Rorty on the Priority of Democracy to Philosophy

Similar documents
Sometimes doing what is Right has No Right Answer: On Hilary Putnam s Pragmatism with Existential Choices

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism

Kant and his Successors

Philosophy Courses-1

Philosophy Courses-1

In this response, I will bring to light a fascinating, and in some ways hopeful, irony

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

Bjørn Ramberg, CSMN/IFIKK, University of Oslo. Tensions in Pragmatism? The Science and Politics of Subjectivity

Anti-foundationalism and Liberal Democracy: Richard Rorty and the Role of Religion in the Public Sphere

KINGSBOROUGH COMMUNITY COLLEGE of The City University of New York. Common COURSE SYLLABUS

University of York, UK

Habermas and Critical Thinking

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

To link to this article:

READING RORTY POLITICALLY

Philosophical Ethics. The nature of ethical analysis. Discussion based on Johnson, Computer Ethics, Chapter 2.

Ethics. PHIL 181 Spring 2018 SUMMARY OBJECTIVES

PHILOSOPHY OF LIFELONG EDUCATION Kenneth Wain London: Croom Helm.

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Authority Beyond the Bounds of Mere Reason in the Schmitt-Strauss Exchange

Philosophical Review.

Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics

Critical Scientific Realism

Carlin ROMANO, America the Philosophical

In On the Genealogy of Morality, Friedrich Nietzsche launches what is perhaps. Ergo

Reading Questions for Phil , Fall 2016 (Daniel)

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

RESPONSES TO AIKIN AND KASSER MICHAEL R. SLATER

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo

Communicative Rationality and Deliberative Democracy of Jlirgen Habermas: Toward Consolidation of Democracy in Africa

On the Rationality of Metaphysical Commitments in Immature Science

Notes on Contributors

Well-Being, Disability, and the Mere-Difference Thesis. Jennifer Hawkins Duke University

Course Text. Course Description. Course Objectives. StraighterLine Introduction to Philosophy

O Neill and Korsgaard on the Construction of Normativity

Love and Duty. Philosophic Exchange. Julia Driver Washington University, St. Louis, Volume 44 Number 1 Volume 44 (2014)

Phil 114, April 24, 2007 until the end of semester Mill: Individual Liberty Against the Tyranny of the Majority

A DILEMMA FOR JAMES S JUSTIFICATION OF FAITH SCOTT F. AIKIN

Knowledge and its Limits, by Timothy Williamson. Oxford: Oxford University

The Critical Mind is A Questioning Mind

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships

Huemer s Problem of Memory Knowledge

Department of Philosophy

VIEWING PERSPECTIVES

PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY

Reading/Study Guide: Rorty and his Critics. Richard Rorty s Universality and Truth. I. The Political Context: Truth and Democratic Politics (1-4)

Evidence and Transcendence

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of

R. M. Hare (1919 ) SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG. Definition of moral judgments. Prescriptivism

POLITICAL SECULARISM AND PUBLIC REASON. THREE REMARKS ON AUDI S DEMOCRATIC AUTHORITY AND THE SEPARATION OF CHURCH AND STATE

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

Kierkegaard is pondering, what it is to be a Christian and to guide one s life by Christian faith.

Introduction: the original position and The Original Position an overview

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

HISTORY OF SOCIAL THEORY I: Community & Religion

A CONTRACTUALIST READING OF KANT S PROOF OF THE FORMULA OF HUMANITY. Adam Cureton

Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 5

The form of relativism that says that whether an agent s actions are right or wrong depends on the moral principles accepted in her own society.

DALLAS BAPTIST UNIVERSITY THE ILLOGIC OF FAITH: FEAR AND TREMBLING IN LIGHT OF MODERNISM SUBMITTED TO THE GENTLE READER FOR SPRING CONFERENCE

We recommend you cite the published version. The publisher s URL is:

Korsgaard and Non-Sentient Life ABSTRACT

HEGEL (Historical, Dialectical Idealism)

Yes But is it a Naturalism?

Pihlström, Sami Johannes.

Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning

Book Review: Badiou, A. (2007). The Century, Oxford, UK: Polity Press.

FREEDOM AND THE SOURCE OF VALUE: KORSGAARD AND WOOD ON KANT S FORMULA OF HUMANITY CHRISTOPHER ARROYO

Two Kinds of Moral Relativism

PROVOCATION EVERYONE IS A PHILOSOPHER! T.M. Scanlon

Why economics needs ethical theory

Human rights theory as solidarity

Process Thought and Bridge Building: A Response to Stephen K. White. Kevin Schilbrack

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Philosophy of Ethics Philosophy of Aesthetics. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Altruism. A selfless concern for other people purely for their own sake. Altruism is usually contrasted with selfishness or egoism in ethics.

Philosophy 102 Ethics Course Description: Course Requirements and Expectations

Others may concern the reliability of methods for forming belief:

Discussion of McCool, From Unity to Pluralism

Relativism and Subjectivism. The Denial of Objective Ethical Standards

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Notes on "Contingency, irony, and solidarity" by Richard Rorty (1989) Sunday, 21 March :23

SANDEL ON RELIGION IN THE PUBLIC SQUARE

Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008

Problems of Philosophy

The ontology of human rights and obligations

Thursday, November 30, 17. Hegel s Idealism

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God

Government Neutrality toward. Conceptions of a Good Life: It s Possible and Desirable, But Perhaps Not so Important. Peter de Marneffe.

A History of Western Thought Why We Think the Way We Do. Summer 2016 Ross Arnold

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

Review of Steven D. Hales Book: Relativism and the Foundations of Philosophy

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

Book Review. The Cambridge Companion to Dewey. Justin Bell

Religious Arguments in the Public Sphere: Rethinking A Free Speech Controversy. Jason Hannan Carleton University, Canada

Transcription:

Rorty on the Priority of Democracy to Philosophy Kai Nielsen I Richard Rorty seeks to defend and newly recontextualize social democratic liberalism and pluralism without an appeal to Enlightenment rationalism with its belief in universalistic reason and its concerns in morals, politics and science as well as concerns about Weltanschaungen over free and open discussion. If this conception is pushed to its limits it will, it is traditionally claimed, produce the truth, the one right answer to moral questions and scientific questions as well (Rorty 1991). Rorty, like Isaiah Berlin, believes that such Enlightenment rationalism has been discredited by twentieth century thought (Berlin 1991, 207-37). Like the religious world views it sought to replace, Enlightenment rationalism is a bit of mythology. Rorty seeks to defend a social democratic liberalism and the values of the Enlightenment that are, more generally, free from Enlightenment rationalism or any other defense of liberalism seeking philosophical foundations. He seeks, that is, some way of hooking on to the world that will give us an Archimedean point which would yield universal substantive values that give us true foundations or, if not foundations, the true rationale for our social and moral lives. The account he rejects is an account which would attempt to tell us either what the best possible life for human beings would be or what the just society, anywhere and anywhen, must be. Rorty wants liberal social democratic pluralism without such philosophical skyhooks devices he takes to be through and through illusory. He wants a reflective and enlightened morals and

2 politics without philosophical foundations, just as he wants science without philosophical foundations. Rorty s critics think that his sort of liberalism will lead to a debilitating relativism and perhaps even to a nihilism that is, in effect, the antithesis of the Enlightenment. Indeed, it is in some respects more like what Isaiah Berlin called the Romantic Counter-Enlightenment. It yields, if we look at its implications, a new irrationalism or at least a fuzzy lightmindedness that can in no way constitute a viable defense of liberalism. Rorty, to use his own phrase, would like to recontextualize social democratic liberalism and certain key Enlightenment values as well as Enlightenment rationalism. But, the criticism goes, coherent recontextualization cannot be saddled with such an aesthetic lightmindedness. II What should be said and thought here? I shall go at this indirectly by first considering how Rorty sees the situation. He thinks the undermining of Enlightenment rationalism will lead us, when thought through properly, to see that the link between truth and justifiability has been broken at least in regards to values. Enlightenment rationalism and the dominant movements in the religious traditions that preceded it thought that there was some tolerably determinate right way to live, some highest good that we humans have or some determinate rights that all human beings have simply in virtue of being human. They typically thought that members of our species everywhere and in all times and culture have the same rights and that, difficult as it is to ascertain, there is the one highest good. Our task as moral philosophers is to discover that one highest good and clearly articulate it. But if the philosophers were also liberals, they came to think as the liberal tradition developed that human beings would have many different conceptions of moral perfection, of what sort of persons to strive to be, of what sort of life plans to live by, and the like. The liberal idea here was to let many flowers bloom and to have no authoritative and comprehensive conception of the good life that

3 everyone was to march lockstep to. But some of them also believed that there is a highest good (though not a good that the State, the Church, or society should authoritatively prescribe, let alone try to enforce) and that there being human rights was compatible with there being many different life plans and ideals of moral perfection. People agreeing on these human rights and their centrality and didactic authority in moral life could have, and typically should have, very different life conceptions of the good. But liberals also came to believe that if an individual s sense of what was right or wrong to do or how to life her life in domains relevant to public policy was not capable of a defense on the basis of beliefs common to her fellow human beings, then these particular beliefs of hers, these life plans and these ideals of perfection, no matter how passionately held, must be abandoned if they have policy implications that would positively harm others. They can in such a circumstance only be rightly held if they have no such policy implications and are taken instead as merely private beliefs. Only when there is a thorough overlapping consensus concerning them within the community can it be otherwise and they can rightly be insisted on and acted on in the public domain and then only when insisting and acting on them would not cause harm to others. What on such a conception a conception Rorty opposes would save Enlightenment rationalism with its identification of conceptions of justifiability to humanity at larger with truth? Such an identification comes to the belief that free and open discussion, if pursued with diligence, integrity and thoroughness, will produce the one right answer to moral questions. They thought that a moral belief that cannot be justified to the mass of humankind is irrational and thus is not really a product of our moral faculty at all. It is, on such a rationalistic liberal conception, not in reality a genuine moral belief but a prejudice masquerading as a moral belief; it is not, in such a circumstance, a deliverance of conscience but merely of the superego. Genuine moral beliefs moral truths must be justifiable to humanity as a whole and not merely to some local embodiment of humanity. We must, that is, avoid ethnocentrism. If on such a conception we cannot so square our putative moral beliefs with those of humanity at large, we must, if we would be rational and reasonable, reject them

4 as unjustified. Thus, if we believe, for example, that abortion is murder or that euthanasia is taking in hand that which only God has a right to take in hand and we cannot justified these beliefs to our fellow humans, then we must not press these beliefs in the public domain; we must recognize that they cannot in reality be the true deliverances of conscience. We must refuse to take them as having public authority. Instead, we must take them as merely private beliefs without public authority, moral or otherwise. Rorty thinks that nothing like this Enlightenment rationalism is sustainable. We cannot find a justification for liberal political values, for liberal theories of justice or for human rights rooted in some ahistorical Archimedean point which would tell us (that is, all humanity) how we ought to live. Yet liberals we liberals, as Rorty likes to put it need something to distinguish the sort of individual conscience we respect from the sort we condemn as fanatical (Rorty 1991). We need such a rationale, Rorty has it, for explaining how it is we can argue such matters with Condorcet, Bakunin, Voltaire or Marx but now with Nietzsche or Loyola. In explaining how he thinks we should go here, Rorty makes a remark that is sure to raise a lot of hackles. To sort out the kind of moral consciousness we can respect from the kind we regard as fanatical we must abandon the search for rationalist skyhooks and come to recognize that we can only appeal to something relatively local and (as Rorty puts it) ethnocentric. What that will be is the tradition of a particular community, the consensus of a particular culture (Rorty 1991, 176). According to this view, Rorty goes on to add, [W]hat counts as rational or as fanatical is relative to the group to which we think it necessary to justify ourselves to the body of shared belief that determines the reference of the word we. The Kantian identification with a central transcultural and ahistorical self is thus replaced by a quasi-hegelian identification with our own community, thought of as a historical product. For pragmatist social theory, the question of whether justifiability to the community with which we identify entails truth is simple irrelevant (Rorty 1991, 177). Rorty wants to defend a liberalism indeed a social democratic liberalism without philosophical skyhooks or indeed without any skyhooks. He starts his discussion here by noting how and why

5 some critical theorists and some communitarians have rejected liberalism. For him we can have nothing transcendent or transcendental or even quasi-transcendental whatever, if anything, that means. Some critical theorists Herbert Marcuse, Max Horkheimer and Theodor Adorno most preeminently among them thought that liberal institutions and culture either should not or could not survive the collapse of the philosophical justification that the Enlightenment provided them (Rorty 1991, 177). Rorty also notes how they believed that these Enlightenment justifications had been discredited. This is also the view of Martin Heidegger and many communitarians. Among the communitarians it is stated most categorically and with the most persistent perspicuity by Alasdair MacIntyre. In coming to grips with this critique of liberalism, there are three important theses that Rorty states and examines separately. First, there is the empirical prediction and with it the question that no society can survive that sets aside the very idea of an ahistorical moral truth in the way that the pragmatists recommend. Such a society will not have enough social glue to do so. The thesis, to expand a bit, is that as a matter of sociological and historical fact we humans cannot have a moral community in a disenchanted world where different religions are tolerated like so many different cultural artifacts (and widely felt to be just that) and where pragmatism, fallibilism and historicism erode claims to transcendent or transcendental truth. In short, it is their view that pragmatism was the inevitable outcome of Enlightenment rationalism and that, psychologically and culturally speaking, pragmatism is not a strong enough philosophy to make moral community possible (Rorty 1991, 177). (Berlin seems, at least, to share this belief. But Dewey does not.) Second, there is the moral thesis, pushed very hard by MacIntyre and Geuss and which finds echoes in the Frankfurt School as well, that the sort of human being who is produced by liberal institutions and culture is undesirable (Rorty 1991, 178). Our liberal societies are, the claim goes, pretty awful places infected by a crass neo-liberal ideology. They are, as MacIntyre puts it, societies

6 dominated by the Rich Aesthete, the Manager and the Therapist (Rorty 1991, 178). This, MacIntyre maintains, is a reduction ad absurdum both of the philosophical views that helped create it and of those now invoked in its defence (Rorty 1991, 178). Third, there is the claim that political institutions presuppose some doctrine (presumably a philosophical doctrine) about the nature of human beings. This returns us to our starting point. Liberalism, uncritically accepting Enlightenment rationalism, the claim goes, adopted an unrealistic and normatively feckless ahistorical conception of the self, self-deceptively taking it to be an adequate account of the self and its place in the world. But, the thesis continues, an account that would actually support the moral institutions of a society or the world must make clear the self s through and through historicity. We cannot get along in liberal society or any society, if we are going to make sense of the moral life and of our institutions, with an ahistorical conception of the self (Rorty 1991, 178). We must instead have a culturally embedded self. This is a view powerfully developed by the communitarian theorists Charles Taylor and Michael Sandel as well as by MacIntyre and Geuss and historically it is rooted in Hegel s thought and particularly in his criticism of Kant. III Rorty devotes most of his discussion to the third thesis. But concerning all three he remarks: The first claim is a straightforward empirical, sociological-historical one about the sort of glue that is required to hold a community together. The second is a straightforward moral judgment that the advantages of contemporary liberal democracy are outweighed by the disadvantages, by the ignoble and sordid character of the culture and the individual human beings that it produces. The third claim, however, is the most puzzling and complex. I shall concentrate on this third, most puzzling claim, although toward the end I shall return briefly to the first two (Rorty 1991, 178). Rorty thinks there are two crucial questions that we should ask in coming to grips with the third thesis. They are:

7 1. Does liberal democracy need any philosophical justification at all? 2. Does the conception of the self articulated by communitarians such as Charles Taylor a conception which makes the community constitutive of the individual comport better with liberal democracy than the Enlightenment conception of the self? (This assume, of course, that there is something called the Enlightenment conception of the self.) Rorty, not unsurprisingly, answers the first question in the negative and the second question in the positive. Liberal democracy does not need, and indeed should not seek, in justifying and rationalization its institutions and moral and political commitments, a philosophical foundation any more than it needs a theological one. We can, and indeed must, given the intractable pluralism of our societies and a belief in the respect for persons, avoid taking any such anti-theological stance. Where religious believers do not try to intervene in the public domain, they should be left to benign neglect or at least unopposed. As much as I admire Lenin, we should not take his religious approach to religion. As long as religion does not go around persecuting people it should be left alone (Nielsen ). In the course of explaining and justifying this answer, Rorty draws a useful distinction between a philosophical articulation and a philosophical backdrop or foundation. He thinks that John Dewey and John Rawls give liberal social democracy a philosophical articulation and that this may, at least for certain persons and in certain intellectual climates, be useful and indeed for some it may be very valuable. It may, that is, be a very good thing that there are public intellectuals in a society, including a liberal society, who can perspicuously represent that society to itself: that is, make clear the rationale of its institutions and social practices and show people in that society how things hang together. This may include giving us a picture of human nature or the self which comports better with the institutions and practices of the society than the more traditional philosophical conceptions that the society has inherited. John Dewey, Rorty maintains, did this very well for liberal democracy. He found ways of talking about human nature and morality that squared better and were less intellectually problematic than the society s inherited foundationalist and metaphysical or theological articulations. But a philosopher doing what Dewey does does not thereby justify these

8 institutions by reference to more fundamental premises or by some theory of human nature. Just the reverse: he or she is putting politics first and tailors a philosophy to suit. Communitarians, by contrast, often speak as though political institutions were no better than their philosophical foundations (Rorty 1991, 1878). (This is particularly clear in Michael Sandel.) The pragmatists were adept at such philosophical articulations without philosophical foundations as, on Rorty s reading, is John Rawls, particularly in his later writings centering around his Justice as Fairness: Political not Metaphysical (Rawls 1999, 388-414). Rawls, Rorty claims, following up on Dewey, shows us how liberal democracy can get along without philosophical presuppositions. He has thus shown us how we can disregard the third communitarian claim (Rorty 1991, 179). Bibliography Berlin, Isaiah (1991). The Crooked Timber of Humanity: Chapters in the History of Ideas. New York: Alfred A. Knopf. Nielsen, Kai (1999). Taking Rorty Seriously. Dialogue XXXVII, 503-18. Rawls, John (1999). Justice as Fairness: Political not Metaphysical. In Samuel Freeman, ed., John Rawls: Collected Papers. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 388-414. Rorty, Richard (1991). The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy. In Richard Rorty, Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth: Philosophical Papers. London: Cambridge University Press, 175-96.