A Reply to New Zeno. appeared in Analysis v.60, #2 (April 2000) S. Yablo

Similar documents
The St. Petersburg paradox & the two envelope paradox

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

How Gödelian Ontological Arguments Fail

Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard

A Liar Paradox. Richard G. Heck, Jr. Brown University

On Infinite Size. Bruno Whittle

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

Intersubstitutivity Principles and the Generalization Function of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh. Shawn Standefer University of Melbourne

JAMES CAIN. wants a cause. I answer, that the uniting. or several distinct members into one body, is performed merely by

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

= (value of LEAVE if rain x chance of rain) + (value of LEAVE if dry x chance of dry) = -20 x x.5 = -9

The problem of evil & the free will defense

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

THE RELATION BETWEEN THE GENERAL MAXIM OF CAUSALITY AND THE PRINCIPLE OF UNIFORMITY IN HUME S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE

AGENT CAUSATION AND RESPONSIBILITY: A REPLY TO FLINT

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 3

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

Summer Preparation Work

On the Aristotelian Square of Opposition

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports. Stephen Schiffer New York University

NB: Presentations will be assigned on the second week. Suggested essay topics will be distributed in May.

What God Could Have Made

Moore s paradoxes, Evans s principle and self-knowledge

Puzzles of attitude ascriptions

The Kalam Cosmological Argument provides no support for theism

Supplementary Section 6S.7

Potentialism about set theory

Searle vs. Chalmers Debate, 8/2005 with Death Monkey (Kevin Dolan)

Is the law of excluded middle a law of logic?

Believing Epistemic Contradictions

Logic I or Moving in on the Monkey & Bananas Problem

The Quality of Mercy is Not Strained: Justice and Mercy in Proslogion 9-11

Vagueness and supervaluations

A Short Course in Logic Example 3

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014

R. G. Collingwood, An Essay on Metaphysics, Clarendon Press, Oxford p : the term cause has at least three different senses:

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY

A Puzzle about Knowing Conditionals i. (final draft) Daniel Rothschild University College London. and. Levi Spectre The Open University of Israel

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Scott Soames: Understanding Truth

Today we begin our discussion of the existence of God.

Why Counterpart Theory and Four-Dimensionalism are Incompatible. Suppose that God creates ex nihilo a bronze statue of a

TWO NO, THREE DOGMAS OF PHILOSOPHICAL THEOLOGY

INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC 1 Sets, Relations, and Arguments

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Aboutness and Justification

Shieva Kleinschmidt [This is a draft I completed while at Rutgers. Please do not cite without permission.] Conditional Desires.

Spinoza s Modal-Ontological Argument for Monism

Coordination Problems

Cartesian Rationalism

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

The Cosmological Argument

Confirmation Gary Hardegree Department of Philosophy University of Massachusetts Amherst, MA 01003

Nozick s fourth condition

Grokking Pain. S. Yablo. draft of June 2, 2000

MITOCW Lec 2 MIT 6.042J Mathematics for Computer Science, Fall 2010

SUPPOSITIONAL REASONING AND PERCEPTUAL JUSTIFICATION

Warrant and accidentally true belief

The Kalam Cosmological Argument

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

WRIGHT ON BORDERLINE CASES AND BIVALENCE 1

Knowability as Learning

CRITICAL THINKING (CT) MODEL PART 1 GENERAL CONCEPTS

Intro: The Toulmin Model for Arguments

On the Coherence of Strict Finitism

DO TROPES RESOLVE THE PROBLEM OF MENTAL CAUSATION?

Natural Deduction for Sentence Logic

Published in Michal Peliš (ed.) The Logica Yearbook 2007 (Prague: Filosofia), pp , 2008.

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016

Cartesian Rationalism

The Paradox of the Question

In his paper Studies of Logical Confirmation, Carl Hempel discusses

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2011

Hardback?18.00 ISBN

Material objects: composition & constitution

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning

What would be so bad about not having libertarian free will?

Can logical consequence be deflated?

1. Introduction. 2. Clearing Up Some Confusions About the Philosophy of Mathematics

The Externalist and the Structuralist Responses To Skepticism. David Chalmers

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology

On Interpretation. Section 1. Aristotle Translated by E. M. Edghill. Part 1

Informalizing Formal Logic

Finite Reasons without Foundations

Figure 1 Figure 2 U S S. non-p P P

Does the Third Man Argument refute the theory of forms?

The Zimboic Hunch By Damir Mladić

Is Innate Foreknowledge Possible to a Temporal God?

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio

Proofs of Non-existence

The Role of Love in the Thought of Kant and Kierkegaard

A Solution to the Gettier Problem Keota Fields. the three traditional conditions for knowledge, have been discussed extensively in the

A simple solution to the hardest logic puzzle ever

Transcription:

A Reply to New Zeno appeared in Analysis v.60, #2 (April 2000) S. Yablo I. A new Zeno paradox has been devised that looks at first sight rather more challenging than the old ones. It begins like so: A man decides to walk one mile from A to B. A god waits in readiness to throw up a wall blocking the man's further advance when the man has travelled 1/2 mile. A second God (unbeknownst to the first) waits in readiness to throw up a wall of his own blocking the man s further advance when the man has travelled 1/4 mile. A third God etc. It is clear that this infinite sequence of mere intentions (assuming the contrary to fact conditional that each God would succeed in executing his intensions if given the opportunity) logically entails...that the man will be arrested at point A; he will not be able to pass beyond it, even though not a single wall will in fact be thrown down in his path (Bernardete 1964: 259). So far this is just a surprising result. But a contradiction ensues if we stipulate -- what seems anyway implicit in the original set-up -- that the man does not stop unless a barrier is put in his way. Now we can infer from the fact that no walls are thrown down that he eventually makes it to B, and so in particular makes it past A. So he both does and doesn't progress beyond A. 1

Borrowing from Priest (1999), we can see the paradox as disclosing an unexpected inconsistency between some innocent-looking assumptions. Suppose that object α is gliding in from the left along an infinite number line, with A and B at the x=0 and x=1 marks respectively. The Gods are waiting to set up their walls if α goes anywhere to the right of A, that is, if α s position on the x-axis becomes positive. Let Rx mean that α reaches point x, and Bx mean that a barrier is put up at x while α is to the left of x, that is, while α is at some y<x. Our first three premises describe what Priest calls general features of α's motion. First, α passes through all points to the left of points it passes through: (1) (Rx & y<x) Ry Second, α can t pass through barriers: (2) (By & y<x) Rx. Third, barriers are the only thing that can prevent α s forward advance: (3) ( x (x<y Bx)) Ry One final assumption gives the rules for barrier-introduction. A barrier is put up at x iff x =1/2 n for some n, and α makes it halfway to x, that is to the 1/2 n+1 mark: 2

(4) Bx <--> ( n (x = 1/2 n ) & R(x/2)). From (1), (2), and (4), we see that α will advance no further than x>0. For suppose that α makes it to x = 1/2 n. By (1), α has already advanced to to x/4, whence (4) tells us that a barrier has been put up at x/2. But then α never makes it to x, by (2). α can't get past 0 without reaching 1/2 n for some n, so α is stopped at 0. That being so, though, we can conclude by (4) that no barriers are ever put in α s path. And now (3) tells us that α gets as far to the right as you like, contrary to our earlier conclusion that it stops at x=0. What are we to make of this? Priest says, plausibly enough, that (1) to (3) are features of continuous motion, and are true in this world. Although (4) is not true in this world there are no parts of the world where passing certain spots brings barriers spontaneously into existence -- it certainly seems as though it could be. There could, for instance, be a demon. The demon is bound by the laws of physics, and so, in particular cannot suspend the laws of motion (1) to (3). Yet it might mine an area of space in accordance with (4) Alternatively, to use Bernardete's example, there might be an infinitude of such demons, each of which has the appropriate intention. There are imaginable circumstances, then, Priest reasons, in which motion produces contradictions. And this seems little different from saying that motion itself could be contradictory. Are these conclusions warranted? 3

They are if we can take it for granted, as Priest does, that if there were an infinitude of demons, each of which has the appropriate intention, then (4) would be true, that is, the system of barriers would work as advertised. But what if the demons aren't able to do as they intend? Bernardete is more careful. He sees the need to assume as well that each demon would succeed in executing his intentions if given the opportunity. A case can be made, though, that the stronger assumption is still not strong enough. For it isn t in general true that if each member of a group is able to do as she intends, whatever the others do, then the members can execute their intentions en masse. Imagine that our infinite series of demons is asked to call off YES s and NO s in reverse order, with demon n calling off after demon n+1. (They can do this in finite time if the nth demon calls off at t = 1/2 n.) Each demon wants to be the first to say YES, but would rather say NO if she cannot be first. Each demon thus forms the intention of calling YES if and only all the earlier-calling demons have called NO, and calling NO if and only if some earlier-calling demon has called YES. If we focus on any particular demon, there is nothing to stop her from executing her intention, given the opportunity. All she has to do is call YES iff her predecessors have called NO, otherwise NO. Does it follow that there is nothing to stop the demons from fulfilling their intentions as a group? Logic stops them. Either some demon says YES or none do. If none do, then all should, because their predecessors have all said NO. If some do, then for some n the nth demon says YES. If she has been faithful to her intentions, then for all m>n, the mth demon has said NO. But then the (n+1)st demon's 4

predecessors have all said NO, and so the (n+1)st demon should have called not NO but YES. Not all of the demons, then, can have stuck to the plan. Now let s go back to the original paradox, except this time let s forget about α. The demons have decided, quite apart from any desire to thwart α, to do some reverse-order wall-building. Each demon n resolves that (R) I will put up my wall if and only if no demon m with m>n has put up hers. It s clear from the argument given that not all the demons can act in accordance with (R). At least one will put up a wall despite that walls have already been been put up, or refrain from doing so despite that no walls have yet been put up. But then it should be equally clear that if α were to make it past 0, not all of the demons would be able to carry out their original resolution (R 0 ) I will put up my wall if and only if α makes it half-way to me. Should α make it past 0, then given the stated constraints on its motion -- in particular the fact that α gets to 1/2 n+1 iff no walls have yet been put in its path -- success in carrying out (R 0 ) would ipso facto be success in carrying out (R). 5

Where does this leave us? The paradox turns on a lemma: α stops at 0. It has to stop at 0, for we get a contradiction when we try to work out α s progress through the gauntlet of demons. But maybe the reason for the contradiction is that the gauntlet is incoherent in itself. Or rather, it is saved from incoherence only by the assumption that α stops at 0. Installing a desired conclusion as the only escape route from what would otherwise be a contradiction is a time-honored method of proof. (The usual example is "either this statement is false or God exists.") The new Zeno paradox might be seen as fitting the pattern as well: either α stops at 0 or something impossible happens: the demons act in accordance with (R). But even this gives the paradox too much credit, since there is another way out. All we we can conclude on the basis of the given conditions is that either α stops at 0, or the demons act in accordance with (R) if they act in accordance with (R 0 ). Either α stops at 0, or it continues past 0 and the demons are forced to face up to their inability to carry through on their promises. 6

The general point is that α s continuing past 0 puts the security system to a test that it cannot possibly pass. Let it be that the demons mine the x>0 region so that a bridge comes down automatically iff α advances too far. If α advances too far, the mines will not work as advertised not because they are defective but because logic doesn t allow it. If there s a paradox here, it lies in the difficulty of combining individually operational subsystems into an operational system. But is this any more puzzlikng than the fact that although I can pick a number larger than whatever number you pick, and vice versa, we can t be combined into a system producing two numbers each larger than the other? Stephen Yablo Department of Linguistics and Philosophy, MIT 77 Massachussetts Ave Cambridge, MA 02139 USA yablo@mit.edu REFERENCES Bernardete, J. 1964. Infinity: an essay in metaphysics. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Priest, G. 1999. On a version of one of Zeno's paradoxes. Analysis 59: 1-2 Yablo, S. 1993. Paradox without self-reference. Analysis 53: 251-2 7