HAS DAVID HOWDEN VINDICATED RICHARD VON MISES S DEFINITION OF PROBABILITY?

Similar documents
SINGLE TRIAL PROBABILITY APPLICATIONS: CAN SUBJECTIVITY EVADE FREQUENCY LIMITATIONS?

ON THE POSSIBILITY OF ASSIGNING PROBABILITIES TO SINGULAR CASES, OR: PROBABILITY IS SUBJECTIVE TOO!

A CHALLENGE TO LUDWIG VON MISES S THEORY OF PROBABILITY

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Israel Kirzner is a name familiar to all readers of the Review of

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Boethius, The Consolation of Philosophy, book 5

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

The St. Petersburg paradox & the two envelope paradox

PLAUSIBILITIES IN ECONOMICS

Proof of the Necessary of Existence

CAN TWO ENVELOPES SHAKE THE FOUNDATIONS OF DECISION- THEORY?

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

What one needs to know to prepare for'spinoza's method is to be found in the treatise, On the Improvement

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

An Analysis of the Proofs for the Principality of the Creation of Existence in the Transcendent Philosophy of Mulla Sadra

Compatibilist Objections to Prepunishment

Logical (formal) fallacies

Quaerens Deum: The Liberty Undergraduate Journal for Philosophy of Religion

The Creation of the World in Time According to Fakhr al-razi

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 5d God

The Problem with Complete States: Freedom, Chance and the Luck Argument

Philosophy of Religion 21: (1987).,, 9 Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht - Printed in the Nethenanas

Kant and his Successors

occasions (2) occasions (5.5) occasions (10) occasions (15.5) occasions (22) occasions (28)

Presuppositional Apologetics

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Lecture 4.2 Aquinas Phil Religion TOPIC: Aquinas Cosmological Arguments for the existence of God. Critiques of Aquinas arguments.

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social

The Cosmological Argument

There are various different versions of Newcomb s problem; but an intuitive presentation of the problem is very easy to give.

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026

Robert Formaini's illuminating work throws into question a

WHAT VERSION OF THE BIBLE SHOULD I USE? THE KING JAMES VERSION: GOD S RELIABLE BIBLE FOR THE ENGLISH-SPEAKING CHURCH

1/10. Descartes and Spinoza on the Laws of Nature

Stout s teleological theory of action

1/12. The A Paralogisms

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

FROM CONFORMITY TO TRANSFORMATION. A Basis for Conversation in Minneapolis, August 24, James R. Edwards

232 Infinite movement, the point which fills everything, the moment of rest; infinite without quantity, indivisible and infinite.

1/8. Introduction to Kant: The Project of Critique

Is Innate Foreknowledge Possible to a Temporal God?

Cosmological Arguments

Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Chance, Chaos and the Principle of Sufficient Reason

The Cosmological Argument: A Defense

RESOLVING THE DEBATE ON LIBERTARIANISM AND ABORTION

Against Against Intellectual Property: a Short Refutation of Meme Communism

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

THE GOD OF QUARKS & CROSS. bridging the cultural divide between people of faith and people of science

THE RELEVANCE OF THE SUBJECTIVE

Revista Economică 66:3 (2014) THE USE OF INDUCTIVE, DEDUCTIVE OR ABDUCTIVE RESONING IN ECONOMICS

On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title being )

Treatise I,iii,14: Hume offers an account of all five causes: matter, form, efficient, exemplary, and final cause.

What we want to know is: why might one adopt this fatalistic attitude in response to reflection on the existence of truths about the future?

Peter Singer, Famine, Affluence, and Morality

Proof as a cluster concept in mathematical practice. Keith Weber Rutgers University

The Social Nature in John Stuart Mill s Utilitarianism. Helena Snopek. Vancouver Island University. Faculty Sponsor: Dr.

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

DISCUSSIONS WITH K. V. LAURIKAINEN (KVL)

Chapter 2 Science as a Way of Knowing: Critical Thinking about the Environment

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

5 A Modal Version of the

Phil 435: Philosophy of Language. P. F. Strawson: On Referring

A Critique of Friedman s Critics Lawrence A. Boland

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Lucky to Know? the nature and extent of human knowledge and rational belief. We ordinarily take ourselves to

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

5: Preliminaries to the Argument

Marcel Sarot Utrecht University Utrecht, The Netherlands NL-3508 TC. Introduction

The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970)

Since Michael so neatly summarized his objections in the form of three questions, all I need to do now is to answer these questions.

Betting With Sleeping Beauty

Checking Your Arguments

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

Statistical Inference Without Frequentist Justifications

A Fundamental Thinking Error in Philosophy

Benjamin Morison, On Location: Aristotle s Concept of Place, Oxford University Press, 2002, 202pp, $45.00, ISBN

The Quality of Mercy is Not Strained: Justice and Mercy in Proslogion 9-11

Anselmian Theism and Created Freedom: Response to Grant and Staley

Shafer-Landau's defense against Blackburn's supervenience argument

The Principle of Sufficient Reason and Free Will

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

Probability Foundations for Electrical Engineers Prof. Krishna Jagannathan Department of Electrical Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Moral Philosophy : Utilitarianism

THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1. Dana K. Nelkin. I. Introduction. abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory.

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

Hume s An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding

Probability: A Philosophical Introduction Mind, Vol July 2006 Mind Association 2006

David Hume. On Compatibility

Aquinas 5 Proofs for God exists

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

METHODENSTREIT WHY CARL MENGER WAS, AND IS, RIGHT

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio

Dave Elder-Vass Of Babies and Bathwater. A Review of Tuukka Kaidesoja Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

Transcription:

LIBERTARIAN PAPERS VOL. 1, ART. NO. 44 (2009) HAS DAVID HOWDEN VINDICATED RICHARD VON MISES S DEFINITION OF PROBABILITY? MARK R. CROVELLI * Introduction IN MY RECENT ARTICLE on these pages entitled On the Possibility of Assigning Probabilities to Singular Cases: Or, Probability is Subjective Too! (Crovelli 2009) I argued that members of the Austrian School of economics have adopted and defended a faulty definition of probability. I argued that the definition of probability necessarily depends upon the nature of the world in which we live. I claimed that if the nature of the world is such that every event and phenomenon which occurs has a cause of some sort, then probability must be defined subjectively; that is, as a measure of our uncertainty about the likelihood of occurrence of some event or phenomenon, based upon evidence that need not derive solely from past frequencies of collectives or classes (Crovelli 2009, p. 3). I further claimed that the nature of the world is indeed such that all events and phenomena have prior causes, and that this fact compels us to adopt a subjective definition of probability. David Howden has recently published what he claims is a refutation of my argument in his article Single Trial Probability Applications: Can Subjectivity Evade Frequency Limitations (Howden 2009). Unfortunately, Mr. Howden appears to not have understood my argument, and his purported refutation of my subjective definition consequently amounts to nothing more than a concatenation of confused ideas that are completely irrelevant to my argument. My reply will focus on the first three sections of Mr. Howden s paper in isolation, and a discussion of the final two sections together. *Mark R. Crovelli may be reached at mark.crovelli@gmail.com. CITE THIS ARTICLE AS: Mark R. Crovelli, Has David Howden Vindicated Richard von Mises s Definition of Probability?, Libertarian Papers 1, 44 (2009). ONLINE AT: libertarianpapers.org. THIS ARTICLE IS subject to a Creative Commons Attribution 3.0 License (creativecommons.org/licenses). 1

2 LIBERTARIAN PAPERS 1, 44 (2009) On the Supposed Necessity of the Frequency Definition of Probability The first major section of Mr. Howden s paper bears the subtitle The necessity of a frequency interpretation for probability theory. With a subtitle as ambitious as this, one would expect that Mr. Howden would offer some sort of argument to the effect that the frequency interpretation is a necessity. Disappointingly, one searches in vain to find any argument whatsoever let alone an argument indicating the necessity of the frequency interpretation. It is thus unnecessary for me to reply to Mr. Howden s argument, since there is no argument to which I might reply. I will, however, reply to a few of the random ideas in the section. First, I would point out that Mr. Howden s claim that a priori probability distributions cannot be ascertained without verification through empirical tests (Howden 2009, p. 2) is baldly question begging. To claim that all probabilities must be tested against experience begs the question: well, what is probability in the first place? The classical method for generating probabilities by assuming equal likelihood of occurrence does not rely upon testing or empirical verification of any kind. Whether or not this method for generating numerical probabilities is legitimate depends upon how we define probability. So, to assume from the outset that this method is illegitimate simply begs the question. Another idea in this section of Mr. Howden s paper that is apparently advanced as evidence of the necessity of the frequency interpretation revolves around my reclassification of Richard von Mises s definition as a conceptual method, rather than the definition of probability itself. In reply, I would point out that my claim was not that Richard von Mises created a conceptual definition of probability, as Mr. Howden mistakenly claims (Howden 2009, p. 3 emphasis in original). On the contrary, I specifically claimed that Richard von Mises created what is best described as a conceptual method for generating numerical probabilities (Crovelli 2009, p. 10). I made this claim based upon the observation that, since relative frequencies can never be calculated for infinite or indefinite series of observations, the method people actually use must rely upon finite series of actual observations. And, this is precisely the point that Richard von Mises himself makes in the quote Mr. Howden cites (Howden 2009, p. 3). Mr. Howden s misunderstanding on this point ultimately leads him to attribute to my argument the idea that the relative frequency method requires infinite repetitions, an argument that I never made. Mr. Howden s extremely important discussion of odds-makers in this section also deserves notice. In my paper I claimed that since bookies and

RICHARD VON MISES S DEFINITION OF PROBABILITY 3 casinos are able to consistently generate accurate odds for singular events and phenomena like boxing matches this is strong prima fascia evidence that nonfrequentist methods for generating numerical probabilities were not meaningless, as the brothers von Mises had claimed. Mr. Howden will have none of this, and he denounces such odds as an illusion fabricated by an odds-maker (Howden 2009, p. 4). His reason for denying that such odds are probabilities, however, is almost embarrassingly question begging. Indeed, his evidence that such odds are not probabilities amounts to nothing more than a mistaken restatement of how bookies go about generating odds: [T]he odds-maker only has to have an estimate of who will win and who will lose a fight. The odds established are used to entice individuals to bet against the expected winner, in the hopes of pocketing more winnings. (Howden 2009, p. 4) Setting aside the fact that this is not how bookies manage a sportsbook, (and setting aside the fact that Mr. Howden is here admitting that odds-makers can indeed accurately predict who will win a fight!), it should be obvious that it is question begging to use claims such as this as evidence that probability must be defined as a frequency. Again, the question thus begged would be: well, what is the definition of probability in the first place? To assume from the outset that the methods of odds-makers utilizing non-frequentist methods are not exercise(s) in probability, is to assume the very thing one is attempting to prove! In sum, despite the ambitious subtitle of this section of Mr. Howden s paper, we are not offered any argument whatsoever for the supposed necessity of the frequency definition of probability. What Does Risk Have to do with the Definition of Probability? Turning now to the second section of Mr. Howden s paper, we find errors in reasoning that rival those of the first section in their seriousness. In the first place, the section opens with a quote drawn from my paper where I made the following claim: [W]hen we deal with the subject of probability we must necessarily and concomitantly deal with the subject of uncertainty. The term probable applies to statements and facts about which we are uncertain the word does not apply to statements and facts about which we are absolutely certain. (Crovelli 2009, p. 7) Mr. Howden then makes the following claim: That there are only two options available complete certainty and complete uncertainty seems to neglect the case of risk. (Howden 2009, p. 5)

4 LIBERTARIAN PAPERS 1, 44 (2009) At no point in my paper, however, did I ever claim that these are the only two options available, and it is thus completely invalid to ascribe this claim to me. In fact, my claim was that there man s uncertainty varies since probability acts as a numerical measure of man s uncertainty about the world. Mr. Howden then turns to what he apparently considers to be a critical concept when attempting to define probability: the concept of risk. I am chided for not citing Frank Knight, who made a distinction between risk and uncertainty in terms of the ability to quantify outcomes (Howden 2009, p. 5). How Knight s conception of risk is relevant to the problem of defining probability is never explained, however. The supposed distinction between these two concepts is simply stated and then abandoned without any argument whatsoever about why it is critical for defining probability. Mr. Howden s lamentation that I did not analyze the concept of risk is thus difficult to fathom. For, if he cannot explain exactly why this distinction is important in the quest to define probability, on what basis should I be condemned for not discussing it? It is important to bear in mind that my paper aimed to define probability. My argument that probability must be defined subjectively cannot be refuted by simply restating what the frequentists have said about the concepts of risk uncertainty class probability and case probability. But this is precisely what Mr. Howden s argument, such as it is, amounts to, because he never even attempts to explain how these concepts are relevant to my argument. There is also a very serious element of circular reasoning involved in citing the frequentists conception of risk and uncertainty as the only evidence that the frequentists definition is the correct definition. The question at hand is whether the relative frequency conception of probability is correct one, and to cite their conception as the only evidence that their conception is correct is circular. In addition, as I have previously noted, the conception of uncertainty that I developed in my paper has absolutely nothing to do with the idea of complete uncertainty (Howden 2009, p. 5). Hence, Mr. Howden s repeated condemnation of applying probabilities to things about which we are completely uncertain is nothing more than a repetitious flaying of his own straw man. To argue that subjectivists are seeking to apply numerical probabilities to things about which we are completely uncertain (e.g., does God have a beard?) is to completely misunderstand the debate. In sum, the second section of Mr. Howden s paper offers only irrelevant and distracting straw men and begged questions, and absolutely no discussion of my argument.

RICHARD VON MISES S DEFINITION OF PROBABILITY 5 Richard von Mises Was an Indeterminist The third section of Mr. Howden s paper offers yet another restatement of the frequentists conception of collectives and classes. No reply on my part is necessary here, since a restatement of the frequentists position is no argument against my position. The question at hand, after all, is whether the frequentists have a correct definition of probability, and a mere restatement of their position is no evidence whatsoever that they are right and I am wrong. Interestingly, however, Mr. Howden attempts to bring the idea of randomness into the discussion in this section. He cites Richard von Mises to the effect that randomness in the world is what necessitates the probabilistic approach (Howden 2009, p. 8). As in previous portions of the paper, Mr. Howden does not explain how randomness is relevant to the definition of probability, but he does not seem to be aware that my entire argument rests on the claim that there is no randomness whatsoever in the world. In other words, my claim was that if every event and phenomenon in the world has a prior and certain cause, (and I argued that there are indeed causes for everything that occurs in the world), there is quite literally no such thing as randomness in the world. I claimed that if every event and phenomenon has a prior and certain cause, then the reason why man is uncertain about those events and phenomena lies in man s own mental limitations not in some mysterious property of randomness in the world itself. I concluded from this that probability, as a numerical measure of man s uncertainty, must be defined as a measure man s subjective uncertainty. Mr. Howden seems to be unaware of all this when he cites Richard von Mises, an outspoken indeterminist, on the topic of randomness. Has David Howden Vindicated Richard von Mises s Definition of Probability? The final two sections of Mr. Howden s paper offer a summary of his purported refutation of the subjective definition of probability and a vindication of the frequentist definition. The penultimate section of the paper is entitled Probability what is it? In this section, one would expect to find a recap of the argument against the subjective definition, and this is indeed what one finds, in a sense. The argument, in sum, is that subjective methods cannot be applied to collectives. That this type of argument is question begging when deployed as evidence that the subjective definition is mistaken hardly needs to be mentioned, but it is worth noting that non-frequentist methods are in fact capable of being applied to problems involving collectives. To cite but one example, if we generate a probability of

6 LIBERTARIAN PAPERS 1, 44 (2009) throwing a six with a die by assuming that each side of the die has an equal likelihood of being thrown, (i.e., we utilize the classical method), this would give us a probability of 1/6. Dogmatic frequentists such as Richard von Mises would no doubt object that this number is meaningless and absurd until the die is actually cast many, many times, but their protestation would be based upon their assumption that probability must be defined as a frequency. In short, whether or not non-frequentist methods are capable of being applied to problems involving collectives depends upon what definition of probability we adopt. Mr. Howden also claims that the subjective definition of probability lacks the generality of the frequentist approach, while offering no significant advantages in replacement (Howden 2009, p. 9). This claim is absolutely dumbfounding. In the first place, to think that the frequentists definition of probability is more general than the subjectivists is to state precisely the reverse of the truth. It is the frequentists who condemn all attempts to quantify uncertainty that are not derived from past frequencies as absurd, and the subjectivists who allow for other methods. How the frequentists dogmatic and virulent condemnation of other methods could be interpreted as more general is difficult to fathom. In addition, the fact that the subjective definition allows for other methods for quantifying man s uncertainty demonstrates the significant advantages of the subjective definition. For, the subjective definition allows for calculating numerical probabilities for singular boxing matches, singular wars, singular elections et cetera ad infinitum. In his concluding remarks, Mr. Howden sums up very nicely his entire argument against the subjective definition of probability: When we realize the distinction between two similar concepts risk and uncertainty for Frank Knight, case and class probabilities for Ludwig von Mises, and collectives and unique events for Richard von Mises we understand that probability is not something which may be redefined as Crovelli assumes. (Howden 2009, p. 10) There is not much more to Mr. Howden s argument than that. The paper contains no argument showing that the definition of probability does not depend upon the nature of the world. There is no argument claiming that the world is not governed by time-invariant causal laws. There is no argument or explanation whatsoever as to why we must reserve the term probability only for those situations where we can construct a collective. And there is absolutely no argument as to why the concept of risk obliges us to adopt a frequentist definition.

RICHARD VON MISES S DEFINITION OF PROBABILITY 7 The answer to the question of whether David Howden has vindicated Richard von Mises s definition of probability must therefore be that he has failed. References Crovelli, Mark R. 2009. On the Possibility of Assigning Probabilities to Singular Cases, or: Probability is Subjective Too! Libertarian Papers 1(26): 1 17. Howden, David. 2009. Single Trial Probability Applications: Can Subjectivity Evade Frequency Limitations. Libertarian Papers 1(42): 1 12.