Chisholm s Simple Souls vs. Clark s Extended Selves 1

Similar documents
Ridgeview Publishing Company

The Extended Mind. But, what if the mind is like that? That is, what if the mind extends beyond the brain?

Trinity & contradiction

a0rxh/ On Van Inwagen s Argument Against the Doctrine of Arbitrary Undetached Parts WESLEY H. BRONSON Princeton University

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

Skepticism and Internalism

Foreword to Andy Clark s Supersizing the Mind

Received: 11 June 2011 / Accepted: 8 August 2011 / Published online: 23 August 2011 Ó Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011

Russell s Problems of Philosophy

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

A Review of Neil Feit s Belief about the Self

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

EXTENDED BELIEF AND EXTENDED KNOWLEDGE. Åsa Wikforss Stockholm University

Is phenomenal character out there in the world?

Published in Analysis 61:1, January Rea on Universalism. Matthew McGrath

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Faith and Philosophy, April (2006), DE SE KNOWLEDGE AND THE POSSIBILITY OF AN OMNISCIENT BEING Stephan Torre

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

R. Keith Sawyer: Social Emergence. Societies as Complex Systems. Cambridge University Press

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

Philosophy of Mind. Introduction to the Mind-Body Problem

Realism and instrumentalism

Comments on Saul Kripke s Philosophical Troubles

Epistemic two-dimensionalism

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body

Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011.

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

Theories of propositions

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026

Chalmers on Epistemic Content. Alex Byrne, MIT

24.09 Minds and Machines Fall 11 HASS-D CI

Nagel, Naturalism and Theism. Todd Moody. (Saint Joseph s University, Philadelphia)

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1

Gale on a Pragmatic Argument for Religious Belief

On A New Cosmological Argument

Holtzman Spring Philosophy and the Integration of Knowledge

Philosophy 125 Day 13: Overview

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

Williamson, Knowledge and its Limits Seminar Fall 2006 Sherri Roush Chapter 8 Skepticism


Reply to Robert Koons

Can logical consequence be deflated?

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

A CRITIQUE OF THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. A Paper. Presented to. Dr. Douglas Blount. Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary. In Partial Fulfillment

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

Introduction to Logic

Coordination Problems

On David Chalmers's The Conscious Mind

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Kitcher, Correspondence, and Success

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

On Dispositional HOT Theories of Consciousness

PLANTINGA ON THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. Hugh LAFoLLETTE East Tennessee State University

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle

IA Metaphysics & Mind S. Siriwardena (ss2032) 1 Personal Identity. Lecture 4 Animalism

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

Grounding and Analyticity. David Chalmers

The free will defense

Molnar on Truthmakers for Negative Truths

The normativity of content and the Frege point

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

Philosophy 125 Day 12: Overview

2016 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers

Crawford L. Elder, Familiar Objects and Their Shadows, Cambridge University Press, 2011, 222pp., $85.00 (hardback), ISBN

Glossary of Terms Jim Pryor Princeton University 2/11/03

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

On possibly nonexistent propositions

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action

Primitive Thisness and Primitive Identity Robert Merrihew Adams

Philip D. Miller Denison University I

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Postmodal Metaphysics

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe.

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

Well-Being, Time, and Dementia. Jennifer Hawkins. University of Toronto

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

Revelation, Humility, and the Structure of the World. David J. Chalmers

Brain Death and Irreplaceable Parts Christopher Tollefsen. I. Introduction

Kripke s skeptical paradox

Transcription:

Chisholm s Simple Souls vs. Clark s Extended Selves 1 Selmer Bringsjord Selmer.Bringsjord@gmail.com version of 020411-1045NY As the bibliography for his volume (XXV) of The Library of Living Philosophers attests, and as his many students confirm, the late Roderick Chisholm grappled indefatigably for decades with problems related to personhood. Toward the end of his storied and seminal career, Chisholm directed his attention toward the view of the self encapsulated under the phrase simple souls. Proponents of simple souls include Augustine, Descartes, and Bolzano, but the clearest expression of the doctrine, and the most formidable defense of it, has been given by Chisholm (1989, 1991). Following the other just-mentioned famous friends of simple souls, Chisholm uses the term soul or self to simply mean the same thing as person ; he is thus talking about us: beings who persist through time and exemplify diverse mental properties judging, wondering, desiring, believing (in the occurrent sense), wishing, hoping, enjoying which themselves have certain key (tobe-discussed-below) properties. According to the doctrine of the simplicity of the soul, we are unextended and incorporeal substances. 2 Here is Chisholm just before defending the simplicity of the soul: I will defend the thesis according to which there is something that is metaphysically unique about persons: we have a nature wholly unlike anything that is known to be true of things that are known to be compound physical things. I will attempt to show how this thesis coheres with the traditional doctrine of the simplicity of the soul. And I will argue that the doctrine of the simplicity of the soul is, in William James terms, very much a live option. (Chisholm 1991: 167) After briefly discussing the defense to which Chisholm here alludes, I present an attack on it that Chisholm never anticipated, one built from the view, recently defended by Andy Clark (and David Chalmers), that selves extend beyond the human bodies in which they are usually taken to be enclosed. I then show that Chisholm and other friends of simple souls have nothing to fear from this attack. 1 Chisholm s Argument In the space we have here, Chisholm s argument for the simplicity of the soul can t be treated in the detail it deserves, but a level of detail sufficient for the purposes at hand can probably be reached. Chisholm s starts by encouraging us to examine our mental properties fearing ghosts, intending to work another two hours, believing that Frege s Axiom V has been successfully replaced by the axiom-schema of separation, etc. Such examination, according to Chisholm, reveals that our mental properties have five structural properties, viz., 1 As is the case with nearly all philosophy I write, I m indebted to Jim Fahey (who himself studied at Brown during some of Chisholm s rather extended tenure there) for insightful comments and suggestions on many of the topics treated herein. A full version of this paper, which perhaps at some point I ll get around to writing, would include systematic consideration of emergentism as set out and defended by Fahey and Zenzen (the latter a thinker whose thoughts on some of the matters here analyzed have also been quite helpful), and more recent statements of the extended mind view by Clark. 2 The simplicity of the soul ought not to be confused with the doctrine of divine simplicity, a radically different notion. Note also that the use of soul in Chisholm s simplicity account contrasts with it Aristotelian usage, according to which we could only be said to have souls, not be them. These issues, and others, are discussed in a paper by the late Philip Quinn (1997) on simple souls, to which Chisholm (1997) replies. [RC and PQ were together at Brown for many years before PQ moved to Notre Dame.] 1

(S1) Mental properties are open, in the sense that a property is open iff it is possibly such that, for any number n, there are n substances that have it, and n substances that don t. (S2) Mental properties are repeatable, where a property is repeatable iff it is possibly such that there is something that doesn t have it, but did have it and will have it. (S3) Mental properties are not compositive, where a property is compositive iff it is necessarily such that whatever is composed of things that have it is itself a thing that has it. (S4) Mental properties aren t divisive, where a property is divisive iff it is necessarily such that any compound thing that has it has a proper part that has it. (S5) Mental properties are internal properties of substances, where a property is an internal property of substances iff it is necessarily such that whatever has it is a substance, and either it is necessary to whatever has it or it is necessarily such that whatever has it has every open and repeatable property it implies. Ignoring certain technical details that needn t detain us, 3 Chisholm then defines a qualitative property as one that is open and repeatable, neither compositive nor divisive, and internal. Now here is his argument (Chisholm 1991: 177) for simple souls: Arg 1 (1) We have qualitative properties. (2) Every qualitative property that we are acquainted with is known to be possibly such that it is exemplified by simple substances. (3) No qualitative property is known to be such that it may be exemplified by compound substances... (4) Some of our properties are known to be such that simple substances can have them and are not known to be such that compound substances can have them... (5) We have a nature which is wholly unlike the nature that anything known to be a compound physical thing is known to have. Those who, like Chisholm himself, find the argument to be a powerful defense of simple souls, must apply disjunctive syllogism in a manner that falls beyond Arg 1. As Chisholm writes: [T]he conclusion of this argument leaves us with two possibilities: either (a) the soul is an unextended substance or (b) souls have a type of property that extended physical substances are not known to have. The latter option is defended by those who have argued that the fact of thinking indicates the presence of a peculiar type of emergent property in nature. (1991: 177) The fact of the matter is that the soundness of Arg 1 is perfectly consistent with some such view as that we are extended souls (brains, perhaps; or maybe proper physical parts of brains) that have properties not known to be possessed by extended things. So for Chisholm, and for other contemporary friends of simple souls (e.g., Philip Quinn 1997), the power of Arg 1 hinges on whether or not some form of emergentism (according to which our mental properties somehow arise from the ordinary physical realm) is plausible. Chisholm, as you might guess, rules out option (b) from the previous quote; he then arrives at a complete argument for the doctrine of simple souls, viz., Arg 1 sound (a) (b); Arg 1 sound (b). What rationale does Chisholm give for (b)? Note, first, that, as Quinn (1997) seems to acknowledge, perhaps the only sort of formidable emergentism is one aligned with supervenience. Quinn appeals to a brand of supervenience due to Jaegwon Kim, defined as follows. 3 There are certain disjunctive properties that have all five properties on this list, and they need to be excluded from the class of qualitative properties if qualitative properties are to attach to things that are capable of thinking. Certain conjunctive properties need to be excluded for similar reasons. Like Quinn (1997), I ignore these details, which are outside the focus of my paper. 2

(D1) A-properties supervene on B-properties = df Necessarily, for any object x and A-property a, if x has a, then there is a B-property b such that (i) x has b, and (ii) necessarily, if anything has b, it also has a. (Kim 1984, 165) The idea here would be that mental properties supervene on certain physical properties; such a scheme would lend credence to option (b). Chisholm s response is vintage Chisholm: If we take [this bolstering of (b)] seriously, then we should consider how we might go about applying it to some property that is quite obviously mental and not merely sensory. Let it be the property of concluding that it is about to rain. We should have at least one plausible version of how the explication might go. We would like to know, for example, how to complete the following thesis: (T) The mental property of concluding that it is about to rain supervenes upon the physical property of. How are we to fill in the blank? At present, the only examples we have are make-believe, such as The mental event supervenes on the Z excitation of the C-fibers, where one offers no real terms with which Z excitations and C-fibers might be replaced. Have there been any real attempts to answer this question? Or have there been any conflicting theories about what the answer might be? When we try to consider all the things that can influence one s mental life, doesn t it seem clear that the physical upon which any mental event depends would need to be put as an extraordinarily complex disjunctive property? One cannot help but wonder whether the finding of such a property would have to await the completion of the natural sciences. (Chisholm 1997: 69) Perhaps you find this line of defense to be at least somewhat successful. But there is another sort of attack on Arg 1, one Chisholm never anticipated. The attack appeals to the view, defended by Andy Clark and David Chalmers, that selves are compound physical entities extending beyond the human bodies to which they are usually taken to be limited. This is view has now splintered into many variations, but certainly Clark is still promoting it, and busy speculating about the wild future for humanity that the view portends. 4 The counter-argument I have in mind is this one: Arg 2 (1) We have qualitative properties. (6) We are composed (at least in part) of compound physical objects that extend beyond our bodies... (7) (3), i.e., Arg 1 is unsound. 4 The abstract for a talk by Clark at RPI on 2/9/11: We are entering an age of widespread human enhancement. The technologies range from wearable, implantable, and pervasive computing, to new forms of onboard sensing, thought-controlled equipment, prosthetic legs able to win track races, and on to the humble but transformative iphone. But what really matters is the way we are, as a result of this tidal wave of self- re-engineering opportunity, just starting to know ourselves: not as firmly bounded biological organisms but as delightfully reconfigurable nodes in a flux of information, communication, and action. This gives us a new opportunity to look at ourselves, and to ask the fundamental question: Where does the mind stop, and the rest of the world begin? Chisholm liked to remind people that when they refer to the mind, or their mind, they are almost invariably simply referring to themselves as persons. Where, then, do you stop, and the rest of the world begin? These are simple questions with simple answers, and the answers are based on the doctrine of simple souls. Put brutally, since you stop well before you get to, say, your hand, we should not even take seriously the notion that you extend into your computer. You can throw your computer away, and still be around, thinking just fine, and at least in theory, you could decide to donate one of your hands to someone, and after the surgery you could still be around, one and the same, thinking just fine. 3

This argument is formally valid. Premise (1) is of course one Chisholm himself champions in Arg 1. So if premise (6) is true, or even if it s judged to be plausible, the doctrine of simple souls would be threatened in a way that Chisholm didn t anticipate. 5 I turn now to an evaluation of the case made for (6) by Clark and Chalmers. 2 The Unexpected Attack from Extended Selves In The Extended Mind, Andy Clark and David Chalmers (1998) advance three main theses about the reach of mentation beyond skull and skin: T 1 T 2 Cognition extends into the external world to include physical objects other than our bodies and body parts (e.g., pencil and paper, computers, and perhaps in the future neural implants and the like). Dispositional beliefs can reside in, or at least be partly constituted by, external physical objects. T 3 = (6) We are composed (at least in part) of compound physical objects that extend beyond our bodies. No doubt I am not alone in finding this trio provocative, and the case presented on its behalf imaginative, but, as will be seen, C&C fail to deliver compelling argumentation, at least when it comes to T 3, which, for reasons set out above, is the heart of the matter. 6 Because the argument for T 3 has T 2 as a premise, we need to review the case for T 2. I ll try to show that T 2 should probably be supplanted with a more circumspect relative, but even if I m wrong about this, C&C s argument for T 3 will still fail in light of what we uncover in our investigation of their case for T 2. At the heart of the case for T 2 stand thought-experiments involving C&C s duo of Inga and Otto. Inga hears that there is an exhibition at the Museum of Modern Art, and decides to see it. She remembers that the Museum is on 53rd Street, walks to that location, and enters. Otto, on the other hand, is plagued by Alzheimer s disease; hence he carries a notebook around in which he writes down new information as he learns it. When he needs some old information, he looks it up in his notebook. As C&C put it: For Otto, his notebook plays the role usually played by biological memory (1998: 12). When Otto hears about the exhibition at the Museum, he too decides to see it. So he consults his notebook, finds the address, walks to 53rd Street, and enters. C&C claim that Otto believed the Museum was on 53rd even before he consulted his notebook, just as Inga believed the Museum was so located before accessing her memory. Since Otto is arbitrary, the idea is that we can generalize from Otto s particular dispositional belief to T 2 ; I readily grant this inference. But what argument do C&C give for the proposition that Otto dispositionally believes, along with Inga, that the Museum is on 53rd? This is not an easy question to answer; after much reading and reflection, I find at best two rapid enthymemes. The first is designed to counter an analysis of Otto that explains his museum attendance in terms of his occurrent desire to go to the museum, his standing belief that the museum is at the location inscribed in his notebook, and the accessible fact that the notebook says the Museum is on 53rd. This analysis call it A o is said by C&C to be 5 In fact, Chisholm said: Surely, whatever else I may be, I am not identical with any bodily thing having parts that are not shared by this body. (1991: 168) 6 T 1 strikes me as unexceptionable and routinely affirmed. The term cognition is an abstract noun whose denotation, by the lights of the cognitive-science literature, includes composite systems having as parts agents (conventionally delineated) and external objects. A mundane but convincing example is to be found in an account of arithmetical cognition multiplication, say in children, an account that includes not only John, but John s use pencil and paper to follow familiar algorithms. For textual evidence that cognition is routinely understood to be extended, consult any popular textbook in cognitive psychology; e.g., see Ashcraft (1994). 4

pointlessly complex, in the same way that it would be pointlessly complex to explain Inga s actions in terms of beliefs about her memory. The notebook is a constant for Otto, in the same way that memory is a constant for Inga; to point to it in every belief/desire explanation would be redundant. In an explanation, simplicity is power (1998: 14). Before we try to excavate the argument here, note that though they regard it to be pointlessly complex, clearly C&C see an analysis of Inga s actions that parallels A o. This second analysis, A i, would presumably explain Inga s museum attendance in terms of her occurrent desire to go to the museum, her standing belief that the museum is at the location recorded in her memory, and the accessible fact that her memory says the museum is on 53rd. Let us refer to the general schema of analysis and explanation at work here as A. Now, what exactly is the argument for T 2? Clearly, it revolves around some such general principle as P 1 If there are two competing explanations E 1 and E 2 for S s action a, and E 1 invokes fewer terms than E 2, then E 1 is to be preferred. The idea would then be to instantiate E 2 to an explanation appealing to A o, and E 1 to an explanation that treats Otto s dispositional belief as being partly constituted by his notebook and features thereof. I concede for the sake of argument that E 1 does invoke fewer terms. (I envisage a first-order formalization of the explanations, with terms having the customary meaning in such systems.) But there are many serious problems. For starters, P 1 is false. To see this, suppose Jones explains the movement of your arms and hands as you play a game of bridge by appeal to a lone, super-strong gremlin pedaling inside your skull, whereas Smith explains the movement by appeal to all the customary ins and outs of anatomy and intention and so on. We would not want to say that the gremlin story is preferred, despite its simplicity. The upshot would seem to be that the competing explanations in P 1 must both be at least genuine contenders; both must be to use one covering term in the interests of space plausible. P 1 is plagued by other problems. For example, in what context are E 1 and E 2 to be judged? Consider again the movement of your hands and arms as cards are played and tricks are taken. Suppose again that Smith gives an explanation that mixes folk psychology with facts about neuroscience, whereas Brown accurately explains things by appeal to technical biomechanics. Which explanation is to be preferred? I should think that the answer depends on the background metric at play. For a crowd of psychologists, Smith is on the right track; for a group of biomechanical engineers, Brown is. This time the upshot seems to be that some metric needs to be included in P 1. So what we have at this point is P 2 If there are two competing, plausible explanations E 1 and E 2 for S s action a, both to be judged under metric M, and E 1 invokes fewer terms than E 2, then E 1 is to be preferred. Despite these and other niceties, in the end, it would appear that all that will ever follow from P 2 in C&C s argument is its instantiated consequent, viz., that from the standpoint of M we should prefer an explanation in which Otto s notebook partly constitutes his dispositional belief. How will it ever follow that in fact dispositional beliefs can reside in, or at least be partly constituted by, external objects? All that C&C will obtain via their present tack is merely something like T 2 From the standpoint of M, dispositional beliefs ought to be regarded to possibly reside in, or be at least partly constituted by, external physical objects. 5

With M set to something like seeking economical folk-psychological explanations, we have in T 2 a thesis I gladly affirm. As I scour C&C s paper, I find no arguments for anything stronger. 7 With the stage set, let s turn now to the argument for T 3 = (6), presented in its entirety in the penultimate paragraph of C&C s paper: What, finally, of the self? Does the extended mind imply an extended self? It seems so. Most of us already accept that the self outstrips the boundaries of consciousness; my dispositional beliefs, for example, constitute in some deep sense part of who I am. If so, then these boundaries may also fall beyond the skin. The information in Otto s notebook, for example, is a central part of his identity as a cognitive agent. What this comes to is that Otto himself is best regarded as an extended system, a coupling of biological organism and external resources. To consistently resist this conclusion, we would have to shrink the self into a mere bundle of occurrent states, severely threatening its deep psychological continuity. Far better to take the broader view, and see agents themselves as spread into the world (1998: 18). This too is painfully enthymematic; logicists like me cannot help but wonder why philosophy, the most rigorous and impressive type of which is firmly and unshakably based in the end on formal logic, is so routinely done without the kind of explicit proposition-link-proposition-link... that formal logic (and, in general, the formal sciences) demands. Yet the quote is easy enough to unpack. First, to ease exposition, reword T 2 so that (i) it drops mention of the stronger notion that dispositional beliefs reside in physical objects in favor of the more palatable relation of partial constitution, and (ii) in place of the modal can appearing in the original version, reference is made to the type T of dispositional beliefs pointed to by Otto s notebook-based one. (Membership conditions for T could be extracted from the features of of [C&C s] central cases (1998: 17). 8 ) Then the argument can be reconstructed as follows. Arg 3 T 2 Dispositional beliefs in T are at least partly constituted by external physical objects. (8) If it is not the case that some selves are partly constituted by dispositional beliefs in T, then some selves are mere bundles of occurrent states without psychological continuity. (9) It s not true that some selves are mere bundles of occurrent states without psychological continuity... (10) Some selves are partly constituted by dispositional beliefs in T. [(1) (2)] (11) x, y, z ((x is constituted in part by y y is constituted in part by z) x is constituted in part by z).. T 3 = (6) Some selves are partly constituted by external physical objects. [(3), (4), T 2 ] Should Chisholm and others (including not just the aforementioned trio of Augustine, Descartes, and Bolzano, but contemporary Christians who are likely to be rather unimpressed and unruffled by the advance of human enhancement ; see e.g. Bringsjord 2010) who hold that all selves are simple souls take this argument seriously? No. While Arg 3 looks to be formally valid, while the 7 C&C s other main argument for T 2 comes in the form of a challenge to their opponents to show that Otto s and Inga s cases differ in some important and relevant respect (1998: 14-5). I grant for the sake of argument that this challenge expresses the kernel of a careful and compelling argument. As will become clear, I treat Otto s and Inga s cases the same on behalf of friends of simple souls. 8 We could say something like: A dispositional belief b that p for agent s at t is in T iff (i) the physical object in which p is represented by r is (a) a constant in the life of s and (b) directly available to s without difficulty; (ii) upon retrieving r s automatically endorses p; and (iii) at some t < t s consciously endorsed p via r. 6

mereological principle in it, (11), seems plausible (in fact, as astute readers will have observed, Chisholm s position on the self, sketched earlier, presupposes (11)), and while (9) is something the proponent of simple souls will certainly affirm, the argument has at least one obvious, fatal flaw: T 2. After all, we have already seen that C&C fail to establish this proposition, and have at best substantiated T 2. If T 2 supplants T 2 in Arg 3 the argument is no longer valid. If we propagated this replacement through Arg 3 to produce formal validity, the upshot would be the rather unimpressive proposition that some selves can be regarded to be extended. I have met seemingly sane people who regard all sorts of nutty things to be true; as have you. But suppose that T 2 is conceded for the sake of argument. What then? The argument still fails again, for reasons uncovered above. Recall the analyses A i and A o, and the general schema these instantiate, A. Now look again at premise (8). It is easy enough to see how, given A, (8) may well be false. This is so because, as we have seen, and as C&C tacitly concede, all dispositional beliefs of type T can be eliminated in favor of locutions that firmly preserve a psychologically continuous self. To see this, recall Otto, and the instance A o of A in his case. The resulting locutions are: Otto has an occurrent desire to go to the Museum. Otto believes (where this is not a dispositional belief in T ) that the museum is at the location inscribed in his notebook. The notebook contains the fact that the museum is on 53rd. Such locutions promote and presuppose a psychologically continuous self. So, even if C&C can devise an acceptable replacement for P 1 that yields T 2, there remains what even they have seen: a coherent picture in which (8) s antecedent holds, while its consequent does not. With premise (8) in limbo, Arg 3 fails. Cognition extends beyond skull and skin, yes, and the same may well be a way to regard some dispositional beliefs, but Clark and Chalmers fail to provide a compelling argument for extending the self even beyond an utter simplicity that stands in diametric opposition to their brand of externalism. References Ashcraft, M. 1994. Human Memory and Cognition. New York, NY: HarperCollins. Bringsjord, S. 2010. God, Souls, and Turing: A Defense of the Theological Objection to the Turing Test Kybernetes 39.3: 414 422. An offprint of the paper can be obtained at http://kryten.mm.rpi.edu /SB theo obj tt offprint.pdf Burge, T. 1979. Individualism and the mental. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 4: 73-122. Chisholm, R. 1997. Reply to Philip Quinn. In The Philosophy of Roderick Chisholm, The Library of Living Philosophers Volume XXV, ed. L.E. Hahn. Chicago, IL: Open Court, 68-71. Chisholm, R. 1991. On the simplicity of the soul. In Philosophical Perspectives 5: Philosophy of Religion, ed. J. Tomberlin. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview. Chisholm, R. 1989. Bolzano on the simplicity of the soul. In Traditionen und Perspektiven der Analytischen Philosophie, ed. W.L. Gobmocz, H. Rutte and W. Sauer. Vienna: Holder-Pichler-Tempsky. Clark, A. and Chalmers, D. 1998. The extended mind. Analysis 58.1: 7-19. Hahn, L.E. 1997. The Philosophy of Roderick Chisholm, The Library of Living Philosophers Volume XXV. Chicago, IL: Open Court. Kim, J. 1984. Concepts of Supervenience. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 45. Putnam, H. 1975. The meaning of meaning. In Language, Mind, and Knowledge, ed. K. Gunderson. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. 7

Quinn, P. 1997. Tiny selves: Chisholm on the simplicity of the soul. In The Philosophy of Roderick Chisholm, The Library of Living Philosophers Volume XXV, ed. L.E. Hahn. Chicago, IL: Open Court, 55-67. 8