Philosophy and Theology: The Time-Relative Interest Account

Similar documents
the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

The Comparative Badness for Animals of Suffering and Death Jeff McMahan November 2014

Philosophy and Theology: Notes on Speciesism

The Moral Significance of Animal Pain and Animal Death. Elizabeth Harman. I. Animal Cruelty and Animal Killing

Jeff McMahan, The Ethics of Killing: Problems at the Margins of Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press, xiii pp.

Philosophy and Theology: Notes on Diachronic Personal Identity

IN THE ETHICS OF ABORTION: Women s Rights, Human Life, and the Question

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan

Suicide. 1. Rationality vs. Morality: Kagan begins by distinguishing between two questions:

Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, Pp $90.00 (cloth); $28.99

24.03: Good Food 3 April Animal Liberation and the Moral Community

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships

PLEASESURE, DESIRE AND OPPOSITENESS

This is an opinionated survey of some ways in which our thinking about death intersects

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

Aristotle's Theory of Friendship Tested. Syra Mehdi

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial.

Scanlon on Double Effect

Peter Singer, Practical Ethics Discussion Questions/Study Guide Prepared by Prof. Bill Felice

WHAT S IDENTITY GOT TO DO WITH IT? THE UNIMPORTANCE OF PERSONAL IDENTITY FOR BIOETHICS

Stem Cell Research on Embryonic Persons is Just

Kantianism: Objections and Replies Keith Burgess-Jackson 12 March 2017

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

Utilitarianism. But what is meant by intrinsically good and instrumentally good?

RESOLVING THE DEBATE ON LIBERTARIANISM AND ABORTION

What We Are: Our Metaphysical Nature & Moral Implications

Well-Being, Disability, and the Mere-Difference Thesis. Jennifer Hawkins Duke University

Why Speciesism is Wrong: A Response to Kagan

Topic III: Sexual Morality

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract

THESIS HOW DOES DEATH HARM THE PERSON WHO DIES? Submitted by. Andrew John Bzdok. Department of Philosophy. In partial fulfillment of the requirements

Introduction. Steven Luper

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Mary Anne Warren on Full Moral Status

Philosophy 320 Selected Topics in Ethics: Death

A Coherent and Comprehensible Interpretation of Saul Smilansky s Dualism

Sacred mountains and beloved fetuses: can loving or worshipping something give it moral status?

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

Compatibilist Objections to Prepunishment

Review of Jean Kazez's Animalkind: What We Owe to Animals

THE ROLE OF COHERENCE OF EVIDENCE IN THE NON- DYNAMIC MODEL OF CONFIRMATION TOMOJI SHOGENJI

Is it Reasonable to Rely on Intuitions in Ethics? as relying on intuitions, though I will argue that this description is deeply misleading.

In his essay Why Abortion is Immoral, Don Marquis asserts that,

HUME AND HIS CRITICS: Reid and Kames

WRONGFUL LIFE: PARADOXES IN THE MORALITY OF CAUSING PEOPLE TO EXIST. Jeff McMahan

Paradox of Happiness Ben Eggleston

A Contractualist Reply

The Principle of Sufficient Reason and Free Will

Equality, Fairness, and Responsibility in an Unequal World

McDowell and the New Evil Genius


The Future of Practical Philosophy: a Reply to Taylor

Philosophy and Theology: Notes on Pro-Life Consistency, Personhood Potentiality, and Prayer for Healing

Kant's Moral Philosophy

Love and Duty. Philosophic Exchange. Julia Driver Washington University, St. Louis, Volume 44 Number 1 Volume 44 (2014)

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Epistemic Consequentialism, Truth Fairies and Worse Fairies

Philosophical Review.

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Golden Rule Thomas Carson

Well-Being, Time, and Dementia. Jennifer Hawkins. University of Toronto

On Humanity and Abortion;Note

Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning

Self-Evidence in Finnis Natural Law Theory: A Reply to Sayers

Why 'Nonexistent People' Do Not Have Zero Well-Being but No Well-Being at All

Unified Teleology: Paul Taylor s Biocentric Egalitarianism Through Aristotle

Warren. Warren s Strategy. Inherent Value. Strong Animal Rights. Strategy is to argue that Regan s strong animals rights position is not persuasive

What s Wrong with Speciesism?

PHIL1010: PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS FORDHAM UNIVERSITY PROFESSOR ROBIN MULLER M/TH: 8:30 9:45AM OFFICE HOURS: BY APPOINTMENT

Virtuous act, virtuous dispositions

Marquis. Stand-off in Abortion Debate

Contemporary moral issues

MORAL DISAGREEMENT CONCERNING ABORTION 1

The free will defense

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5)

Carruthers and the Argument from Marginal Cases

Mission Statement of The Catholic Physicians' Guild of Chicago

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers

Anderson and Velleman s Kantian Thesis : A Case-Study in the Serpent Windings of Ethical Taxonomy

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social

On Making the Case for Life

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Altruism, blood donation and public policy:

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Pollock and Sturgeon on defeaters

When does human life begin? by Dr Brigid Vout

Ethics Handout 19 Bernard Williams, The Idea of Equality. A normative conclusion: Therefore we should treat men as equals.

Are Practical Reasons Like Theoretical Reasons?

PHIL 176: Death (Spring, 2007)

COPLESTON: Quite so, but I regard the metaphysical argument as probative, but there we differ.

Transcription:

Digital Commons@ Loyola Marymount University and Loyola Law School Philosophy Faculty Works Philosophy 1-1-2013 Philosophy and Theology: The Time-Relative Interest Account Christopher Kaczor Loyola Marymount University, Christopher.Kaczor@lmu.edu Repository Citation Kaczor, Christopher, "Philosophy and Theology: The Time-Relative Interest Account" (2013). Philosophy Faculty Works. 96. http://digitalcommons.lmu.edu/phil_fac/96 Recommended Citation Christopher Kaczor, Philosophy and Theology The Time-Relative Interest Account, National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 13.4 (Winter 2013): 753-758. This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at Digital Commons @ Loyola Marymount University and Loyola Law School. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Works by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons@Loyola Marymount University and Loyola Law School. For more information, please contact digitalcommons@lmu.edu.

Philosophy and Theology Don Marquis s future-like-ours argument holds that killing you or me is wrong because it deprives us of a future-like-ours, all that we would have enjoyed had we not been killed. Since the human fetus also has a future-like-ours, abortion is wrong. 1 Jeff McMahan challenges this argument because it leads to the conclusion that the death of a human fetus is worse than the death of a twenty-year-old, since the human fetus has twenty extra years of a future-like-ours to lose. Yet most people, even many who oppose abortion, hold that the death of the twenty-year-old is worse than the death of the fetus. To explain this common intuition, McMahan introduces the time-relative interest account (TRIA). The TRIA is used as an argument to justify killing human beings prior to birth and is the subject of this reflection. 2 In the typical case, the human fetus has more years of a valuable future than the twenty-year-old does. However, according to the TRIA, we must discount this overall value in virtue of the weak psychological relationship between the fetal human being now and the future human being who will enjoy these goods. The idea is that one s present self and one s future self stand in a psychological relationship to each other that varies over time. To have strong time-relative interests is to have powerful ties between current and future selves (such as most adults enjoy). By contrast, to have weak time-relative interests means that the current self and future self do not hold much (if anything) in common (as is the case with the human fetus and the human adult). The TRIA view suggests that death is worse for the twenty-year-old than for the human fetus 1 Don Marquis, Why Abortion Is Immoral, in Bioethics: An Anthology, ed. Helga Kuhse and Peter Singer (Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing, 1999). See, too, Don Marquis, Abortion and Death, in The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Death ed. Ben Bradley, Fred Feldman, and Jens Johansson (New York: Oxford University Press, 2013), 409 431. 2 David DeGrazia, The Harm of Death, Time-Relative Interests, and Abortion, The Philosophical Forum 38.1 (2007): 57 80. 2013 The National Catholic Bioethics Center 753

The National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly Winter 2013 because the twenty-year-old is strongly invested in her future self, in continuing to realize various life plans, whereas the prenatal human being is unaware that he exists, that he has a future, and so is not invested in this future. Because there are no psychological links between the prenatal human and the twenty-year-old, the interest in a future-like-ours is radically discounted, making this interest virtually zero, thus justifying abortion. In the words of David DeGrazia, the utter lack of psychological unity between the presentient fetus and the later minded being it could become justifies a very substantial discounting of the harm of the fetus death. 3 How should we assess the time-relative interest account? In the TRIA, the human being s interest in living could be understood objectively (a good for the individual regardless of that individual s consciousness) or subjectively (what an individual takes an interest in, wants, or desires). It seems that interests in the TRIA should be understood objectively. The future goods of a whole life matter for the TRIA, but sentient fetuses and newborns lack subjective interests in a future-like-ours. But if fetal interests are taken objectively, one then wonders why subjective considerations (like the degree of psychological unity between present and future selves) are relevant for discounting this objective interest. Objective interests are, by definition, interests an individual has regardless of the individual s subjectivity. In other words, regardless of particular psychological states such as what the individual may subjectively be interested in, or care about, or desire, the individual has an objective interest in the matter under consideration. So if prenatal human beings or newborn human beings have an objective interest in life (a future-like-ours), then regardless of the time-relative psychological strength or weakness of the present self to the future self, the objective interest remains unaltered and, in this case, extremely strong. On the other hand, if the interest is merely subjective, then it is hard to see what work the time-relative aspect plays in the discussion. According to this view, no presentient fetus has any subjective interest at all, and no newborn has a subjective interest in remaining alive since the newborn lacks a concept of self and therefore lacks the desire to remain alive. 4 Furthermore, in assessing the TRIA, it is important to consider the harm of death. A harm can be considered in two ways: in itself (per se) and accidentally. In itself, stealing $35,000 is equal to stealing $35,000. But considered circumstantially, in terms of accidental characteristics, stealing $35,000 from a poor widow is worse than stealing $35,000 from Bill Gates. The harm of blindness deprives individuals of sight equally. However, for a photographer, more is lost when sight is lost. The harm of deafness deprives individuals of hearing equally. But circumstantially, for a musician in an orchestra, the loss of hearing accidentally brings other harms, like the loss of income, meaningful work, and the social goods of orchestra membership. With respect to the harm of death considered in itself, the infant, the twentyyear-old, and the eighty-year-old are equally harmed, since they all lose the same 3 Ibid., 72. 4 See Alberto Giubilini and Francesca Minerva, After-Birth Abortion: Why Should the Baby Live?, Journal of Medical Ethics 39.5 (May 2013): 261 263. See, too, Christopher Kaczor, Philosophy and Theology Notes on After-Birth Abortion, National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 12.4 (Winter 2012): 739 745. 754

Notes & Abstracts Kaczor thing their life, the bodily integration they enjoyed as living organisms. Death destroys each one equally. However, when considering the harm of death not per se but accidentally, many factors are relevant in terms of assessing the harm considered in its circumstantial specificity, including but not limited to the loss of future goods, the loss of currently enjoyed goods, and the loss of social goods. With respect to the loss of future goods (a future-like-ours), the infant s death is worse than the twentyyear-old s death, and the twenty-year-old s death is worse than the eighty-year-old s death. The greater the amount of future good that is lost, the greater the loss for the deceased in that respect. 5 With respect to currently enjoyed goods, the twenty-year-old (and presumably the eighty-year-old) loses more than the infant or prenatal human being, since adults can enjoy certain goods like friendship, knowledge, and freely chosen meaningful activity that the infant and prenatal human being cannot enjoy. Other currently enjoyed goods are also relevant. An individual with a happy life loses more in dying than an individual with a miserable life. An intelligent, friendly, and healthy person loses more in dying than does an unintelligent, misanthropic, and sickly person. The badness of death can also be considered in terms of social goods. Other things being equal, the death of a president or pope is worse than the death of a plain person in view of the place of the deceased in the political or religious community. The death of a good father or mother with young children is worse than the death of a person with no children. The roles, responsibilities, and benefits provided by the deceased are all relevant in considering how bad a particular person s death is, all things considered. Yet in terms of fundamental worth and value, all human persons the young and the old, the beautiful and the ugly, the well connected and the isolated are equal in dignity. 6 Thus, all human persons, regardless of accidental differences in future goods, current goods, or social goods, have equal rights to live. All human deaths are per se alike in that each destroys a person of inestimable worth and value. Every human death is circumstantially different from all others in the loss of future goods, the loss of current goods, and the loss of social goods. In short, we do not need the TRIA to account for accidental differences in the badness of deaths. In addition, the TRIA supposes that death is bad because death deprives the one who dies of benefits in the future. In Killing and the Time-Relative Interest Account, Nils Holtug points out, The Deprivation Account of the Badness of Death states that an individual s death is bad for her to the extent that, had she not died, she would have enjoyed benefits (welfare units) in the future. 7 Thus, the TRIA makes an individual s value contingent on current or potential future welfare units enjoyed, rather than on an intrinsic property. As Holtug puts it, the Deprivation Account of 5 In answer to some objections to this claim, see Don Marquis, Abortion and Death, in The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Death, ed. Ben Bradley, Fred Feldman, and Jens Johansson (New York: Oxford University Press, 2013), 409 431. 6 See Christopher Kaczor, A Defense of Dignity: Creating Life, Destroying Life, and Protecting the Rights of Conscience (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press), 2013. 7 Nils Holtug, Killing and the Time-Relative Interest Account, Journal of Ethics 15.3 (September 2011): 179. 755

The National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly Winter 2013 the Badness of Death does not commit us to the claim that death is intrinsically bad for the person who dies; rather it is extrinsically bad, in the sense that it prevents certain intrinsic goods from accruing to this individual. 8 However, what makes the destruction of something bad is relative to the value of what or who is destroyed. Now things have value merely as conduits to other desired states of affairs. A smartphone is valuable as a means of communicating and computing but has little or no value in itself if it cannot bring about these other states of affairs. But, as Kant pointed out long ago, persons are not things whose value is contingent on bringing about satisfactory states of affairs. 9 The human person is no mere means to generating welfare units. Rather, persons have dignity, worth in themselves. 10 An individual s death is the destruction of that individual as an integrated organism. If the organism in question has intrinsic worth, then the death of the organism is something bad. Thus, while part of what makes death bad (circumstantially considered) is the loss of future welfare units, what makes death bad in itself for the human person cannot be fully explained by lost welfare units. Another objection can be raised against the TRIA, namely, that the Deprivation Account of the Badness of Death does not account for the harm of death as death. Many unfortunate occurrences can deprive us of future welfare units, such as kidnapping, imprisonment, full or partial lobotomy, drug overdose, serious stroke, intense sedation, or Alzheimer s disease. All of these (and more) can take away opportunities that we would have had for enjoying benefits in the future. But death is a distinctive and specific harm that is not exactly equivalent to these other harms. If an account of the harm of death is to be precise, it should identify the specific deprivation that death itself inflicts on its victim. The obvious candidate is that death deprives the victim of life, and life (the most basic bodily well-being of an organism) is a good for that organism. Indeed, an organism is what it is in virtue of being alive. Without life, what was a human being, a horse, or a dolphin becomes simply a disordered heap of organic matter. Death is bad in itself for an organism (indeed, death is the destruction of that organism), so the infliction of death is the infliction of harm on an organism. If the organism in question is a human being with intrinsic dignity, this destruction is a weighty moral matter. In Killing and the Time-Relative Interest Account, Holtug raises an objection to this line of thought. He writes, The Deprivation Account entails a proposition many find compelling, namely that death need not always be bad for the individual who dies. If an individual s future would hold more bad than good for her, it may indeed benefit her to die. 11 However, in a discussion of physician-assisted suicide, Jorge Garcia points out that death cannot be a benefit to the one who dies. Garcia writes, Ending her pain cannot be a benefit to her for the usual reason, then, because here [when the patient is dead] the patient does not experience relief and 8 Ibid., 170 171. 9 Immanuel Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals (New York: Harper Perennial Modern Thought, 2009), 48. 10 On this topic, see the magisterial article by Patrick Kain, Kant s Defense of Human Moral Status, Journal of the History of Philosophy 47.1 (2009): 59 102. 11 Holtug, Killing and the Time-Relative Interest Account, 171. 756

Notes & Abstracts Kaczor thereafter live pain-free. As the end of her pain here does not improve her experience neither does it improve her life, her condition. Rather, she (her integrated human life) ends along with the pain, and she is in no condition at all during the period when she is lifeless. We cannot, then, meaningfully compare it with her condition over the same time had she lived.... Thus, it is difficult to see just what benefit our killing renders her, as it improves neither her experience, nor her life, nor her condition. 12 Even if the individual s future holds more negative experiences than positive experiences, death does not benefit the individual but rather destroys the individual. Good can come from bad and bad can come from good without good becoming bad or bad becoming good. Just because something good (the elimination of pain) comes from something bad (the destruction of the individual) does not mean that the death itself is a good for the individual. The TRIA leads to several counterintuitive conclusions. First, consider someone on death row waiting to be executed in a few minutes. Just before the execution, a guard on his own prerogative kills the inmate. This guard does something seriously wrong, but the inmate has lost (almost no) future benefits since he was going to die momentarily anyway. Second, Holtug points out that on the TRIA, the moral assessment of an action ends up depending on whether or not the action is performed. 13 Third, Peter Nichols in his article Abortion, Time-Relative Interests, and Futures like Ours argues that the TRIA implies that it is morally permissible to kill Alzheimer s patients: It seems that an adult in the advanced stages of Alzheimer s Disease has very little time-relative interest in continuing to live, since there is only a very weak degree of psychological unity between such a person and herself at future times. Thus, the TRIA implies that it would be morally permissible or at best, only very slightly wrong to kill the Alzheimer s victim. [Jeff] McMahan s response to this problem is that psychological unity is the basis of rational egoistic concern, but that moral concern is grounded in an individual s intrinsic nature, which need not vary over time: [T]he basis of our moral concern for the Alzheimer s Patient s future interests need not be any different from the basis of our moral concern for her present interests. Her future suffering should, for example, matter just as much to a disinterested third party as her present suffering should, other things being equal.... Thus, as third parties, we need to respect the Alzheimer s patient s current and future time-relative interests, just as we should do in cases of prenatal harm. 14 But why, on McMahan s view, should the Alzheimer s patient be the object of moral concern? She is not an autonomous person and so, on McMahan s view, is not due respect. She has very little or no time-relative interests, so time-relative interests cannot ground moral concerns. 12 J. L.A. Garcia, The Doubling Undone? Double Effect in Recent Medical Ethics, Philosophical Papers 36.2 (2007): 245 70. 13 Holtug, Killing and the Time-Relative Interest Account, 169 89. 14 Peter Nichols, Abortion, Time-Relative Interests, and Futures like Ours, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 15.4 (2012): 501, quoting Jeff McMahan, The Ethics of Killing: Problems at the Margins of Life (New York: Oxford University Press, 2002), 284. 757

The National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly Winter 2013 Finally, Matthew Liao, in his article Time-Relative Interests and Abortion, argues that the time-relative interest account permits not only abortion but also infanticide. 15 Neither the fetal human being nor the newborn human being has greater time-relative interests in life than a normal dog, so neither should be accorded a right to live. McMahan recognizes this implication of his view: It therefore seems difficult, within the framework I have sketched, to avoid the conclusion that it would be permissible (and perhaps even morally required, if other things are equal) to kill the healthy, orphaned newborn in order to use its organs to save the three other children. (It should, of course, be obvious that [Peter] Singer s understanding of the morality of killing has the same implication.) Most people will find this implication intolerable, and I confess that I cannot embrace it without significant misgivings and considerable unease. 16 If the TRIA is commended to us because it is able to account for common intuitions about the badness of death, the implications of the TRIA for obligatory infanticide and harvesting a baby s organs weigh heavily on the other side of common intuitions. Indeed, obligatory infanticide for organ harvesting is a reductio ad absurdum for the TRIA. To avoid justifying infanticide, Liao points out that one could revise the TRIA so that having any subjective interests whatsoever is sufficient for granting a right to life. In this case, both infanticide and late-term abortion would be wrong, since both the newborn and the late-term human fetus have some interests, but a presentient fetus (lacking as he or she does all subjective interests) would not have a right to life. Liao argues that this strategy for saving the TRIA fails to work in part because if the threshold is quite low, then normal dogs also have a right to live. Many people believe that once a being meets the minimum requirement of the morality of respect for persons, then that being has equal worth to all the other beings who also meet this minimum requirement. Call this the Equal Worth View. On this view, even if other beings have comparatively stronger time-relative interests than this being does, all beings that meet the minimum requirement still have equal worth. 17 But this view would entail that killing a dog is just as wrong as killing a college student. This is hard to believe. In addition, once the standards are lowered (in the revised TRIA) to include both newborns and sentient fetuses, it is difficult to see why presentient fetuses should not also be included in the realm of protection. The differences between a presentient fetus and a postsentient fetus are often miniscule, but radical differences in treatment cannot be justified by miniscule differences. In the revised TRIA, both early and late abortions are excluded. So the standard TRIA justifies both abortion and infanticide, and the revised TRIA justifies neither late abortion nor early abortion. Thus, unless we are willing to embrace obligatory infanticide and the killing of adults with Alzheimer s disease (in addition to the more theoretical difficulties mentioned earlier), we should reject the TRIA as a justification for abortion. Christopher Kaczor 15 S. Matthew Liao, Time-Relative Interests and Abortion, Journal of Moral Philosophy 4.2 (2007): 242 256. 16 McMahan, Ethics of Killing, 360. 17 Liao, Time-Relative Interests and Abortion, 251 252. 758