thomas Aquinas

ORTHODOX CHRISTIAN AND CLASSICAL EDUCATION:

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

REVIEW. St. Thomas Aquinas. By RALPH MCINERNY. The University of Notre Dame Press 1982 (reprint of Twayne Publishers 1977). Pp $5.95.

STS Course Descriptions UNDERGRADUATE

Edinburgh Research Explorer

On The Logical Status of Dialectic (*) -Historical Development of the Argument in Japan- Shigeo Nagai Naoki Takato

Department of Philosophy. Module descriptions 2017/18. Level C (i.e. normally 1 st Yr.) Modules

Metaphysical Problems and Methods

Early Franciscan Theology: an Outline. Relationship between scripture and tradition; theology as interpretation of scripture and tradition

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Finding God and Being Found by God

CONTENTS PART I PRE-MEDIAEVAL INFLUENCES

In the last chapter we examined from the Scriptures several

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

Durham Research Online

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

Epistemology and Metaphysics: A Theological Critique

AQUINAS: EXPOSITION OF BOETHIUS S HEBDOMADS * Introduction

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

QUESTION 56. An Angel s Cognition of Immaterial Things

Scholasticism I INTRODUCTION

Who Was St. Athanasius?

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE LET THOMAS AQUINAS TEACH IT. Joseph Kenny, O.P. St. Thomas Aquinas Priory Ibadan, Nigeria

MODELS CLARIFIED: RESPONDING TO LANGDON GILKEY. by David E. Klemm and William H. Klink

Reply to Robert Koons

QUESTION 47. The Diversity among Things in General

5.3 The Four Kinds of Categorical Propositions

AUGUSTINE et inquietum est cor nostrum donec requiescat in te. Monday, February 9, 2015

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action

Socrates, Seated Socrates. First Philosophy and Sophistic

Medieval Thought February Medieval Thought

Logical Mistakes, Logical Aliens, and the Laws of Kant's Pure General Logic Chicago February 21 st 2018 Tyke Nunez

Plato s Protagoras Virtue & Expertise. Plato s Protagoras The Unity of the Virtues

Transcription:

PHILOSOPHY IN THE LATIN CHRISTIAN WEST: 750 1050 THE revival of philosophy after the Dark Ages (roughly 525 750) was a drawn-out process, lasting nearly three centuries. The only philosopher worthy of the name between Boethius at the end of Antiquity and the twelfth-century genius of Anselm and Peter Abelard was the anomalous John Scottus Eriugena, whose extraordinary knowledge of Greek allowed him direct access to ancient philosophical and theological literature, presumably the inspiration for his strikingly original neoplatonic metaphysics. Aside from Eriugena there was little philosophy to speak of. The work of summary, paraphrase, gloss, and transmission absorbed most of the intellectual energies of several generations. Yet there were signs and stirrings of interest in philosophy throughout the period, if not for its own sake then as an adjunct to religious and theological speculation. The first important thinker in the revival of philosophy was the English monk Alcuin of York (735 804), whose sojourn at the court of Charlemagne near the end of the eighth century gave him wide influence on the Continent. Alcuin and his many students were the heirs and imitators of the earlier mediæval encyclopædists Cassiodorus, Martianus Cappella, Isidore of Seville who tried to preserve classical learning for an uncertain future, and their efforts were equally wide-ranging and diffuse. Alcuin, in his Dialogue on True Philosophy, which serves as an introduction to his schooltexts collectively known as the Didascalion, identifies the seven stages of philosophy with the liberal arts: grammar, rhetoric, dialectic, arithmetic, geometry, music, and astronomy. But to identify philosophy with the whole of human intellectual endeavor is to miss the distinguishing feature of philosophy proper, namely reasoned argument directed at first principles. In this narrower sense, Alcuin s discussion of philosophy is largely confined to the treatise on dialectic, covering the material traditionally known as the old logic (logica vetus). Like most of the treatises in the Didascalion, it is written as an elementary question/answer catechism between Charlemagne and Alcuin. Here is a sample: Charlemagne: How should a syllogism be constructed? Alcuin: Typically from three elements so that from the first two premisses the third follows as the conclusion. The raw materials of logic, philosophy of language, and metaphysics are presented in this simplified textbook fashion. Alcuin wrote three works of dogmatic theology that suggest a wider ac- 1

2 PHILOSOPHY IN THE LATIN CHRISTIAN WEST: 750 1050 quaintance with philosophy than do his school texts. Belief in the Holy and Undivided Trinity, for the most part an epitome of Augustine s masterwork The Trinity, recounts the African Doctor s theory of relative predication in the Trinity and analyzes a miscellany of questions suggested by dogma, for instance whether Christ had full knowledge of his own divinity. While Alcuin does not contribute anything original to these discussions, they offer a summary of arguments and distinctions that suggest how philosophy might be done systematically. Likewise, his shorter works The Nature of the Soul and The Virtues and Vices respectively epitomize Augustine s The Nature and Origin of the Soul and some of his sermons, in each case reproducing key lines of argument in the original works. Alcuin was followed in the work of paraphrase and explanation by his student Rhabanus Maurus (776 856), whose massive Rules for Clerics, a compendium of Christian practice, follows Alcuin s identification of philosophy with the seven liberal arts. But he adds that Christians should have the same attitude to works of philosophy, especially those written by Platonists, as the Israelites had to their Egyptian masters: carry off only what is valuable (Exodus 12:35 36). Rhabanus identifies dialectic with philosophy in the narrower sense, namely the discipline of rational inquiry (Rules 3.20), and he seems to mean by this any activity using logical or syllogistic reasoning. Rhabanus says nothing about any specifically philosophical topics or questions, though. Most of his writings on religious matters were low-level exegesis and edifying commentary rather than rigorous logical inquiries, and he generally avoided issues in dogmatic theology. Yet Rhabanus also composed a Treatise on the Soul, which alternated summary and paraphrase of Augustine with original discussion of the issues. For instance, Rhabanus argues that the soul cannot have a form, since forms are geometrical shapes and therefore only apply to corporeal items, whereas the soul is incorporeal. In addition to such claims, Rhabanus discusses the virtues as the psychologically distinctive feature of the soul. Some of Alcuin s students showed a particular interest in logic and the philosophy of language, though no great sophistication. Fridugisus (782? 834), who succeeded Alcuin as abbot of St. Martin s in Tours, wrote a letter about the kind of being that nothingness and shadows have a problem he took to be posed by the requirement that every finite noun signify something, in which case nothing must signify something. The English monk Candidus (Wizo), who became head of Charlemagne s palace school when Alcuin departed for Tours, wrote some short notes investigating logical puzzles having to do with the Trinity. He compiled a record of such inquiries by members of Alcuin s circle, which range from mere excerpts of Patristic

PHILOSOPHY IN THE LATIN CHRISTIAN WEST: 750 1050 3 authors to apparently original investigations into questions such as the location of the soul in space, whether truth is something physical, and even an attempt to prove the existence of God; these short notes betray familiarity not only with Augustine but also with the old logic, and a commendable enterprise in applying their knowledge to theological issues. The next generation of thinkers was dominated by John Scottus Eriugena and witnessed an increase in philosophical sophistication, harnessed more than ever to the service of theological problems. Around the middle of the ninth century several doctrinal controversies erupted. The first was precipitated by Gottschalk of Orbais (805 866), who argued on scriptural and patristic grounds that God predestined some for salvation and some for damnation, and furthermore that this was the view of Augustine; Eriugena was called in, by Hincmar, Archbishop of Reims, to write a rebuttal of Gottschalk s views, and he effectively ended the debate by uniting all opposed sides against his views. Around the same time Paschasius Radbertus revised his treatise on the Eucharist (The Lord s Body and Blood), raising questions about Christ s real presence: Is the body in the host the same as Christ s historical body? How can this body be present in the host in many places and many times? What change occurs in the bread and wine in consecration? Radbertus argued that Christ s historical body is present in the host, though veiled by the continued appearance of bread and wine, and that this one body must therefore be present in all places and times, presumably by God s incomprehensible direct creative activity. Charles the Bald then asked Ratramnus of Corbie (died after 868) to respond to Radbertus. Ratramnus then wrote his own The Lord s Body and Blood, in which he argued that Christ s presence in the host is spiritual rather than corporeal, so that there is no real change in the bread and wine which are now called the body and blood of Christ in virtue of representing them. Furthermore, Christ s spiritual body and spiritual blood are not the same as his physical body and blood, maintains Ratramnus, so further recourse to God s creative activity isn t necessary. The Eucharistic debate between Ratramnus and Radbertus, whatever one may think of their views, is much more sophisticated than controversies of the preceding generation. The techniques of philosophy are deployed throughout: argumentation, drawing or rejecting distinctions, attempts to define issues on an abstract level, use of examples and counterexamples, drawing out consequences of positions all these and more are part of their debate. Ratramnus later wrote a treatise On the Soul as part of another theoc Peter King, in A Companion to Philosophy in the Middle Ages (Blackwell 2003), 32 35

4 PHILOSOPHY IN THE LATIN CHRISTIAN WEST: 750 1050 logical controversy, this time on the nature of the soul; he spends most of the treatise analyzing the relation between the individual soul and the kind of thing it is, the species, given that an individual really is its species. Ratramnus argues that genera and species are strictly speaking mental abstractions, not real items in the world, and therefore do not threaten the individuality of different souls. Although he does not develop his view in any detail, it s clear Ratramnus has the metaphysical problem of universals in mind, introduced by speculation on the nature of the soul. By the end of ninth century, then, philosophical issues were being explored in connection with dogmatic theology. Much of the tenth century was devoted to assimilating philosophical material for its own sake. The scholars of the tenth century were aided by the efforts of Remigius of Auxerre (ca. 841 908) who, at the end of the ninth century, produced glosses or commentaries on the scattered remnants of classical learning: Donatus, Priscian, Boethius, Martianus Cappella. To these were added the old logic and Boethius s mongraphs. This work, largely anonymous, had its flower at the close of the first millenium: Abbo of Fleury (945? 1004) wrote his own explanation of categorical and hypothetical syllogisms, the Enodatio; Notker Labeo (ca. 950 1022), a monk at St. Gall, translated several logical works into Old High German and wrote a treatise in Latin on the syllogism. A measure of how far such purely philosophical interests had spread may be seen in Gerbert (ca. 955 1003), a.k.a. Pope Sylvester II, who wrote a treatise On the Rational and the Use of Reason. He begins with a problem drawn from Porphyry, who says that a differentia can be predicated of its cognate difference, as using reason is predicated of what is rational; but how can this be, given that only some of those who are capable of using reason may actually be using it? Gerbert eventually concludes that this predication is indefinite, and hence logically equivalent to the claim that some people able to reason are actually doing so. His journey to this conclusion takes him through an original analysis of potency and act, inspired by a few sketchy remarks in Boethius; he manages to reconstruct a fair amount of Aristotle s doctrine with little help. But perhaps more impressive is that Gerbert takes up a purely philosophical question and treats it on its merits, a sign that philosophical research had come into its own. Philosophy had, in fact, become enough of a specific intellectual activity to be seen by some as problematic. A controversy broke out in the first half of the eleventh century over the proper role of philosophy, namely whether it could illuminate doctrinal questions (the view held by the dialecticians ) or was a hindrance rather than a help (the view held by the anti-dialecticians ). Around 1050, Berengar of Tours (ca. 999 1088) challenged the traditional

PHILOSOPHY IN THE LATIN CHRISTIAN WEST: 750 1050 5 view that in the Eucharist the bread and wine are changed at all, roughly on the grounds that he could not sense any difference before and after their consecration. Lanfranc of Bec (ca. 1005 1089) charges in his reply that Berengar has left behind authority and taken refuge in dialectic, and, although he would prefer to refute Berengar by citing authoritative works, he too must therefore take up the cudgels of dialectic to defend the doctrine of Christ s real presence in the host. Berengar retorted that taking refuge in dialectic is simply to use reason, a divine gift to man, which cannot go against God but rather confutes His enemies. The same conflict arose in a different context. Peter Damian (1007 1072), in a letter on divine omnipotence, took up the question whether God could change the past. Some philosophers argued that God could not, on the grounds that it is logically impossible; what has happened is now fixed and unchangeable in a word, necessary but it is no restriction or limitation on God s power to say that he cannot do the impossible. Damian objects that God was able to make things now past turn out otherwise than they did, and, since God is outside of time and eternal, He still has the power to make that event turn out otherwise, even if it is now past to us (and hence unchangeable by us). Damian further objects that the necessity of the past is only a necessity relative to us, or, more precisely, to our discourse; dialectic only draws connections among statements, not things, and so is intrinsically limited in revealing the truth. Worse yet, the partisans of dialectic discard the foundation of a clear faith because of the obscure darknesses of their arguments. Damian countenances only a subordinate role for philosophy. In a simile that was to become famous, Damian asserted that philosophy should be related to Scripture like a handmaiden to her mistress. No resolution to the conflict between dialecticians and anti-dialecticians was reached in the first half of the eleventh century, and this set the stage for the different paths followed in the second half of the century by Anselm and Abelard. The sophisticated appropriation of ancient philosophical literature likewise prepared the ground, so that even critics of philosophy were relatively skilled in dialectic compared to their predecessors. There are more detailed and penetrating glosses on works of grammar, logic, and rhetoric drawn up in this period too, most anonymous. By the latter part of the eleventh century Anselm and Abelard could flourish in an intellectual world in which there was widespread familiarity with the best of the ancient philosophical literature available.