Review of Science and Ethics. Bernard Rollin Cambridge University Press pp., paper

Similar documents
Lecture 9. A summary of scientific methods Realism and Anti-realism

The Critical Mind is A Questioning Mind

Lecture 8. Ethics in Science

NORTH SOUTH UNIVERSITY DEPARTMENT OF HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY DHAKA, BANGLADESH

THE GREATEST SCANDAL NEVER EXPOSED

VIEWING PERSPECTIVES

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

Philosophical Ethics. The nature of ethical analysis. Discussion based on Johnson, Computer Ethics, Chapter 2.

Ethics is subjective.

Philosophical Ethics. Distinctions and Categories

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers

WHY SHOULD ANYONE BELIEVE ANYTHING AT ALL?

IDHEF Chapter 2 Why Should Anyone Believe Anything At All?

Spring CAS Department of Philosophy Graduate Courses

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles.

Annotated List of Ethical Theories

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

Chapter 2 Ethical Concepts and Ethical Theories: Establishing and Justifying a Moral System

Ethics Handout 19 Bernard Williams, The Idea of Equality. A normative conclusion: Therefore we should treat men as equals.

Atheism: A Christian Response

Kant On The A Priority of Space: A Critique Arjun Sawhney - The University of Toronto pp. 4-7

Epistemic Responsibility in Science

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Syllabus Fall 2014 PHIL 2010: Introduction to Philosophy 11:30-12:45 TR, Allgood Hall 257

PH 101: Problems of Philosophy. Section 005, Monday & Thursday 11:00 a.m. - 12:20 p.m. Course Description:

Hoong Juan Ru. St Joseph s Institution International. Candidate Number Date: April 25, Theory of Knowledge Essay

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING

Philosophy of Ethics Philosophy of Aesthetics. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Environmental Ethics. Espen Gamlund, PhD Associate Professor of Philosophy University of Bergen

Knowledge, Reality, and Values CORC 1210 SYLLABUS

WhaT does it mean To Be an animal? about 600 million years ago, CerTain

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

Christ-Centered Critical Thinking. Lesson 6: Evaluating Thinking

Philosophy Courses-1

Korsgaard and Non-Sentient Life ABSTRACT

Philosophy Courses-1

To link to this article:

Epistemic Normativity for Naturalists

Psychological and Ethical Egoism

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

When does human life begin? by Dr Brigid Vout

Chapter 2 Normative Theories of Ethics

appearance is often different from reality, and it s reality that counts.

Introduction to Technical Communications 21W.732 Section 2 Ethics in Science and Technology Formal Paper #2

Introduction to Animal Welfare Ethics Lecture Notes

Suppose a school were to set out deliberately to improve the mental

CHRISTIANITY vs HUMANISM

BIO 221 Invertebrate Zoology I Spring Course Information. Course Website. Lecture 1. Stephen M. Shuster Professor of Invertebrate Zoology

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

Florida State University Libraries

Instructor's Manual for Gregg Barak s Integrating Criminologies. Prepared by Paul Leighton (Boston: Allyn & Bacon, 1997) * CHAPTER 4

Objectivism and Education: A Response to David Elkind s The Problem with Constructivism

Philosophy Courses Fall 2016

Naturalism and is Opponents

A Framework for Thinking Ethically

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2009

Falsification or Confirmation: From Logic to Psychology

Lesson 2 The Existence of God Cause & Effect Apologetics Press Introductory Christian Evidences Correspondence Course

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary

COURSE OUTLINE. Philosophy 116 (C-ID Number: PHIL 120) Ethics for Modern Life (Title: Introduction to Ethics)

Your RE: matching chart for the Curriculum for Excellence. Arranged by Curriculum for Excellence statement.

Framingham State University Syllabus PHIL 101-B Invitation to Philosophy Summer 2018

STUDY GUIDE ARE HUMANS MORE VALUABLE THAN ANIMALS? KEY TERMS:

UNIT 1: THE ETHICAL DIGNITY OF THE PERSON

[name] [course] [teaching assistant s name] [discussion day and time] [question being answered] [date turned in] Cultural Relativism

KS4 Curriculum. Religious Education (Short Course) Unit 1

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

Department of Philosophy

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

The Advancement: A Book Review

Climate change and you: consequences, intentions and consistency. Climate change is a many-sided problem. It s a scientific problem, because what

Sociology 475 Classical Sociological Theory. Office: 8103 Social Science Bldng

Louisiana Law Review. Cheney C. Joseph Jr. Louisiana State University Law Center. Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue Repository Citation

Subject Overview Curriculum pathway

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

Consciousness might be defined as the perceiver of mental phenomena. We might say that there are no differences between one perceiver and another, as

Religion and the Roots of Climate Change Denial: A Catholic Perspective Stephen Pope

THE GOD OF QUARKS & CROSS. bridging the cultural divide between people of faith and people of science

5: Preliminaries to the Argument

PHIL University of New Orleans. Clarence Mark Phillips University of New Orleans. University of New Orleans Syllabi.

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true.

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

Political Science 206 Modern Political Philosophy Spring Semester 2011 Clark University

Course Coordinator Dr Melvin Chen Course Code. CY0002 Course Title. Ethics Pre-requisites. NIL No of AUs 3 Contact Hours

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

A Philosophical Critique of Cognitive Psychology s Definition of the Person

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

The Experience Machine and Mental State Theories of Wellbeing

We aim to cover in some detail a number of issues currently debated in the philosophy of natural and social science.

16 Free Will Requires Determinism

A primer of major ethical theories

CRITIQUE OF PETER SINGER S NOTION OF MARGINAL UTILITY

Phil/Ling 375: Meaning and Mind [Handout #10]

Mill s Utilitarian Theory

PHILOSOPHY. Minor in Philosophy. Philosophy, B.A. Ethical theory: One course required. History: Two courses required.

Subject Overview Curriculum pathway

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

Philosophical Ethics. Consequentialism Deontology (Virtue Ethics)

Reviewed Work: Why We Argue (and How We Should): A Guide to Political Disagreement, by Scott Aikin and Robert Talisse

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Transcription:

92 Between the Species Review of Science and Ethics Bernard Rollin Cambridge University Press 2006 306 pp., paper Walters State Community College greg.bock@ws.edu Volume 18, Issue 1 Aug 2015

93 Bernard Rollin is one of the leading voices in the animal rights movement, and while Science and Ethics deals with science more broadly, arguments for the ethical treatment of animals are prominent throughout the book. Of particular interest are the chapters on biotechnology and ethics in which he explores issues ranging from animal cloning to the genetic engineering of Lesch-Nyhan syndrome in mice. Science and Ethics is an introductory book that would be useful in any science or philosophy course, and it has engaging examples and stories that make it accessible even to lower division undergraduates. For example, Rollin describes the shocking practices once prevalent in veterinary schools like bleeding out dogs and abdominal surgery on cats without anesthesia. When discussing research on humans, he uses several famous cases including the Nazi hypothermia experiments and the Tuskegee syphilis study. Rollin attacks so-called scientific ideology, or blind faith in science. As he explains, an ideology is something that hinders critical thinking. He says, When we refer to a set of beliefs as an ideology, we usually mean that, for the person or group entertaining those beliefs, nothing counts as a good reason for revising those beliefs, and, correlatively, raising questions critical of those beliefs is excluded dogmatically by the belief system (11). Scientific ideology is, in part, the belief that scientific practices are not subject to ethical evaluation. This is the view that science is value-free, which Rollin fights hard against: If science is independent of ethics, why not cheat, falsify data, plagiarize, run trials until they come out as you wish them to, fudge, and so on? (272). Rollin explains that scientific ideology can be traced back to twentieth century logical positivism, which states that only empirically verifiable statements have

94 meaning. Since ethical statements cannot be tested, ethics is not meaningful on this view, and statements about right and wrong are reduced to statements about the psychological state of the individual uttering them. Rollin explains how many scientists are blinded by this ideology. They may have never consciously committed to it, but they have imbibed it through the culture. He says, If one s peer group says uniformly that animal use in research is not a moral issue but a scientific necessity, and one must accept this to receive the requisite education, such a belief becomes incorporated into the cognitive categories one uses to interpret the world (54). He gives an example of a psychology graduate school requiring its students to break the necks of rats after lab experiments. Objections would be met with the disapproving comment that the student did not have what it takes to be a psychologist. In another example, he describes how at one time most medical schools required students to kill a dog in a lab for the sole reason, apparently, of teaching students to be less compassionate (19). Scientific ideology conflicts with what Rollin calls social consensus ethics, which is a set of agreed upon rules that govern social behavior. In general, society leaves professions to conduct their own ethical discussions (professional ethics); however, when a profession fails to do so, society intervenes through legislation. As Rollin says, Professionals should be zealous in seeking out and listening to rational criticisms of their ethics. Failure to do so can put them at loggerheads with social ethics, resulting in loss of autonomy (43). He gives the example of when society learned that veterinarians were to blame for the increase of drug-resistant pathogens because of

95 the practice of supplying farmers with large amounts of antibiotics in an extralabel fashion. To some readers, it may not be clear what role social consensus ethics is playing in Rollin s project. Is it a normative theory or a statement of public opinion? Sometimes he seems to be justifying a moral claim; at other times, he seems to be simply reporting what many people believe. The answer, I think, is a bit of both. Perhaps this can be better understood by examining Rollin s distinction between Ethics 1 and Ethics 2. Ethics 1 is the set of moral beliefs an individual or a society holds. Ethics 2 is the critical examination of Ethics 1. Social consensus ethics belongs in the category of Ethics 1, and he says that Ethics 2 can be used to criticize Ethics 1 (44). He describes Martin Luther King, Jr. as one who balanced both: he preached Ethics 1 and used Ethics 2 to critique the principles that were used to support segregation (32). Rollin says, My purpose is clearly an attempt to get scientists to take Ethics 1 more seriously and to abandon the ideology we discussed that affirms that science is ethics-free (32). So, for Rollin, social consensus ethics is a kind of normative ethics that represents society s current thinking about morality. Consensus ethics is not necessarily a rival to other normative theories and theorists like Kant, utilitarianism, Plato, and the Golden Rule; rather it is a mixture of consequentialist/ utilitarian notions and Kantian/deontological notions (62). Social consensus ethics has been instrumental in forcing researchers to take seriously the subjective experience of pain. In the chapter Pain and Ethics, Rollin explains how scientific ideology kept many researchers from properly identifying and managing pain. For example, he tells how one particular veterinarian reinterpreted obvious signs of post-operative pain in an animal as the after-effects of anesthesia (216). In a particu-

96 larly disturbing section, he discusses the failure to adequately recognize and manage pain in human newborns. Even as late as the 1980s, surgeons were doing open heart surgery on babies without anesthesia, using only paralyzing muscle relaxants. There are many other notable cases and illustrations that make this book useful in the classroom, like bovine growth hormone usage in the dairy industry, embryonic stem cell research, whistleblowing, and cloning. Rollin does an excellent job with the issue of cloning, addressing the theological objections and arguing that the problem with cloning is not that it is inherently wrong, but that it may have serious negative consequences. Rollin ends his last chapter with this statement: The failure to teach young scientists to think and reflect about ethics is an intellectual and prudential sin, one punishable by loss of scientific credibility in society (274). Assigning Rollin s book to future scientists is an excellent way to remedy this problem. References Rollin, Bernard E. 2006. Science and Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.