Ethics is subjective.

Similar documents
Ethical non-naturalism

Chapter 2 Ethical Concepts and Ethical Theories: Establishing and Justifying a Moral System

Annotated List of Ethical Theories

Philosophical Ethics. Distinctions and Categories

Henrik Ahlenius Department of Philosophy ETHICS & RESEARCH

Naturalist Cognitivism: The Open Question Argument; Subjectivism

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles.

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Review of Nathan M. Nobis s Truth in Ethics and Epistemology

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

Psychological Aspects of Social Issues

Philosophical Ethics. The nature of ethical analysis. Discussion based on Johnson, Computer Ethics, Chapter 2.

David Copp, ed., The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory, Oxford: Oxford University

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning

Theme 1: Ethical Thought, AS. divine command as an objective metaphysical foundation for morality.

Kantian Deontology. A2 Ethics Revision Notes Page 1 of 7. Paul Nicholls 13P Religious Studies

Hugh LaFollette: The Practice of Ethics

Chapter 2 Normative Theories of Ethics

The form of relativism that says that whether an agent s actions are right or wrong depends on the moral principles accepted in her own society.

Phil 108, July 15, 2010

Value Theory. Contemporary approaches to metaethics

-- did you get a message welcoming you to the cours reflector? If not, please correct what s needed.

Reactions & Debate. Non-Convergent Truth

Hume s emotivism. Michael Lacewing

Suppose... Kant. The Good Will. Kant Three Propositions

Practical Rationality and Ethics. Basic Terms and Positions

Lecture 2: What Ethics is Not. Jim Pryor Guidelines on Reading Philosophy Peter Singer What Ethics is Not

Ethical Theory. Ethical Theory. Consequentialism in practice. How do we get the numbers? Must Choose Best Possible Act

Being Realistic about Reasons

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

24.02 Moral Problems and the Good Life

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Huemer s Clarkeanism

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers

Scanlon on Double Effect

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics

PROSPECTS FOR A JAMESIAN EXPRESSIVISM 1 JEFF KASSER

The Trolley Problem. 1. The Trolley Problem: Consider the following pair of cases:

Introduction to Moral Reasoning


The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

(naturalistic fallacy)

Philosophy Courses-1

What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Lecture 12 Deontology. Onora O Neill A Simplified Account of Kant s Ethics

Contents. Detailed Chapter Contents Preface to the First Edition (2003) Preface to the Second Edition (2013) xiii

Phil 114, April 24, 2007 until the end of semester Mill: Individual Liberty Against the Tyranny of the Majority

Intro to Philosophy. Review for Exam 2

Moral Theory. What makes things right or wrong?

Evolution and the Possibility of Moral Realism

SAMPLE COURSE OUTLINE PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS GENERAL YEAR 11

Carritt, E. F. Anthony Skelton

10 R E S P O N S E S 1

Ethical Relativism 1. Ethical Relativism: Ethical Relativism: subjective objective ethical nihilism Ice cream is good subjective

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

SEMINAR IN ETHICS: ETHICS AND EVOLUTION PHIL 848J

Philosophy Courses-1

In this paper I offer an account of Christine Korsgaard s metaethical

How many people will be studied? We expect about 200 people will be in this research study internationally.

Ethical Theories. A (Very) Brief Introduction

Metaethics: An Introduction

From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005)

CHRISTIANITY AND THE NATURE OF SCIENCE J.P. MORELAND

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism

Ethical universal: An ethical truth that is true at all times and places.

Φ The Department of Philosophy

A-LEVEL PHILOSOPHY 7172/1

Quiz 1. Criticisms of consequentialism and Kant. Consequentialism and Nonconsequentialism. Consequentialism in practice. Must Choose Best Possible Act

During the Second World War as V1 rockets rained down on London, Churchill made a fateful decision. He would protect the city center and its vital

MORAL INTUITIONS, RELIABILITY AND DISAGREEMENT

PHIL 202: IV:

Consequentialism, Incoherence and Choice. Rejoinder to a Rejoinder.

24.01: Classics of Western Philosophy

Epistemic Normativity for Naturalists

Foundations of Bioethics

MORAL INTUITIONS, MORAL PERCEPTIONS, AND MORAL DILEMMAS. David Killoren

A Rational Solution to the Problem of Moral Error Theory? Benjamin Scott Harrison

New Chapter: Ethics and Morality

Kant, Deontology, & Respect for Persons

Aims of Rawls s theory

METAETHICAL MORAL RELATIVISM AND THE ANALOGY WITH PHYSICS

Are Humans Always Selfish? OR Is Altruism Possible?

PHIL%13:%Ethics;%Fall%2012% David%O.%Brink;%UCSD% Syllabus% Part%I:%Challenges%to%Moral%Theory 1.%Relativism%and%Tolerance.

PHD THESIS SUMMARY: Rational choice theory: its merits and limits in explaining and predicting cultural behaviour

HOW TO BE (AND HOW NOT TO BE) A NORMATIVE REALIST:

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

A Contractualist Reply

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

Hoong Juan Ru. St Joseph s Institution International. Candidate Number Date: April 25, Theory of Knowledge Essay

UTILITARIANISM AND CONSEQUENTIALISM: THE BASICS

On Audi s Marriage of Ross and Kant. Thomas Hurka. University of Toronto

Epistemic Risk and Relativism

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers

Transcription:

Introduction Scientific Method and Research Ethics Ethical Theory Greg Bognar Stockholm University September 22, 2017 Ethics is subjective. If ethics is subjective, then moral claims are subjective in some sense. Australia is the smallest continent. Our greenhouse gas emissions are causing climate change. There is no largest prime number. Abortion is killing. Abortion is morally permissible. You ought to keep your promises. Are these claims true or false? What makes them true or false? Truth and falsity depend on facts: facts about continents, greenhouse gases, numbers, abortion, etc. What about moral claims? Are there moral facts that can make them true or false? Four central questions about moral facts (i) Do moral facts exist? Just as there are facts about continents or greenhouse gases, are there facts about the rightness and wrongness of actions? In other fields, we use observation (sciences), proofs (mathematics), perception and reasoning (everyday life). What can we use to learn about moral facts? (iii) How can we account for moral disagreement? People seem to disagree about many moral judgments, and agree on many others. It seems possible to be mistaken in moral beliefs. (iv) How can moral beliefs motivate? Moral beliefs necessarily motivate: there is an internal connection between moral belief and motivation which is lacking in the connection of ordinary belief and motivation. How to explain this? Noncognitivism When you pronounce any action or character to be vicious, you mean nothing, but that from the constitution of your nature you have a feeling or sentiment of blame from the contemplation of it. (Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, III.i.1) Noncognitivism is the view that moral judgments are neither true nor false they are not truth-apt. One example: Expressivism as an account of moral language. One function of language is to make (true or false) statements. Another is to express emotions and attitudes. Expressivism holds that moral judgments are expressions of approval and disapproval. If you say X is wrong, it means you have a negative attitude towards doing X. Thus, the function of moral language is to express attitudes and to influence behavior.

Noncognitivism Error theory (i) Do moral facts exist? No, there are no moral facts. There are no moral facts to be known, only attitudes. (iii) Are moral disagreements genuine disagreements? No, they are merely the expressions of different attitudes. (iv) How can moral beliefs motivate? There is a connection between moral beliefs and motivation, since to make a moral judgment is to express a certain attitude, and an attitude is a disposition to act. problem: moral reasons. Moral judgments aim to influence behavior; they are supported by moral reasons. Can attitudes be correct? Can they be supported by reasons? Error theory. Our moral practice involves a systematic error: there are no moral facts that make moral judgments true. All moral judgments are false, because there are no corresponding facts in the world that could be their truthmakers. (i) Do moral facts exist? No, there are no moral facts. There are no moral facts to be known. (iii) Are moral disagreements genuine disagreements? No, since all moral beliefs are false, there are no genuine moral disagreements. (iv) How can moral beliefs motivate? The connection between (false) moral beliefs and motivation still needs to be explained. Relativism Naturalism and anti-naturalism Noncognitivist relativism. Moral evaluation is not subject to truth or falsity, but it depends on (relative to) something else; e.g., the speaker s own attitudes. problem: this is just noncognitivism. Trivial relativism. The view that (i) there are no universal moral requirements, but (ii) everyone should follow the moral requirements of his or her society or group. Normative relativism. The view that no-one should ever pass judgment on other people s moral codes or practices. The argument from tolerance. It is always unacceptable to interfere with other people s pursuit of their values. problem: all these views are self-defeating: they formulate a universal moral requirement. Relativism is a realist view. Naturalism. The view that moral judgments can be analyzed in terms of, or reduced to, factual statements. Reduction is not the same as elimination. If moral facts can be identified with nonmoral facts, it does not follow that they don t exist. E.g., a table is only a collection of atoms, but it still exists. Anti-naturalism. Realist ethical views that deny that ethics must be fitted into the scientific worldview. They hold that moral facts cannot be analyzed in terms of nonmoral facts: the normative realm is independent of science. Science is relevant only insofar as it settles the relevant facts (i.e., the relevant circumstances). Supernaturalism: moral facts are supernatural facts; Rationalism: moral facts are a priori.

Relativism and absolutism Moral absolutism. The view that there is a single moral code that everyone has reason to follow. There are universal moral demands and they are the source of all moral reasons; these demands apply to all moral agents. Note that on this view, a belief in absolute values is a belief that those values provide everyone with reasons. Note that these reasons may be overridden but they still apply to all. Moral relativism. The view that denies that there is a single moral code that applies to everyone universally. Moral truth and justification are relative to factors which are culturally and historically contingent. Different agents are subject to different moral demands or requirements, given by the moral conventions in which they participate. Are there moral facts? Are there moral facts that make moral judgments true or false? All moral judgments are false Error theory Anti-realism Moral judgments are neither true nor false Noncognitivism Relativism Realism Naturalism Can science give an account of them? Absolutism Anti-naturalism Science and realism Can science give an account of moral facts? Naturalism Anti-naturalism Relativism Absolutism Rationalism Supernaturalism The branches of ethics Metaethics studies basic questions about moral judgments, e.g., Can moral judgments be true or false? If they can, what makes them true (or false)? How can we know about their truth (or falsity)? Normative ethics develops and evaluates moral theories, answering questions like Is the rightness of actions determined solely by the goodness of their consequences? Are there any absolute constraints on what we may do? What makes a person s life good? Applied ethics uses moral theories to answer practical questions, Is abortion wrong? Is reproductive cloning permissible? How should we respond to climate change?

Moral disagreement Defending your moral beliefs Relevant facts. Moral disagreements sometimes turn out to be factual disagreements. Disagreeing on euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide because of their likely consequences (e.g., slippery slopes ). Values. Arguments may appeal to different values. To resolve the disagreement, these values must be identified, defended by more basic principles, and weighed against one another. In balance, which provides the strongest reasons? Something may have instrumental value or final value. E.g., balancing the harms and benefits in legalized organ trading. Fundamental principles. There are disagreements about basic principles. The principles must be evaluated: accepted, rejected, or ruled irrelevant to the issue at hand. The sanctity of life vs the quality of life view; A woman s right to choose vs the prohibition on killing the innocent. Conceptual analysis. The concepts involved in your moral belief may be incoherent or inadequately defined. Cloning involves playing God. Consistency. If your belief is inconsistent with other moral beliefs that you have, you have to reject or modify one or more of them. If you believe abortion is wrong because taking human life is always wrong, you cannot consistently hold that taking human life is not wrong in war or as a punishment. Implications. If your belief has implications you are unwilling to accept, you have to reject or modify it. If you believe abortion is permissible because the fetus is not a person, it follows that infanticide is permissible since a newborn is not a person. Thought experiments. Imaginary cases allow you to isolate a particular feature of an issue ( everything else being equal ). They are used to clarify moral beliefs and to uncover hidden assumptions and implications. Moral knowledge Moral intuitions Error theory: since there are no moral facts, all moral beliefs and judgments are false. There is nothing to be known. Noncognitivism: since moral beliefs and judgments are just expressions of attitudes, there are no moral facts; there is no moral knowledge. Anti-naturalism: there are moral facts, but they are not natural facts; moral knowledge is not possible to attain through science. Supernaturalism: moral facts can be known through revelation. Naturalism: there are moral facts, and they are just like natural facts; moral knowledge is possible to attain through science. Relativism: there are no universal moral demands; truth in ethics is local. Absolutism: there are universal moral demands. How can naturalists give an account of moral knowledge? Non-naturalist intuitionism: there is a moral faculty to detect moral properties. Moral knowledge is non-inferential. G. E. Moore (1903): good is an indefinable, non-natural property that we have intuitive awareness of. problem: it is mysterious what this faculty of moral intuition is. Naturalist intuitionism: moral beliefs are non-inferential, but it is possible to study them through science (e.g., cognitive and evolutionary psychology, decision theory). Intuitive moral judgments can serve as starting points for ethical theory (just as data can play this role for scientific theories). Methodological intuitionism: non-inferential moral beliefs, while not infallible, can be used to justify particular moral theories (and be justified by them) they are part of reflective equilibrium.

Trolley cases Trolley cases Trolley Case 1 A trolley is running out of control down a track. In its path there are five people who do not see it coming. You can flip a switch, which will lead the trolley down a different track to safety. But there is a single person on that track. Should you flip the switch? Most people believe that you should flip the switch. As a consequence of your choice, one person dies and five people are saved from death. Trolley Case 2 A trolley is running out of control down a track. In its path there are five people who do not see it coming. You are on a bridge under which it will pass, and you can stop it by dropping a heavy weight in front of it. The only heavy weight is a very fat man next to you. The only way to stop the trolley is to push him over the bridge and onto the track, killing him to save five. Should you proceed? Most people believe that you should not push the fat man off the bridge. Consequentialism Nonconsequentialism Consequentialism. The ethical view that actions (policies, etc.) should be assessed solely by the goodness of their consequences. Utilitarianism. The right action is that which maximizes well-being (utility). Consequentialist theories are impartial: every person s good (well-being) counts the same. When you determine the goodness of the consequences, you should consider every person s good impartially: your good counts for no more than anyone else s good. Deontology. The view that denies that the rightness or wrongness of actions is determined solely by the goodness of their consequences. There are further moral factors that determine the rightness or the wrongness of an act. These factors generate moral constraints. Avoiding harm. A prohibition on performing certain types of acts even if they would lead to the best consequences if they involve causing harm to others. Rights. Persons are the bearers of rights which protects their central interests and determines what is morally owed to them (claims and entitlements). Treating others merely as means. You ought not to use others as efficacious tools to some goal that do not serve their interests, at least not without their consent.

Trolley cases Trolley cases In both cases, one person dies and five people are saved from death as a consequence of your choice. How can saving the five be the right course of action in Case 1, but the wrong course of action in Case 2? Consequentialism. The right course of action is that which has the best consequences. Since the consequences are the same, you ought to save the five in both Case 1 and 2. Nonconsequentialism. The goodness of consequences is not the only relevant factor: there are further moral constraints. Injunction against treating as mere means In Case 1, you don t treat the one person as a mere means of saving others. In Case 2, you treat the fat man as a mere means of saving others. (You would not treat him as a mere means if you had his consent). Trolley Case 3 A trolley is running out of control down a track. In its path there are five people who do not see it coming. You can flip a switch to divert the trolley through a loop before it reaches these people. There is a fat man on that track whose weight would stop the trolley, but the man would die. Should you flip the switch? In this version, you would use the person as a mere means to save the five, but most people agree that you should flip the switch. Trolley cases and fmri studies Naturalism and moral knowledge The different moral intuitions cannot be explained by the idea that in Case 2 the fat man is used as a mere means, but in Case 1 the one person is not used as a mere means. But we do have a robust negative emotional response to directly killing someone which explains the intuition in Case 2, and we don t have the same emotional response in Case 1. fmri scans of Trolley cases In Case 2, areas of the brain associated with emotional responses show increased activity; In Case 1, areas of the brain associated with cognitive activity show increased activity; Those who consider pushing the fat man off the bridge permissible in Case 2 take longer to respond than those who consider it impermissible. There might be an evolutionary explanation for the difference in moral judgments: direct harming and killing evokes strong and immediate emotional reactions because this is the sort of situation that would have arisen in our evolutionary past. Our intuition in Case 2 might be based on an evolutionary determined reaction. In Case 1, we have no similar reaction. What should we conclude from these studies? Consequentialists might argue that ethical theory should be based on rational reactions. We should reject our moral intuition in Case 2. Nonconsequentialists might argue that moral intuitions have normative significance. Ethical theory should give an account of the difference between Case 1 and 2. Both arguments begin from methodological intuitionism.