David Lewis is well known for his theory of modal realism.

Similar documents
Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Fundamentals of Metaphysics

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Possibility and Necessity

I. Scientific Realism: Introduction

How Successful Is Naturalism?

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Some Good and Some Not so Good Arguments for Necessary Laws. William Russell Payne Ph.D.

DO WE NEED A THEORY OF METAPHYSICAL COMPOSITION?

Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities

Berkeley, Three dialogues between Hylas and Philonous focus on p. 86 (chapter 9) to the end (p. 93).

Branching versus Divergent Possible Worlds

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

In his book Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, J. L. Mackie agues against

Class 33 - November 13 Philosophy Friday #6: Quine and Ontological Commitment Fisher 59-69; Quine, On What There Is

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

Fundamental Things: Theory and Applications of Grounding

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Rejoinder to Zimmerman. Dean Zimmerman defends a version of Substance Dualism Emergent Dualism

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Philip D. Miller Denison University I

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

A Scientific Realism-Based Probabilistic Approach to Popper's Problem of Confirmation

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

The Positive Argument for Constructive Empiricism and Inference to the Best

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Dualism: What s at stake?

Time travel and the open future

Class 6 - Scientific Method

The Illusion of Scientific Realism: An Argument for Scientific Soft Antirealism

3. Campos de conocimiento en los que podría ser anunciado (máximo dos):

Psillos s Defense of Scientific Realism

Ultimate Naturalistic Causal Explanations

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Huemer s Clarkeanism

The Problem of Identity and Mereological Nihilism. the removal of an assumption of unrestricted mereological composition, and from there a

Lecture 9. A summary of scientific methods Realism and Anti-realism

someone who was willing to question even what seemed to be the most basic ideas in a

Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview

The Cosmological Argument, Sufficient Reason, and Why-Questions

Lecture 7.1 Berkeley I

Postmodal Metaphysics

Postscript to Plenitude of Possible Structures (2016)

The Question of Metaphysics

On the Prospects of Confined and Catholic Physicalism. Andreas Hüttemann

Argumentation Module: Philosophy Lesson 7 What do we mean by argument? (Two meanings for the word.) A quarrel or a dispute, expressing a difference

Nagel, Naturalism and Theism. Todd Moody. (Saint Joseph s University, Philadelphia)

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

K.V. LAURIKAINEN EXTENDING THE LIMITS OF SCIENCE

One of the central concerns in metaphysics is the nature of objects which

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

It turns out that there is an important class of sentences that we have so far pretty much avoided mentioning: modal sentences.

[3.] Bertrand Russell. 1

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

5 A Modal Version of the

Copan, P. and P. Moser, eds., The Rationality of Theism, London: Routledge, 2003, pp.xi+292

What Matters in (Naturalized) Metaphysics?

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

Chapter Six. Putnam's Anti-Realism

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

CHRISTIANITY AND THE NATURE OF SCIENCE J.P. MORELAND

Session One: Identity Theory And Why It Won t Work Marianne Talbot University of Oxford 26/27th November 2011

Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2

Van Inwagen's modal argument for incompatibilism

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

The belief in the existence of an omniscient, omnipotent and benevolent God is inconsistent with the existence of human suffering. Discuss.

Problems of Philosophy

A note on science and essentialism

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology* Oxford University Press, 2009

Stout s teleological theory of action

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Copyright 2015 by KAD International All rights reserved. Published in the Ghana

The cosmological argument (continued)

Searle vs. Chalmers Debate, 8/2005 with Death Monkey (Kevin Dolan)

Van Fraassen: Arguments concerning scientific realism

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

The Theory of Reality: A Critical & Philosophical Elaboration

Truth and Modality - can they be reconciled?

DESCARTES ONTOLOGICAL PROOF: AN INTERPRETATION AND DEFENSE

Transcription:

Aporia vol. 25 no. 1 2015 The Tangled Beard of Modal Realism Kelvin Jensen David Lewis is well known for his theory of modal realism. According to this theory, our world us, the universe we inhabit, and anything that has ever existed therein is just one among many. In fact, modal realism holds that there are countless worlds more or less similar to our own. There is a world, for instance, identical to ours saving one difference: in lieu of wearing a polo shirt today, I wore a button - down shirt. Other worlds are not so similar; one world, for example, consists of planets populated by unicorns. Another is governed by physical laws that permit humans to walk on water. Indeed, for any logically possible state of affairs, there is a world embodying that state of affairs. Since there are infinite possible states of affairs, there are infinite worlds. To be sure, these worlds are spatio - temporally inaccessible and causally isolated from our world, but they exist as fully as our world does. Why would Lewis preach such a bizarre metaphysical doctrine? One sole reason: usefulness (Plurality 3). Lewis believes that his theory resolves important problems in philosophy, specifically in metaphysics, philosophy of language, and philosophy of science. Of particular renown is the solution to a perennial issue in modality, an issue that can be summarized by the following question: what makes modal properties possible? What, for instance, grounds the property I have of possibly wearing a button - down shirt? Modal realism has a ready answer: I possess the property of possibly wearing a button - down shirt because there is a world like ours in every Kelvin Jensen is a senior majoring in philosophy at Brigham Young University. His primary interests include ethics, philosophy of religion, and political philosophy. After graduating next April, Kelvin plans on attending law school. This essay tied for third place in the 2015 David H. Yarn Philosophcal Essay Contest.

46 Kelvin Jensen respect except that my counterpart is wearing a button - down shirt. That is, modal properties are grounded in their non - modal realization on Lewisian possible worlds. Whether Lewis s theory can truly explain modal properties and provide the other benefits that Lewis touts has been disputed. However, I shall not argue with Lewis here; for the purposes of this paper, I grant the benefits, all of the benefits, that he ascribes to his theory. I do, however, want to explore an objection that he treats. In his book Counterfactuals, Lewis considers several complaints about modal realism. One qualm relates to Ockham s Razor and can be explained thus: modal realism flies in the face of ontological parsimony, which demands at the very least that one not recklessly postulate the existence of new entities. This prescription is two - pronged: according to quantitative ontological parsimony, one ought not to frivolously postulate additional individual entities; according to qualitative ontological parsimony, one ought not to frivolously postulate additional kinds of entities. Modal realism is thought to run afoul of both senses of parsimony it not only postulates multiple worlds similar to ours, but also postulates multiple worlds different in kind than ours. Inasmuch as ontological parsimony is an important theoretical virtue, modal realism falls short. Lewis s response to this objection is threefold: first, he admits that modal realism disrespects quantitative ontological parsimony but claims that this concession is innocuous (87). Quantitative parsimony is irrelevant to a theory s truth; qualitative parsimony is what matters. Lewis doesn t argue for this position he simply takes it for granted. Second, he insists that modal realism in no way violates qualitative parsimony; after all, possible worlds are not different in kind than the actual world. As Lewis observes, You believe in our actual world already. I ask you to believe in more things of that kind, not in things of some new kind (87). And finally, he presumes that no Ockham s Razor objection can be decisive (87). What he means is that violations of ontological parsimony no matter how flagrant do not, by themselves, warrant rejecting modal realism. I take issue with Lewis s response. Quantitative parsimony is a theoretical virtue, and modal realism does disregard qualitative parsimony. That is, Lewis s theory disrespects both quantitative and qualitative parsimony, both of which are important theoretical considerations. Perhaps a violation of ontological parsimony cannot be decisive, but the violation here is so egregious, even frightful, that we ought to turn our attention to rival theories and remold them to provide the theoretical benefits of modal realism, without the ontological costs. Let s examine the support for my claims. Lewis is not unique in dismissing quantitative parsimony without a hearing. Many philosophers have presumed that quantitative parsimony

The Tangled Beard of Modal Realism 47 is simply irrelevant to the truth of a theory. Why is this assumption so prevalent? According to Alan Baker, many reject quantitative parsimony because it doesn t appear to connect to independently recognizable theoretical virtues (248). For instance, qualitative parsimony can be justified by appeals to epistemic conservatism, which holds, at its core, that we ought not to believe in something unless we have good reason to believe in it (248). Syntactical elegance the other strand of Ockham s Razor, a strand which demands simplicity in a theory s basic principles or axioms can be justified on pragmatic grounds. A theory that is syntactically elegant is easier to use or manipulate, and is generally more comprehensible (248). From which theoretical virtue can quantitative parsimony be derived? It can t be derived from epistemic conservatism, for quantitative parsimony doesn t have to do with the postulation of new kinds of entities or mechanisms. Rather, it postulates additional entities of the kinds in which we already believe. Nor does it seem likely that quantitative parsimony can be derived from pragmatic concerns. Thus, inasmuch as quantitative parsimony can t be tied to any obvious theoretical virtue, Lewis is right quantitative parsimony ought to be jettisoned. It may be true that quantitative parsimony isn t justified by appeals to some recognizable theoretical virtue. But I think it can be justified by appeals to the workings of nature. Nature generally uses the simplest means to achieve her ends, and this fact justifies the prescription to keep down the number of individual entities, even if these entities are not different in kind from those in which we believe. If nature uses the simplest means to accomplish her purposes, quantitatively parsimonious theories are more likely to be true ceteris paribus. An example may prove illustrative: in the early twentieth century, physicists observed a puzzling aspect of beta decay, a type of radioactive decay in which an electron is emitted from a nucleus. Upon emission of the electron, the energy of the nucleus decreased by more energy than could be ascribed to the emitted electron. This result bemused scientists, who had anticipated that the diminution of energy in the nucleus would be equivalent to the energy of the emitted electron. Wolfgang Pauli attempted to resolve the discrepancy by conjecturing the existence of a neutrally charged particle a neutrino emitted concomitantly with the electron. This neutrino, Pauli reasoned, would possess an energy mass equal to the difference between the energy loss of the nucleus and the energy of the emitted electron. Pauli s theory was accepted, and the existence of his neutrino was empirically confirmed many years later. Two features of this example stand out: the quantity of neutrinos actually emitted from the atom, and the quantity of neutrinos Pauli postulated. Only one neutrino was emitted from the anomalous atom. Had the atom emitted two neutrinos, each possessing half of the energy of the original,

48 Kelvin Jensen nature could have achieved the same results (Nolan 333). Indeed, nature could have achieved the same results with three neutrinos, each possessing a third of the energy of the original; or four; or four hundred. But nature didn t employ four hundred neutrinos, each with one four - hundredth of the necessary charge; she selected one neutrino. In this instance, at least, nature really did use the simplest means to accomplish her ends. Interestingly, Pauli decided to postulate only one neutrino. He could have postulated two neutrinos, each possessing half of the energy needed to account for the discrepancy. This postulation would have yielded the same explanatory power as his first theory (Nolan 333). Or he could have postulated three neutrinos, each possessing a third of the energy needed; or four; or four hundred. Yet Pauli proposed just one neutrino. Pauli was apparently guided by considerations of quantitative parsimony, and even if he wasn t, adherence to quantitative parsimony would have encouraged him to postulate merely one neutrino had he considered the postulation of additional neutrinos. Therefore, it appears that a commitment to quantitative parsimony helps us to select theories more likely to reflect the workings of nature. At this juncture I anticipate two objections: first, although quantitative parsimony got it right in this scenario, it may not always pick out the correct theory. There may be some instances in which nature doesn t use the simplest means to achieve her ends. Moreover, even if there are no such instances, it s not clear that nature will always continue to employ the simplest means. This is a fair objection, and I fear that my response may be somewhat weak. I m not sure that the workings of nature vindicate the utility of quantitative parsimony in every instance, and I certainly don t know whether nature will continue to use the simplest instruments to achieve her ends. However, it does seem true that nature usually employs the simplest means. And the story of Pauli s neutrino is not unique: choosing the lowest quantity possible of individual entities, ceteris paribus, has helped scientists other than Pauli arrive at the truth (Nolan 342). If we are realists about scientific theories, quantitative parsimony is valuable. Second, although I may have shown that quantitative parsimony is an important principle for scientific theories, I may not have shown that quantitate parsimony is an important principle for philosophical theories. Philosophers may not care very much about proposing theories that map to the world; for instance, moral theories describe how the world should be, not how the world is. If quantitative parsimony is valuable because it takes into account the fact that nature generally uses the simplest means, then quantitative parsimony may not be a valuable or even relevant standard for evaluating some philosophical theories.

The Tangled Beard of Modal Realism 49 This objection may have merit. The principle of quantitative parsimony may be irrelevant when considering some philosophical theories, but this is not the case when considering theories that seek to inform us about how things are. And modal realism is a theory that purportedly describes how things are; therefore, quantitative parsimony is important to assessments of modal realism. Hence, Lewis is wrong: to concede that modal realism is quantitatively unparsimonious is not innocuous. Rather, the concession indicates a cost of his theory. Let s turn to my second claim, which states that modal realism is qualitatively unparsimonious. As mentioned, Lewis believes that possible worlds are not different in kind than the actual world, so he concludes that modal realism is not qualitatively extravagant. But his premise is patently untrue; many of Lewis s worlds are very different from ours. A plethora of Lewisian worlds are populated by ghosts, witches, unicorns, tooth fairies, talking vacuums, Greek gods and goddesses, and a whole host of creatures whose existence we have rejected. And then there are the worlds themselves. Some of Lewis s worlds have no past or future, others are bereft of regularity, in others there is reverse causation, and in others still there is no causation. Therefore, to believe in modal realism is to believe in copious entities and mechanisms of a very different kind than those in which we now believe. A more glaring violation of qualitative parsimony we would be hard pressed to find. Not so, responds John Divers on Lewis s behalf. In Possible Worlds, Divers admits that belief in modal realism does entail belief in fairy tale - like creatures and obscure mechanisms, but he insists that these things are not of a different kind than the things in our world. For purposes of qualitative parsimony, kind refers to broad ontological categories, like substances or properties (155). And modal realism advocates only two ontological categories: sets and individuals (155). But we already believe in sets and individuals; thus, modal realism doesn t postulate further ontological categories, which signifies that it doesn t posit any new kind of thing. Therefore, concludes Divers, modal realism respects qualitative parsimony. Is Divers response plausible? Not very. First, it s highly unlikely that qualitative parsimony relates merely to Divers broad ontological categories; and second, even if it does, modal realism commits us to the existence of every ontological category, rendering it unparsimonious on Divers own account. Let s consider these assertions. Qualitative parsimony is not treated as if it refers only to Divers general ontological divisions. For example, Cartesian dualism is thought to be less qualitatively parsimonious than material monism, for it posits two substances: mind and body. Mind is thought to be fundamentally different from body, so inasmuch as dualism has no more explanatory

50 Kelvin Jensen power than does material monism, dualism is charged with a qualitative parsimony violation, a charge that seems appropriate. But Divers interpretation of qualitative parsimony would not allow this charge. After all, mind is a substance, just as body is. Therefore, dualism does not postulate further ontological categories, according to Divers. Monists go awry in accusing dualism of being qualitatively unparsimonious. But Divers is clearly wrong: monists don t go awry at all in their accusation; qualitative extravagance seems to be a very appropriate criticism of dualism. Indeed, if qualitative parsimony is used only when dealing with theories that postulate what Divers considers to be a further ontological category, it wouldn t be used very much at all. Even if Divers interpretation of qualitative parsimony is correct, Lewis s theory is still qualitatively unparsimonious. For modal realism holds that if it s logically possible for something to exist and this something surely includes ontological categories then it exists. For example, there is nothing logically impossible about the existence of universals, so universals must exist. Indeed, any ontological category whose existence doesn t entail a contradiction is, according to modal realism, an ontological category that exists on some possible world. Therefore, even on Divers interpretation of qualitative parsimony, modal realism is unparsimonious. In fact, it s as unparsimonious as any theory can possibly be. I have shown that quantitative parsimony is an important theoretical consideration, and that modal realism is qualitatively unparsimonious. But Lewis, as mentioned, doesn t believe that ontological parsimony objections are decisive, so perhaps I have spilt much ink for naught. Why would Lewis believe that ontological parsimony violations don t, by themselves, disprove a theory? One might think that an ontological parsimony objection is decisive to a theory only if there exists a rival theory possessing equal explanatory power. If we didn t insert this condition, a parsimony objection could preclude the acceptance of correct theories. For instance, Ancient Greek chemistry is more parsimonious than is modern chemistry Empedocles hypothesizes merely four elements (earth, water, air, and fire), but modern chemists hypothesize 110 elements, as shown in the periodic table. Yet no one would accept Ancient Greek chemistry in lieu of modern chemistry; why? Explanatory power; modern chemistry, although more promiscuous, explains a lot more than does Ancient Greek chemistry. Indeed, due to greater explanatory power, we have committed ourselves to many theories that are less ontologically parsimonious than are their predecessors. What this suggests, then, is that the sword of ontological parsimony can t be wielded unless there are competing theories of equal explanatory capability and of greater parsimony. But we don t have

The Tangled Beard of Modal Realism 51 such a condition with respect to modal realism: Lewis s theory explains more than does any other rival theory. Hence, an ontological parsimony objection can t be decisive here. I have a qualm with the foregoing argument: to me, it s not clear that ontological parsimony is decisive only when dealing with theories of equal explanatory power. Our adjudications among rival theories indicate that ontological parsimony can be applied to a theory even when its explanatory power is unmatched. Consider the debate about string theory, for example. String theory is an attempt to unify quantum physics with Newtonian physics, which together can explain the motion of any particle. While Newtonian mechanics can explain the motion of macroscopic particles, quantum mechanics is able to account for the motion of microscopic particles. Why do we desire a single, unified theory? Simply put, the axioms of Newtonian and quantum physics contradict each other. So we seek a new theory, one with a consistent axiom system and the explanatory power of both Newtonian and quantum mechanics. Several such theories have been proposed, and we group these all under the category of string theory. Some scientists don t think that any version of string theory resolves the contradictions in Newtonian and quantum mechanics, but some do. But of those who do, few are eager advocates of string theory. What holds them back? Some are held by back by concerns about ontological parsimony (Grandy). The least ontologically promiscuous versions of string theory postulate the existence of seven dimensions; the most promiscuous, twenty six, and existence of twenty six or even seven dimensions is thought to constitute significant ontological baggage. String theory has no peer in terms of explanatory power, but we are hesitant to support such a profligate theory. In other words, we act like ontological parsimony can be decisive, even for a theory that explains more than do its rivals. Thus, if scientific methodology can be used as a guide, we are warranted, on grounds of parsimony, in rejecting a theory of superior explanatory power. In what circumstances is an ontological parsimony objection decisive? Inasmuch as string theory produces discomfort, it does so for two reasons: first, the entities that string theory requires us to believe in are very different from those in which we currently believe; and second, there seems to be a dearth of good reasons to believe them. The first reason strikes me as obvious: we naturally resist a theory which challenges our basic beliefs or assumptions about the world. The second requires some explanation. String theorists don t postulate seven or twenty six dimensions because they actually have any evidence to support the existence of so many dimensions; rather, they postulate a plethora of dimensions because it makes the math of their theory work (Kuhlmann sec. 3). But

52 Kelvin Jensen this seems to offend epistemic conservatism, which states that we ought not to believe in something without possessing good reasons. Believing in an entity solely because it provides theoretical benefits does not constitute a very good reason. What all this suggests, then, is that an ontological parsimony objection can be decisive against a theory if the theory possesses a profligate ontology and little evidence to warrant the ontology. I think that modal realism meets these criteria: the ontology is profligate, and the only reason Lewis adduces to believe in possibilia is because they are serviceable (Plurality 3). Thus, it seems that the ontological parsimony objection waged against modal realism is decisive. Where would the rejection of modal realism leave us? It depends. If we think that the benefits of modal realism are must - haves, then we ought to consider rival modal theories (like Plantinga s or Rosen s) and attempt to remold them to provide the benefits that Lewis s does. Indeed, with the plausibility of modal realism shaved off by the blade of Ockham s Razor, this appears to be the only viable option.

Works Cited Baker, Alan. Quantitative Parsimony and Explanatory Power. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 54.2 (2003): 245 59. Divers, John. Possible Worlds. New York: Routledge, 2002. Grandy, David. Personal Interview. 22 Jan. 2015. Kuhlmann, Meinard. Quantum Field Theory. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Ed. Edward N. Zalta, Spring 2014. Lewis, David. Counterfactuals. Cambridge: Harvard UP, 1973.. On the Plurality of Worlds. New York: Blackwell Publishing, 1986. Nolan, Daniel. Quantitative Parsimony. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48.3 (1997): 329 43.