Situated Ignoramuses? Jim Lang, University of Toronto

Similar documents
PHIL 1301 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY. Mondays and Wednesdays 10:30-11:50. Undergraduate Learning Center 116

Winter 2016: Epistemologies of Ignorance : Topics in Mind or Knowledge University of Windsor Tuesdays 1-3:50 -- DH 359

Bioethics and Epistemology: A Response to Professor Arras t

MDiv Expectations/Competencies ATS Standard

On the Rationality of Metaphysical Commitments in Immature Science

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

Diversity in Epistemic Communities: A Response to Clough Maya J. Goldenberg, University of Guelph

RECENT WORK THE MINIMAL DEFINITION AND METHODOLOGY OF COMPARATIVE PHILOSOPHY: A REPORT FROM A CONFERENCE STEPHEN C. ANGLE

Response to Gavin Flood, "Reflections on Tradition and Inquiry in the Study of Religion"

An Epistemological Position: Knowledge by Sensation is the only Knowledge that can be regarded as Truth. Leon Reynolds

The Human Science Debate: Positivist, Anti-Positivist, and Postpositivist Inquiry. By Rebecca Joy Norlander. November 20, 2007

UNIVERSITY OF WATERLOO DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY PHILOSOPHY 110A,

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Teachur Philosophy Degree 2018

UNDERGRADUATE STUDIES CERTIFICATE IN PHILOSOPHY (CERTIFICATES)

INSTITUTIONAL ETHNOGRAPHY towards a productive sociology an interview with Dorothy E. Smith

October 26-28, 2017 Harvard Divinity School Cambridge, MA CALL FOR PAPERS

Four Asymmetries Between Moral and Epistemic Trustworthiness Susann Wagenknecht, Aarhus University

Introduction to Technical Communications 21W.732 Section 2 Ethics in Science and Technology Formal Paper #2

The stated objective of Gloria Origgi s paper Epistemic Injustice and Epistemic Trust is:

Phenomenal Knowledge, Dualism, and Dreams Jesse Butler, University of Central Arkansas

Nonviolence as a Way of Knowing in the Public School Classroom. Anya Jacobson. The opposite of war is not peace- it is creativity 1

The Nature of Enquiry

Education, Culture and Epistemological Diversity: Mapping a Disputed Terrain

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles.

What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age

Tom Conway, Colorado State University, Department of English Spring 2015 Context: Assignment 2: Sustainable Spaceship Argument Overview sustainably

Cosmopolitan Theory and the Daily Pluralism of Life

Nagel, T. The View from Nowhere. New York: Oxford University Press, 1986.

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

Examining the nature of mind. Michael Daniels. A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000).

Hearts As Large As The World Charles Taylor s Best Account Principle as a Resource for Comparative Theologians

Comparison between Rene Descartes and Francis Bacon s Scientific Method. Course. Date

Against Coherence: Truth, Probability, and Justification. Erik J. Olsson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xiii, 232.

1 Introduction. Cambridge University Press Epistemic Game Theory: Reasoning and Choice Andrés Perea Excerpt More information

The Vocation Movement in Lutheran Higher Education

1. Introduction. 2. Innate Moral Sensibility and its Deficiencies

Necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pp. i-ix, 379. ISBN $35.00.

Katarzyna Gan Krzywoszyńska. Piotr Leśniewski. Archives Poincaré University of Nancy 2 France

The Scripture Engagement of Students at Christian Colleges

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true.

distortions in our collective knowledge resources and practices caused by racism and sexism affect everyone.

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

The Experience Machine and Mental State Theories of Wellbeing

Skepticism and Internalism

Course Organiser and Lecturer: Dr. Aidan McGlynn DSB 6.12)

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

A Review of Norm Geisler's Prolegomena

Bart Streumer, Unbelievable Errors, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ISBN

Feminist Epistemology Feminism in Analytic Philosophy Week One, MT 2012, Oxford

Meursault s Ethical Transcendence : A Žižekian Reading of The Stranger. What does it mean to be displaced, separated from the ever-present sense of

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

Act individuation and basic acts

MODELS CLARIFIED: RESPONDING TO LANGDON GILKEY. by David E. Klemm and William H. Klink

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

Histories, Logics and Politics: An Interview with Mark Bevir

Introduction: Goddess and God in Our Lives

Student Engagement and Controversial Issues in Schools

Review of Who Rules in Science?, by James Robert Brown

Philosophical Traditions and Educational Research

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Relational Knowing and Epistemic Injustice: Toward a Theory of Willful Hermeneutical Ignorance


Saying too Little and Saying too Much. Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul

JUDITH BUTLER AND THE VIRTUE OF TROUBLEMAKING. feminist ethics. The predominate understanding of troublemaking is that it is bad,

Summary Kooij.indd :14

LTJ 27 2 [Start of recorded material] Interviewer: From the University of Leicester in the United Kingdom. This is Glenn Fulcher with the very first

AN EPISTEMIC PARADOX. Byron KALDIS

Review of Stuart Firestein, Ignorance: How it Drives Science. New York: Oxford University Press, 2012, Pp. viii, 195. Lorraine Code, York University

Egocentric Rationality

Researching Choreography: In Search of Stories of the Making

Anthony Thorpe The Critical Thinking Skills Movement and its Implications for Religious Education

From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

On Being Conscious of What We Choose to Worship. Mrinalini Sebastian

Freedom of Religion and Law Schools: Trinity Western University

1. Why were you initially drawn to epistemology (and what keeps you interested)?

Contemporary Theology II: From Theology of Hope to Postmodernism. Introduction: Review and Preview. ST507 LESSON 01 of 24

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

2004 by Dr. William D. Ramey InTheBeginning.org

James L. Kinneavy and the Ethical Imperative

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Book Review. The Cambridge Companion to Dewey. Justin Bell

Towards Guidelines on International Standards of Quality in Theological Education A WCC/ETE-Project

THEOLOGY IN THE FLESH

Yong, Amos. Beyond the Impasse: Toward a Pneumatological Theology of Religion. Grand Rapids, Mich.: Baker, ISBN #

Essay Discuss Both Sides and Give your Opinion

Gilbert. Margaret. Scientists Are People Too: Comment on Andersen. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 6, no. 5 (2017):

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

Action in Special Contexts

Two Approaches to Natural Law;Note

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

3. Knowledge and Justification

What is a counterexample?

37. The Analytic/Synthetic Distinction

Transcription:

Situated Ignoramuses? Jim Lang, University of Toronto Reply to Susan Dieleman s Review of Sullivan, Shannon and Nancy Tuana, eds. Race and Epistemologies of Ignorance. Albany: State University of New York Press, 2007. 284 pp, and Proctor, Robert N. and Londa Schiebinger, eds. Agnotology: The Making and Unmaking of Ignorance. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2008. 312 pp. This is not a critical reply to Susan Dieleman s comprehensive and thoughtful review of these two remarkable volumes. Her reading of these works so closely reflects my own that I would be hard-pressed to find differences sufficient to warrant such a response and furthermore, I ve been granted some latitude in producing the first ever reply to a review, so I ve decided to use this space for other, perhaps more constructive, purposes. That said, anyone interested in reading what will undoubtedly become two profoundly generative works in the exciting emerging field of agnotology would be very well served by reading Dieleman s succinct and insightful reviews, especially as an aid to choosing which to read first. As a philosopher, like Dieleman, I gravitate more to theory while welcoming succinct illuminating examples and I therefore find all of Sullivan and Tuana s edited volume and Part III (Theorizing Ignorance) in Proctor s and Schiebinger s book more to my purposes. However, I also agree with Dieleman in suggesting that when used in courses from undergraduate to doctoral Agnotology may well be the better first choice as it grounds initial discussions of ignorance in examples which can then invite and set up a more theoretical reading of Race and Epistemologies of Ignorance. To my mind anyone toiling in epistemology would likely benefit from reading their own work through any or all of the articles in both of these books. The study of ignorance provides an important new point of entry to a wide range of epistemological issues, some of which have been pivoting around an S knows that P centre for decades with minimal discernable forward progress. Reading the same problems through an agnotological lens S does not know that P may well breathe new life into some of these intractable debates. For example, the problem of indoctrination has plagued philosophers of education for more than one hundred years, to the extent that the discourse on this subject is likely the largest body of work in the whole discipline. 1 This mountain of research represents a seemingly endless and fractious debate around S knows that P or, what qualifies as knowledge worthy of the name (Lang 1971; 2007; 2008; 2009). I believe that shifting the focus of the discourse from what is being taught (epistemology) to what is not being taught (agnotology) holds great promise for breaking the stalemate on this issue. Agnotology may also be of invaluable assistance in advancing work on philosophical argumentation and engagement. For example, feminist theorists have long since tabled 1 I have identified more than 100 articles and books on this subject in philosophy of education, as of 2008. 1

their exasperation on their inability to engage traditional philosophers in their work. Standing on analytical philosophical principles of argumentation, traditional philosophers seem enveloped in a kind of anti-feminist Teflon coating, deflecting any challenges to traditional arguments without even reading them in their entirety, in some cases (Lang 2010). An agnotological argument may offer a way of shifting the debate to focus on what ignorances may be serving traditionalists and how ignorance of their ignorance prevents them from engaging with new knowledge. Although there are many other possible examples others could cite as potentially benefiting from an agnotological focus, in the space I have left I introduce what I believe is a critical area of agnotological research that needs work, lest the emerging discourse trend toward the flatlining indoctrination debate, noted above. I refer to the brief section on situated knowers, offered by Linda Martin Alcoff as part of her useful organization of epistemologies of ignorance. Related to chapters by Lorraine Code, Sandra Harding and Charles Mills, Alcoff suggests three respective foci for analyzing the ways ignorance is produced: 1) via individual situated knowers; 2) via group identities and, 3) via larger systems (Alcoff 2007, p. 40). This micro to macro spectrum is enhanced further by Code s overall conception of an ecology of ignorance sustained by webs of distortion and error (Code 2007, p. 214) in that it suggests dynamic interrelationships among agnotological locations. Rightfully cautioned by several authors to not expect a perfect correlation between knowledge construction practices and supposed inverse agnotological practices, I would not suggest that an ecology of ignorance is congruent in all ways with Code s larger vision of knowledge construction detailed in Ecological Thinking (Code 2006). However, as a Codean scholar I am drawn to explore the beginnings of something I would call situated ignorances, which I suspect might describe, however loosely, the inverse of what I consider Code s greatest contribution to epistemological research her extensive work on situated knowledges. Alcoff s four-point summary of situatedness, from which she draws her claim that the epistemic implication of any epistemic situation is determined by the context of the object of inquiry, links situatedness to knowledge and experience in matters of who knows best in a particular circumstance (Alcoff 2007, p. 42). This is a useful application of situatedness relative to ignorance and I am curious to see how it might expand at the meta-level, to see how constructed ignorance insulates knowers from difficult knowledges, seemingly providing its own inoculation against the latter; and further, how the situatedness of a knower informs groups and institutions, ecologically. Coming at the subject of situatedness from a modestly different direction helps me focus the issues more in meta-epistemological terms. Given self-imposed limitations on my latitude for reply, what follows is little more than a reflection on situated knowers that formed while I was reading these books, in the hope this exercise will serve as an impetus for a full paper on the subject of situated ignorances. 2

Epistemologies of Situated Knowledges (ESK) Lang, Jim [2012]. Situated Ignoramuses? Suggesting something like situated ignorances requires some minimal foregrounding in ESK. Knowledge does not transcend knowers and it cannot be transmitted intact from one person to another, as Lorraine Code and others have demonstrated compellingly and repeatedly; 2 relatedly, as Alcoff also claims, individual knowers are not universally, innately, interchangeable but rather persons are the creations of other persons (Code 1991, p. 85; Alcoff 2007). Thus, knowledge is inevitably mediated by individual knowers according to their situatedness; it exists only as embodied with socially-constructed persons and as such knowledge is always partial and incomplete. More than a description of social location or a place from which to know, situatedness is better understood as an achieved stance unique to each knower. With Code and Donna Haraway (Haraway 2004/1988, p. 92), I view situatedness as a place to know, an achieved epistemic stance that it is mappable. Doing so not only involves taking into account the multiplyintersecting ways in which knowers are situated historically, politically, culturally, linguistically, sexually, among many more, including knowers power and privilege but also the ways each person has internally constructed a conception of knowing itself. To find out what a person knows, one needs to know how a person knows; because, importantly, as Alcoff points out, using Code, it does not follow that all knowers are epistemically equal since they are at once limited and enabled by the specificities of their locations (Alcoff 2007, Op. cit.). Clearly, approaching knowers as individually multiply-situated complicates the epistemological issues. Whereas traditional S knows that P epistemology aims to eliminate subjective particularities and to universalize knowers and knowledge, epistemologies of situated knowledges require attention to differences and legitimizes for inclusion and for interrogation the subjectivity of knowers. Contrary to traditional arguments claiming that the latter precludes any possibility of objectivity, Code, for example, argues compellingly to the contrary, claiming that a greater objectivity and better truths are possible on epistemologies of situated knowledges (Code 2006, p. 62). When knowledge is understood as being unique to and uniquely constructed by each embodied knower, it loses its singular universal status and becomes plural, with each knower s knowledges unique to themselves. At the same time, in crude terms at least, each person s knowledges become the raw epistemological material that generate an ecology of knowing that informs and encompasses social groups, systems and institutions. Taken in aggregate and considering the interdependence and interconnectedness of knowers, the larger epistemological ecology is well-described as a 2 See any or all of: Code, L. (1995). Rhetorical Spaces: Essays on Gendered Locations. New York and London, Routledge; Code, L. (2006). Ecological Thinking: The politics of epistemic location. Oxford, Oxford University Press; Lang, J. C. (2010). Feminist Epistemologies of Situated Knowledges: Implications for Rhetorical Argumentation. Informal Logic 30 (2): 309-334; Lang, J. C. (2011). Epistmologies of Situated Knowledges: Troubling Knowledge in Philosophy of Education. Educational Theory 61(1): 75-96. 3

social or epistemological imaginary, one that suggests the limits of what can be known and how it can be known. 3 Thus, the knowledges constructed by individual knowers in relationship with their groups, larger and smaller, inform the entire epistemological ecology or imaginary. These simplified claims are key to understanding the notion of situated knowledges and I share Code s view that they are revolutionary in their philosophical implications (Code 2006, p. 3). Epistemologies of Situated Ignorances? Much is rightly made of the power of constructed ignorance to prevent the knowledge of historical facts, as examined in Agnotology, parts I and II. I note important observations that archaeologists would systematically ignore indigenous evidence, for example, or that history books deliberately delete stories of racial violence. These are understandably the primary focus of social epistemologists, but how would these critiques be affected by implications of situated knowledges? In Agnotology, especially, I see many works ostensibly based on broad assumptions that facts and their supporting evidence are accessible to all knowers and that ignorance is mostly about knowers being shielded from the facts and evidence, in any of many different ways. Yet facts, as Code, especially, claims strongly, do not self-announce; they must be brought into existence; they must have makers (Code 1995, p. 168). Just as agnotology addresses some forms of ignorance, for example, in terms of historicity one cannot know what has yet to happen, for example it may be necessary to examine the role of situatedness to see if knowers have been constructed such that they can see the facts, recognize them as facts, and isolate them, individuate them, and know them in order to reverse ignorance. Perhaps most intriguing to me, at least, is the extent to which situated knowers contextualized in epistemic imaginaries are able to identify their own ignorance, to acknowledge what they do not yet know. For surely ignorance of ignorance represents a major barrier to expanding a restricted eye s view and thus is a barrier to recognizing and addressing the moral issues inevitably bound up in this discussion. This problem seems endemic to a range of contexts, in my view. For example, presenting white racists with hitherto hidden information that to others clearly illustrates the basis for racist claims does not guarantee that an individual white racist will be able to see the evidence. The question of how this ignorance acts as an insulating shield seems necessarily to involve interrogation of the subjects situatedness. 3 See, especially, pp. 22, 28-36 in Code, L. (2006). Ecological Thinking: The politics of epistemic location. Oxford, Oxford University Press. 4

Questions suggesting further research Lang, Jim [2012]. Situated Ignoramuses? I found these two volumes on ignorance to be among the most stimulating and potentially generative reading I ve encountered since I began work on epistemologies of situated knowledges. Singularly and in aggregate, these authors have raised in my mind, at least several careers worth of questions, one or two of which I hope to explore myself: If situated knowers knowledges are necessarily partial and incomplete, what then of ignorance? Does it transcend knowers? Can two different knowers share identical ignorance or does each person s ignorance reflect their situatedness? If knowledges can be imbued in the process of the construction of one s subjectivity as well as achieved by each knower in the process of applying his or her own understandings of rational autonomy, are ignorances of knowledges also co-imbued and/or co-constructed simultaneously? In short, how else do epistemologies of situated knowledges inform agnotology? Contact details: jim@jlang.com References Alcoff, L. M. (2007). Epistemologies of ignorance: Three types. Race and epistmologies of ignorance. S. Sullivan, & Tuana, Nancy. Albary, State University of New York Press: 39-57. Code, L. (1991). What can she know? Ithaca, NY, Cornell University Press. Code, L. (1995). Rhetorical Spaces: Essays on Gendered Locations. New York and London, Routledge. Code, L. (2006). Ecological Thinking: The politics of epistemic location. Oxford, Oxford University Press. Code, L. (2007). The power of ignorance. Race and epistemologies of ignorance. S. Sullivan, & Tuana, Nancy. Albany, State University of New York Press: 213-229. Haraway, D. J. (2004/1988). Situated Knowledges: The Science Question in Feminism and the Privilege of Partial Perspective. The Feminist Standpoint Theory Reader: Intellectual and Political Controversies. S. Harding. New York and London, Routledge: 81-101. Lang, J. C. (1971). The concept of indoctrination. Educational foundations. Edmonton, University of Alberta. M.Ed.: 96. Lang, J. C. (2007). The Great Indoctrination Re-construction Project: The Discourse on Indoctrination as a Legacy of Liberalism. Philosophy of Education 2007. B. Stengel. Normal, Illinois, Philosophy of Education Society: 247-255. 5

Lang, J. C. (2008). Indoctrination and Situated Knowers. Theory and Policy Studies. Toronto, University of Toronto. Ph.D.: 289. Lang, J. C. (2009). The DDI, ESK and ME: Troubling the Epistemology of the Dominant Discourse on Indoctrination via Feminist Epistemologies of Situated Knowledges. Philosophy of Education. D. Kerdeman. Urbana, Philosophy of Education Society: 403-412. Lang, J. C. (2010). Feminist Epistemologies of Situated Knowledges: Implications for Rhetorical Argumentation. Informal Logic 30 (2): 309-334. Lang, J. C. (2011). Epistmologies of Situated Knowledges: Troubling Knowledge in Philosophy of Education. Educational Theory 61 (1): 75-96. 6