Descartes entry from Sex from Plato to Paglia: A Philosophical Encyclopedia edited by Alan

Similar documents
Learning to Love: From Egoism to Generosity in Descartes. Descartes is well known for his metaphysics and physics, the roots and trunk of his

Roots of Psychology Aristotle and Descartes

EMPIRICISM & EMPIRICAL PHILOSOPHY

Philosophy 168. Descartes Fall, 2011 G. J. Mattey. Introductory Remarks

William Meehan Essay on Spinoza s psychology.

are going to present Descartes view on the mind/body relation. Our methodology will

The Quest for Knowledge: A study of Descartes. Christopher Reynolds

Descartes and Schopenhauer on Voluntary Movement:

Descartes and the Danger of Irresolution

PHIL History of Modern Philosophy Spring 2015

Descartes to Early Psychology. Phil 255

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

Humanities 3 V. The Scientific Revolution

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Teleological: telos ( end, goal ) What is the telos of human action? What s wrong with living for pleasure? For power and public reputation?

Do you have a self? Who (what) are you? PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2014

Intro to Philosophy. Review for Exam 2

Philosophy 223: Cartesian Man Fall Term 2011 Essentials Professor Alison Simmons Mondays 2-4

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

The unity of Descartes s thought. Katalin Farkas Central European University, Budapest

Asian Philosophy Timeline. Confucius. Human Nature. Themes. Kupperman, Koller, Liu

Descartes's Virtue Theory

Lecture 38 CARTESIAN THEORY OF MIND REVISITED Overview. Key words: Cartesian Mind, Thought, Understanding, Computationality, and Noncomputationality.

PART ONE: HANS-GEORG GADAMER AND THE DECLINE OF TRADITION

MEDITATIONS ON THE FIRST PHILOSOPHY: THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

Theology of the Body. Grace Makes Beauty Out of Ugly Thing

Korsgaard and Non-Sentient Life ABSTRACT

From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005)

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

TO D D C. REAM. VER THE COURSE OF THE PAST FIFTEEN YEARS, intellectual historians have

To be able to define human nature and psychological egoism. To explain how our views of human nature influence our relationships with other

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Philosophy 3020: Modern Philosophy. UNC Charlotte, Spring Section 001, M/W 11:00am-12:15pm, Winningham 101

Friendship in Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics

Hume s An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding

! Jumping ahead 2000 years:! Consider the theory of the self.! What am I? What certain knowledge do I have?! Key figure: René Descartes.

Philosophy (30) WINTER 2005

Adding Substance to the Debate: Descartes on Freedom of the Will

Lecture Notes Comments on a Certain Broadsheet G. J. Mattey December 4, 2008

Dualism: What s at stake?

Lecture 6 Objections to Dualism Princess Elisabeth of Bohemia Correspondence between Descartes Gilbert Ryle The Ghost in the Machine

SPINOZA AND CONSCIOUSNESS. A Thesis. Presented to the. Faculty of. San Diego State University. In Partial Fulfillment

Personal Identity and the Jehovah' s Witness View of the Resurrection

What one needs to know to prepare for'spinoza's method is to be found in the treatise, On the Improvement

Class 12 - February 25 The Soul Theory of Identity Plato, from the Phaedo

Philosophies of Happiness. Appendix 8: Epicurus: Mental Pleasures, Katastematic and Kinetic

1/8. Descartes 3: Proofs of the Existence of God

A Multitude of Selves: Contrasting the Cartesian and Nietzschean views of selfhood

3.0 Is mind a body process?

RESOLVING THE DEBATE ON LIBERTARIANISM AND ABORTION

Who is Able to Tell the Truth? A Review of Fearless Speech by Michel Foucault. Los Angeles, CA: Semiotext(e), 2001.

Reading Euthyphro Plato as a literary artist

Mind and Body. Is mental really material?"

Spinoza, A Spinoza Reader, ed. and trans. E. Curley (Princeton University Press).

The Passions of the Soul

DESCARTES ONTOLOGICAL PROOF: AN INTERPRETATION AND DEFENSE

The Simplest Body in the Spinoza s Physics

VOLUME VI ISSUE ISSN: X Pages Marco Motta. Clear and Distinct Perceptions and Clear and Distinct Ideas: The Cartesian Circle

Phil Aristotle. Instructor: Jason Sheley

GREAT PHILOSOPHERS: Thomas Reid ( ) Peter West 25/09/18

Wiley is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Noûs.

HOBBES S DECEIVING GOD: THE CORRESPONDENCE BETWEEN THOMAS HOBBES AND RENE DESCARTES. Gabriela Gorescu. Thesis Prepared for the Degree of

Descartes and Malebranche on Thought, Sensation and the Nature of the Mind

The New Constructivist Communism in Short, Part 3: Is it really a man s world?

a0rxh/ On Van Inwagen s Argument Against the Doctrine of Arbitrary Undetached Parts WESLEY H. BRONSON Princeton University

This authoritative translation by John Cottingham of the Meditations is taken from the much acclaimed three-volume Cambridge. Descartes: Meditations

Contents. How to Use This Book Preface Acknowledgments

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya

Concerning Those Things that Can Be Called into Doubt

WEEK 1: CARTESIAN SCEPTICISM AND THE COGITO

G. J. Mattey s Lecture Notes on Descartes s Fourth Meditation 1

The preoccupation with the self or with subjectivity would seem to be one of the

Reading the Nichomachean Ethics

NATURALIZING EPISTEMIC VIRTUE

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics

SCHAFFER S DEMON NATHAN BALLANTYNE AND IAN EVANS

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

some of the questions that Blaise Pascal and John Locke seek to address. The two great

Stem Cell Research on Embryonic Persons is Just

Comparison between Rene Descartes and Francis Bacon s Scientific Method. Course. Date

What We Are: Our Metaphysical Nature & Moral Implications

Everywhere we see evidence of the incr:. easingly fast-paced nature of our society.

In the name of God, the Compassionate and Merciful

ASS1 10/26/04 6:12 PM Page 5 PART I EARLY MODERN PHILOSOPHY

1/10. Descartes and Spinoza on the Laws of Nature

PHIL History of Modern Philosophy Spring 2016

Epistemology and sensation

Gestures in the Making

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

Soul/Mind and Body Separation. A Look at Dualism. Noel Linnane

STUDIES IN SALESIAN SPIRITUALITY. Community, Communication, and Ecstasy

Philosophy 1100 Honors Introduction to Ethics

Chapter 16 George Berkeley s Immaterialism and Subjective Idealism

Review of J.L. Schellenberg, Divine Hiddenness and Human Reason (Ithaca, NY: Cornell UP, 1993), i-x, 219 pages.

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 3 D A Y 2 : I M M A T E R I A L I S M, D U A L I S M, & T H E M I N D - B O D Y P R O B L E M

Wednesday, April 20, 16. Introduction to Philosophy

The Unifying Philosophies from India and Greece. Upanishadic Hinduism, one of the broadest philosophies of our time, originated in the

What Must There be to Account for Being?

Transcription:

Descartes entry from Sex from Plato to Paglia: A Philosophical Encyclopedia edited by Alan Soble. Rene Descartes (1596-1650), a Frenchman, was educated by the Jesuits and did groundbreaking work in mathematics and science as well as philosophy. He lost his mother in infancy, suffered from frail health, never married, lived in several countries without settling down, led a private and quiet life, maintained a voluminous correspondence with virtually all the major minds of his time, and died shortly after going to Sweden to be philosopher in residence at the court of Queen Christina (1626-89). He had a brief affair with a Dutch servant named Helene Jars, with regard to which he remarked, Only a little while ago I was young; I am a man and did not take a vow of chastity, and have never claimed to pass as better behaved than other men (Rodis-Lewis, 138). He acknowledged the daughter, Francine (1635-40), whom Helene bore him, arranged for the child and her mother to live near him (in spite of his frequent moves), made provisions for her education, and was deeply grieved by her death at age 5. He is best known for his contributions to epistemology and metaphysics in particular for his use of methodological doubt and for his radical mind-body dualism, according to which the mind is a thinking (conscious) substance, and the body is simply matter extended in space. This constituted a profound break with the Aristotelean/Thomistic tradition, entailed a rejection of teleology (purposiveness) in nature, and committed him to explaining all bodily processes in a mechanistic manner. He viewed life as merely a kind of heat produced in the organs of the body by a process similar to fermentation. His understanding of reproduction is similarly mechanistic. He believed that each of the sexes produces a sort of seminal fluid and that the seminal material of each acts as a kind of yeast for the other, generating the heat that is the essence of biological life. (Description of the Human Body, in Cottingham, Stoothoff and Murdoch,Vol. 1, 322).

Although these changes threatened to undercut the metaphysical foundation of the way the tradition understood sexuality, Descartes own views about love, desire, and sexuality remained quite conventional. He discusses these in letters and in his last book The Passions of the Soul (hereinafter PS) which grew out of his correspondence with Princess Elizabeth of Bohemia (1618-80), who had been pressing him to explain the mind-body union more adequately. The passions are particularly important for understanding the way mind and body are joined, for they are so close and so internal to our soul that it cannot possibly feel them unless they are truly as it feels them to be (PS, Art. 26). Yet they are caused, maintained and strengthened by some movement of the spirits (PS, Art. 27). (The term spirits refers to animal spirits which are tiny, fast-moving particles involved in perception and movement.) They dispose our soul to want the things which nature deems useful for us, and to persist in this volition; and the same agitation of the spirits which normally causes the passions also disposes the body to make movements which help us to attain these things (PS, Art 52), being ordained by nature to relate to the body, and to belong to the soul only in so far as it is joined with the body (PS, Art. 137). Behind the use of the term nature, of course, stands a benevolent God who joined our souls and bodies together in the way He did for our good. Far from believing the passions to be evil, Descartes says, It is on the passions alone that all the good and evil of this life depends... for persons whom the passions can move most deeply are capable of enjoying the sweetest pleasures of this life. The chief use of wisdom, he tells us, lies in teaching us to be masters of our passions (PS, Art. 212). There are six primitive passions: wonder, love, hate, desire, joy, and sadness. Love is an emotion of the soul caused by a movement of the spirits that prompts (inciter) the soul to join itself in volition (de volunte) to objects that appear agreeable (PS, Art. 79, my translation). More

precisely, it is the assent by which we consider ourselves henceforth as joined with what we love in such a manner that we imagine a whole, of which we take ourselves to be only one part, and the thing loved to be the other (PS, Art. 80). Love covers a very wide variety of phenomena, ranging from the prenatal infant s feeling of love for suitable food, to our love for God (to Chanut, 1 February, 1647, Kenny, 211-15). Sometimes we regard ourselves as the larger and more important part. Persons, however, are capable of becoming a second self (PS, Art. 90), and there are cases where we regard ourselves as the smaller and less important part, as happens with a good father s love for his child, a soldier s love for his country, or in the extreme case our love for God. In these latter cases, we are ready to sacrifice even our lives for the other; love thus enables the soul to break out of its isolation and egoism. For Descartes views about love, see Beavers, Frierson, Matherton and Voss. On ethics more generally, see also Marshall, Morgan and Rodis-Lewis (1957). The passion of love is commonly associated with a mysterious heat around the heart and a tendency to open our arms as if to embrace something (To Chanut, 1 February 1647, Kenny, 209). Desire is forward-looking; stimulating us into action to acquire a good or avoid an evil (PS, Art. 57). Sexual desire arises from attraction, and is a result of normal maturation. Nature has established a difference of sex in human beings, as in animals lacking reason, and with this she has also implanted certain impressions in the brain which bring it about that at a certain age and time, we regard ourselves as deficient as forming only one half of a whole, whose other half must be a person of the opposite sex... When we observe something that attracts us in one of them, it makes our soul feel towards that one alone all the inclination which nature gives it to pursue the good which it represents as the greatest we could possibly possess (PS, Art. 90). We are moved (inciter) to love one person more than another by two sorts of causes one in the body

and one in the mind (esprit). It is a mark of the latter that, unlike the former, they are almost always reciprocated; he says he is confident that his inclination toward Chanut is reciprocated so it is clear that he is using the term aimer broadly to include friendship. The physical causes that move us to love one person more than another, even before we know their merit, are dispositions or arrangements of the parts of our brain, sometimes (but not always) caused by previous experiences (letter to Chanut (6 June, 1647, AT V:56-8). Passions based on attraction, being perceived through the senses, affect the soul particularly strongly, but they are also the most deceptive of the passions, against which we must guard ourselves most carefully (PS, Art. 85). Love is stronger than hatred, and disordered love, he tells Chanut, is more harmful than hatred because there is more danger in being united with and almost transformed into, a thing which is bad than in being separated in volition from one that is good (Kenny, 216). Citing a poem about Paris setting Troy ablaze to cool his own passion, Descartes says that the greatest evils of love are those done or permitted for the sole pleasure of the beloved or oneself. Mastering our passions requires us to be guided by reason. We cannot control them directly, since we continue to feel them until the agitation of spirits subsides, so we need to use indirect means for managing them, and he offers a variety of practical suggestions for doing so. Sometimes we just need to wait them out, refraining from action, and trying to direct our attention to something else. But over time we can try to retrain ourselves and build in new habits. Sometimes merely realizing the cause of some inclination may free us from it, as Descartes realization that he was drawn to cross-eyed people because of his childhood love for a cross-eyed girl freed him from feeling this inclination any more (To Chanut. 6 June, 1647, AT 5:56-8). Bibliography

Descartes, Rene. Passions of the Soul. Cottingham, Stoothoff and Murdoch, eds. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, Vol.1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985. Unless otherwise noted, all citations to PS are to this edition, and are by article number not page. Citations marked AT are to the Adam & Tannery 1974 edition of Oeuvres de Descartes. Les Passions de Ame. Introduction and notes by Genevieve Rodis-Lewis. Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin, 1955. Kenny, Anthony, ed. and trans. Descartes Philosophical Letters. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1981. Rodis-Lewis, Genevieve. Descartes: His Life and Thought, Jane Todd, trans. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1998.