Similar documents
Commentary on Professor Tweyman's 'Hume on Evil' Pheroze S. Wadia Hume Studies Volume XIII, Number 1 (April, 1987)



By J. Alexander Rutherford. Part one sets the roles, relationships, and begins the discussion with a consideration


David O Connor. Hume on Religion H. O. Mounce Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 2 (November, 2002)

The midterm will be held in class two weeks from today, on Thursday, October 9. It will be worth 20% of your grade.

Post-doctoral Researcher at the Academy of Finland. Department of History and Philosophy, University of Tampere, Finland

Philosophy of Religion: Hume on Natural Religion. Phil 255 Dr Christian Coseru Wednesday, April 12

Argument from Design. Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion. David Hume

Your use of the HUME STUDIES archive indicates your acceptance of HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions of Use, available at


Hume s An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY

HUME AND HIS CRITICS: Reid and Kames

Issue XV - Summer By Dr Peter Millican


Anne Jaap Jacobson, ed. Feminist Interpretations of David Hume Michelle Mason Hume Studies Volume XXVII, Number 1 (April, 2001)


The problem of God s cognoscibility in David Hume


Review of Hume s Philosophy of Mind. Hume Studies Volume IX, Number 1 (April, 1983) Daniel E. Flage

Skepticism and Toleration in Early Modern Philosophy. Instructor: Todd Ryan Office: McCook 322 Office Phone:

Locke s and Hume s Theories of Personhood: Similarities and Differences. In this paper I will deal with the theories of personhood formulated by

Evangelism #3: THEGODTEST

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

Realism and Anti-Realism about Science A Pyrrhonian Stance

Skepticism is True. Abraham Meidan

On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title being )

How to Become a Moderate SKeptic: Hume s Way Out of Pyrrohonism

A Hobbist Tory: Johnson on Hume Paul Russell Hume Studies Volume XVI, Number 1 (April, 1990)

Is the Skeptical Attitude the Attitude of a Skeptic?

Philosophy 1100 Introduction to Ethics. Lecture 3 Survival of Death?

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

Critique of Cosmological Argument

Anaximander. Book Review. Umberto Maionchi Carlo Rovelli Forthcoming, Dunod

What Does Academic Skepticism Presuppose? Arcesilaus, Carneades, and the Argument with Stoic Epistemology

An Early Account of David Hume. Hume Studies Volume 1, Issue 2 (November, 1975), J.C. Hilson

1/8. Reid on Common Sense


The Riddle of Epicurus

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

2014 THE BIBLIOGRAPHIA ISSN: Online First: 21 October 2014

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first.

A Studying of Limitation of Epistemology as Basis of Toleration with Special Reference to John Locke

1. What two texts does the author give that speaks to the timelessness of Scripture?

Of Cause and Effect David Hume

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

Something versus Nothing & Some Thoughts on Proof of No God

A Vindication. Hume Studies Volume XVII, Number 2 (November, 1991) Wim Klever 212.

A Review of Norm Geisler's Prolegomena


Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature ( ), Book I, Part III.

[JGRChJ 9 (2013) R28-R32] BOOK REVIEW

Reality. Abstract. Keywords: reality, meaning, realism, transcendence, context

Philosophy 428M Topics in the History of Philosophy: Hume MW 2-3:15 Skinner Syllabus

Naturalism and is Opponents

Plato and the art of philosophical writing

Who Has the Burden of Proof? Must the Christian Provide Adequate Reasons for Christian Beliefs?

QUERIES: to be answered by AUTHOR

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Epistemology Naturalized

THE PHILOSOPHY OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE

Hume s Refutation of Wollaston? Oliver A. Johnson Hume Studies Volume XII, Number 2 (November, 1986)

COURSE GOALS: PROFESSOR: Chris Latiolais Philosophy Department Kalamazoo College Humphrey House #202 Telephone # Offices Hours:

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

THE CRISIS OF THE SCmNCES AS EXPRESSION OF THE RADICAL LIFE-CRISIS OF EUROPEAN HUMANITY

Outline of the Apology 1. I. Prologue: knowledge is very valuable, though sometimes esteemed too highly. F, 319

Hume s Playful Metaphysics Greg Moses Hume Studies Volume XVIII, Number 1 (April, 1992)

TED HONDERICH, AFTER THE TERROR. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2002, Pp. vii A Review by Lansana Keita

David Hume ( ) and His Attack on Divine Action (Miracles) and Providence: From Empiricism to Skepticism and Naturalism

Pihlström, Sami Johannes.

EXAMPLE RESPONSES GCSE RELIGIOUS STUDIES B (8063) Marked responses Paper /1: 01.5 and 02.5

Hume and Collins on Miracles. Hume Studies Volume VI, Number 2 (November, 1980), David Berman

Reid Against Skepticism

1. An inquiry into the understanding, pleasant and useful. Since it is the understanding that sets

Luce Irigaray. To Be Born. Genesis of a New Human Being

Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues

ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis

History and Causality

Critical Notices. Sextan Skepticism and Self-Refutation * Renata Ziemińska University of Szczecin

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

SYSTEMATIC RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY. Contents

hal , version 1-2 Dec 2008

Louisiana Law Review. Cheney C. Joseph Jr. Louisiana State University Law Center. Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue Repository Citation

BENJAMIN R. BARBER. Radical Excess & Post-Modernism Presentation By Benedetta Barnabo Cachola

Stem Cell Research on Embryonic Persons is Just

Inconsistency within a Reconciling Project Antony Flew Hume Studies Volume IV, Number 1 (April, 1978), 1-6.

[JGRChJ 3 (2006) R65-R70] BOOK REVIEW

Philosophical Review.

ELEONORE STUMP PENELHUM ON SKEPTICS AND FIDEISTS

In Search of a Political Ethics of Intersubjectivity: Between Hannah Arendt, Emmanuel Levinas and the Judaic

The Paranormal, Miracles and David Hume

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

Certainty, Necessity, and Knowledge in Hume s Treatise

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On

Transcription:

Review of Marianne Groulez. Le scepticisme de Hume: les Dialogues sur la religion naturelle Eléonore Le Jallé Hume Studies Volume 33, Number 1, (2007) 179 182. Your use of the HUME STUDIES archive indicates your acceptance of HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.humesociety.org/hs/about/terms.html. HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the HUME STUDIES archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Each copy of any part of a HUME STUDIES transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. For more information on HUME STUDIES contact humestudies-info@humesociety.org http://www.humesociety.org/hs/

Hume Studies Volume 33, Number 1, April 2007, pp. 179 182 Book Reviews Marianne Groulez. Le scepticisme de Hume: les Dialogues sur la religion naturelle. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 2005. Pp. 154. ISBN 2-13-053579-8, Paperback, 12. Marianne Groulez s book has two objects: 1) it offers a general interpretation of Hume s avowed mitigated skepticism, based on the whole corpus of Hume s works; 2) it offers a study of moderate skepticism within Hume s Dialogues concerning natural religion, which is itself naturally grounded on the previous general interpretation. It seems to me that this second object actually turns out to be a global interpretation of Hume s Dialogues. Indeed, the study of the relationship between moderate skepticism and religious belief in the Dialogues enables Groulez to examine the whole economy of this book, the main arguments and the evolution of its protagonists, the place of the author himself and, finally, the link between the dialogue genre, skepticism, and religion. The first part of the book endeavours successfully I think to analyse the signification of Hume s skepticism. Groulez qualifies it as a metaskepticism, thus alluding to the fact that Hume himself characterizes its own moderate skepticism as skeptical of skepticism. The author provides an original interpretation of it, mainly through a comparison between Hume s and ancient skepticism. Of course, M. Groulez does not overlook the fact that in the Enquiry concerning Human Understanding, Hume explicitly identifies its own mitigated skepticism with Volume 33, Number 1, April 2007

180 BOOK REVIEWS the skepticism of the New Academy, whereas he rejects the pyrrhonian doubt as excessive. Nevertheless, M. Groulez recalls that Sextus Empiricus considered pyrhhonian skepticism as metaskeptical, that is, skeptical of the potentially dogmatical tendency of skepticism itself. This remark does not lead the author to see in Hume an unconscious pyrrhonian. Indeed, she notices that Hume s metaskepticism is also naturalist. Hume thinks that both reasoning and practical beliefs are natural necessities, whereas Sextus did not clearly state that theoretical belief belonged entirely, as Hume says, to the sensitive part of our nature. Groulez then shows that Academic skepticism may also be characterized as metaskeptical. More interesting, Carneades, one of the most prominent figures of the skeptical Academy, provided a quasi pre-humean description of the consistent skeptic: a genuine skeptic knows that his judgment must be suspended in all matters, he nevertheless assents to what is the most probable and, meanwhile, he perfectly acknowledges that this approval is not rationally grounded. This portrait is, indeed, very similar to Hume s own descriptions of the true skeptic (see esp. A Treatise of Human Nature 1.4). But, once again, Groulez points out an important difference between this ancient description and Hume s one. According to Hume, the skeptical assent to natural beliefs is not a privilege of the wise: his ideal skeptic is not essentially different from the common man. To this precise analysis of Hume s debt to ancient skepticism and of his distancing from it, Groulez adds a direct examination of Hume s avowed mitigated and careless skepticism. Two points seem to me particularly noteworthy: first, the difference which Hume implicitly establishes between carelessness (a positive easiness) and indolence (a negative easiness), second, the affinity between excessive skepticism and abstruse philosophy on the one hand (both rejected by Hume on account of their uneasiness and of the seclusion and melancholy they induce), and the parallel affinity between moderate skepticism and easy and accurate philosophy on the other hand (both valued by Hume in order to attain and communicate true knowledge). Finally, the author suggests that besides the form of the essay, which Hume considered as the most able manner to unite accuracy and communicability, the genre of the dialogue could also serve the same purpose. The study of the relationship between careless skepticism and religious belief in the Dialogues concerning natural religion forms the second main part of Groulez s book. In my opinion, this examination proves to be a fruitful approach to Hume s last work. Indeed, both Philo (who is explicitly presented as an adept of careless skepticism ) and Cleanthes (the adept of experimental theism ) profess to be mitigated skeptics. Besides, both accuse each other of being commited to the total skepticism they reject. However, Groulez firmly establishes that these characters strongly disagree concerning the due limits of their moderate skepticism. While Philo says in the First Part of the Dialogues and constantly maintains that the Hume Studies

BOOK REVIEWS 181 religious belief does not belong to the set of the natural beliefs which naturally limit, and ought to limit, skepticism; Cleanthes thinks that the belief in the Design of God is a natural belief to which a genuine mitigated skeptic should assent. More precisely, Groulez shows that Cleanthes adopts two successive strategies to sustain his claim: first, he presents the belief in the Design Argument as a belief resulting from a well-established reasoning from cause to effect (Dialogues, II); secondly, he presents this belief as an instinctive and unavoidable one (Dialogues, III-end). With this second argument, Cleanthes assumes that the belief in Design is similar to the natural beliefs which Hume himself, in Treatise 1.4, considered as proper limits to skepticism, for example, the belief in an external world or the belief in personal identity. Philo s refutation also has two stages. At first, he argues that God and the present world are two unique objects, thus incommensurable with the productions of human design; so that, at best, the so-called proof of Cleanthes reduces itself to a very slight probability. Secondly, Philo replies to Cleanthes that the so-called evident resemblance between natural productions and human artifacts is in fact the result of an anthropomorphical prejudice. Philo then suggests other better resemblances (this world is similar to a vegetable, an animal, etc.) which all aim at proving that natural religion is not a natural belief but is rather a natural disease, due to man s adulation of his own reason. Groulez very ingeniously remarks that Philo s replies to Cleanthes use two traditional (pyrrhonian) devices : 1. the discovery of an isosthenia between the arguments of the dogmatists and other equiprobable hypotheses; 2. the use of the arguments of the dogmatists as a weapon against them. Philo uses the first device when he counterbalances Cleanthes Design argument with other hypotheses concerning the origin of the universe. With the second device, Philo shows that Cleanthes favorite principle the liker the better actually makes the materialist hypothesis more probable that the religious one; indeed, men do observe innumerable cases of an apparent autonomous activity of matter. This technical interpretation of Philo s skeptical offensive enables M. Groulez to reinforce her idea that, according to him, religious matters are a proper target (and not a due limit) to skeptical assaults. Normally then, an entire suspension of judgement should be the result of Philo s skepticism. Nevertheless, it is well known that in the 12th and last part of the Dialogues Philo eventually admits that the arguments of experimental theism possess an evidence to which the most resolute skeptic must assent. Wondering how this apparent conversion is to be interpreted, Groulez considers that it depends on the interpretation one makes of Philo s willingness to mitigate his own skepticism. Some interpreters think that Philo acknowledges that the religious belief should be included in the set of the natural beliefs which are proper limits to skepticism. But Groulez observes that the evidence which Philo eventually admits is only so for the most careless and most stupid thinker (Dialogues, XII, my emphasis). At this point, Groulez makes an argument against Volume 33, Number 1, April 2007

182 BOOK REVIEWS the previous interpretation which seems to me perfectly decisive: Philo cannot think that the religious belief in a Design is a natural one, for he does not think it is a universal one. In Philo s opinion, such a belief is only the faith of the thinking part of mankind; it is a philosophical belief. Groulez then concludes that if Philo s discussion with Cleanthes has actually produced a change in his mind he actually discovers that an assent to the religious belief should mitigate his skepticism he does not state that such a belief has the extension of natural ones. Besides, he argues that it is a purely theoretical belief, with no practical consequences. These are two major differences with the profane natural beliefs. Groulez devotes the last chapter of her book to examining the relationship between skepticism and the genre of the dialogue. The author argues that this literary form proves to be suitable to skepticism in general and to Hume s metaskepticism in particular. Indeed, the dialogue submits all dogmatic assertions to refutation, and it makes it impossible for the reader to identify the Authorship s opinions and convictions. Groulez also supports a suggestion she made in the first part of her book: the Dialogues are a proper way to make abstract philosophy easier to communicate. Besides, this last chapter provides a subtle description of the evolution of Hume s own attitude towards religion as a matter of philosophical investigation. We won t reproduce here the portrait of Hume Groulez delicately draws while following the course of this evolution. We hope this omission will introduce in this review a flavour of the suspense which is also present in Groulez s Le scepticisme de Hume. To conclude, we consider this book as highly commendable, not only for the historiographical precisions it provides concerning the link between Hume and ancient skepticism, but also on account of its new and perfectly consistent explanation of Hume s Dialogues concerning Natural Religion. ELÉONORE LE JALLÉ Maître de conferences en philosophie Université Lille 3 5 rue Larrey 75005 Paris France e.lejalle@free.fr Hume Studies