Five Arguments for God - by Peter S. Williams

Similar documents
Copan, P. and P. Moser, eds., The Rationality of Theism, London: Routledge, 2003, pp.xi+292

Simplicity and Why the Universe Exists

The Principle of Sufficient Reason and Free Will

The Grounding for Moral Obligation

3) Christian theism has significantly more explanatory power and scope than Specified naturalism.

Philosophy of Religion. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Cosmological Argument

The Cosmological Argument

God, the Church, and Society: Turning Back the Tide of Atheism with The God Question

-1 Peter 3:15-16 (NSRV)

5 A Modal Version of the

Chance, Chaos and the Principle of Sufficient Reason

THEISM AND BELIEF. Etymological note: deus = God in Latin; theos = God in Greek.

What God Could Have Made

Today s Lecture. Preliminary comments on the Problem of Evil J.L Mackie

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Getting To God. The Basic Evidence For The Truth of Christian Theism. truehorizon.org

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

The cosmological argument (continued)

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

On A New Cosmological Argument

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

A Rational Solution to the Problem of Moral Error Theory? Benjamin Scott Harrison

The Grand Design and the Kalam Cosmological Argument. The Book

The Kalam Cosmological Argument provides no support for theism

FALSE DICHOTOMY FAITH VS. SCIENCE TRUTH

Many cite internet videos, forums, blogs, etc. as a major reason*

The Metaphysics of Perfect Beings, by Michael Almeida. New York: Routledge, Pp $105.00

Baha i Proofs for the Existence of God

God Is Not Dead Yet. How current philosophers argue for his existence. William Lane Craig posted 7/03/ :50AM

On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology. In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with

Logic and Theism: Arguments For and Against Beliefs in God, by John Howard Sobel.

The Cosmological Argument

First Principles. Principles of Reality. Undeniability.

Nagel, Naturalism and Theism. Todd Moody. (Saint Joseph s University, Philadelphia)

Causation and Free Will

On Finitism and the Beginning of the Universe: A Reply to Stephen Puryear. Citation Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 2016, v. 94 n. 3, p.

1/6. The Resolution of the Antinomies

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

Does God Exist? Understanding arguments for the existence of God. HZT4U1 February

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

The Christian God Part I: Metaphysics

No Dilemma for the Proponent of the Transcendental Argument: A Response to David Reiter

There is a God. A Much-Maligned Convert

THE GOD OF QUARKS & CROSS. bridging the cultural divide between people of faith and people of science

Avicenna, Proof of the Necessary of Existence

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

A Fine Tuned Universe The Improbability That God is Improbable

A level Religious Studies at Titus Salt

PAST, PROBABILITY, AND TELEOLOGY J.W. Wartick 228

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Ultimate Naturalistic Causal Explanations

NEIL MANSON (ED.), God and Design: The Teleological Argument and Modern Science London: Routledge, 2003, xvi+376pp.

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 2. Background Material for the Exercise on Inference Indicators

Epistemological Foundations for Koons Cosmological Argument?

Understanding the burning question of the 1940s and beyond

Wk 10Y5 Existence of God 2 - October 26, 2018

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

The Nature of Humanness Module: Philosophy Lesson 13 Some Recommended Sources The Coherence of Theism in Philosophical Foundations for a Christian

Charles Hartshorne argues that Kant s criticisms of Anselm s ontological

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

Aquinas' Third Way Modalized

Is God the Necessary Being?

Summer Preparation Work

Welcome back to week 2 of this edition of 5pm Church Together.

1/5. The Critique of Theology

Table of x III. Modern Modal Ontological Arguments Norman Malcolm s argument Charles Hartshorne s argument A fly in the ointment? 86

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Evolution and Meaning. Richard Oxenberg. Suppose an infinite number of monkeys were to pound on an infinite number of

The Rationality of Religious Beliefs

A CRITIQUE OF THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. A Paper. Presented to. Dr. Douglas Blount. Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary. In Partial Fulfillment

Philosophy of Religion (PHIL11159)

Explaining causal loops

Moral Argument. Theistic Arguments: The Craig Program, 4. Edwin Chong. God makes sense of the objective moral values in the world.

We [now turn to the question] of the existence of God. By God I shall understand a

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

BENEDIKT PAUL GÖCKE. Ruhr-Universität Bochum

Preliminary Apologetics Syllabus Dr. Timothy McGrew, July 2012

A Bayesian formulation of the kalam cosmological argument

Theistic Arguments: The Craig Program

2014 Religious, Moral and Philosophical Studies. Advanced Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

Does God Exist? By: Washington Massaquoi. January 2, Introduction

Puzzles for Divine Omnipotence & Divine Freedom

The Argument for the Existence of God: A Philosophical and Theoretical Discussion

Christian Apologetics The Classical Arguments

Critique of Cosmological Argument

Aquinas s Third Way Keith Burgess-Jackson 24 September 2017

Can science prove the existence of a creator?

Review of Erik J. Wielenberg: Robust Ethics: The Metaphysics and Epistemology of Godless Normative Realism

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

CHRISTIANITY AND THE NATURE OF SCIENCE J.P. MORELAND

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Naturalist Cognitivism: The Open Question Argument; Subjectivism

GOD EXISTS: A DEBATE ABOUT THEISM. Two Statements: Atheist and Theist (1) Consistent Theism is Socially Undesirable. Paul Cliteur 1 (2)

J. L. Mackie The Subjectivity of Values

Introduction to Apologetics-Part VI

Science, Religion & the Existence of God Seidel Abel Boanerges

Science and religion: Is it either/or or both/and? Dr. Neil Shenvi Morganton, NC March 4, 2017

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Transcription:

Five Arguments for God - by Peter S. Williams 1) A Kalam Cosmological Argument At a recent conference honouring physicist Stephen Hawking s 70th birthday, atheist cosmologist Alexander Vilenkin affirmed that All the evidence we have says that the universe had a beginning. 1 A New Scientist editorial on the conference commented: The big bang is now part of the furniture of modern cosmology... Many physicists have been fighting a rearguard action against it for decades, largely because of its theological overtones. If you have an instant of creation, don t you need a creator? Cosmologists... have tried on several different models of the universe that dodge the need for a beginning while still requiring a big bang. But recent research has shot them full of holes. It now seems certain that the universe did have a beginning. Without an escape clause, physicists and philosophers must finally answer a problem that has been nagging at them for the best part of 50 years: how do you get a universe, complete with the laws of physics, out of nothing.2 Physicist Paul Davies observes that: One might consider some supernatural force as being responsible for the big bang, or one might prefer to regard the big bang as an event without a cause. It seems to me that we don t have too much choice. Either... something outside of the physical world [or] an event without a cause.3 However, a physical event is by nature a contingent event, and a contingent event is by definition contingent upon something beyond itself. Quantum mechanics doesn t provide a counter example to this causal claim, even if we grant the controversial Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics, for quantum events are set against a background of physical conditions that causally condition, even if they don t causally necessitate, the events in question. As atheist Quentin Smith admits, quantum considerations at most tend to show that acausal laws govern the change of condition of particles... They state nothing about the causality or acausality of absolute beginnings... 1 One obviously can t posit a physical cause for the first physical event, but to deny that the first physical event had a non-physical cause one must either reject the premise that All physical events have at least one cause, or else claim that physical events must have physical causes. However, on the one hand, to make an exception to the rule that all physical events have at least one cause when it comes to the first physical event is ad hoc. On the other hand, the claim that physical events must have physical causes entails an unacceptable infinite regress. It also begs the question in favour of naturalism. Hence we should recognize the existence of a first physical event explained by a non-physical cause: 1 Quentin Smith, The Uncaused Beginning of the Universe, Philosophy of Science 55 (1988): p. 50. 1

1) There was a first physical event 2) All physical events have at least one cause outside and independent of themselves 3) Therefore, the first physical event had at least one cause outside and independent of itself 4) The cause of the first physical event cannot have been a physical cause 5) Therefore, since causes can only be either physical or non-physical, the first physical event had a non-physical cause outside and independent of itself As Dallas Willard argues: the dependent character of all physical states, together with the completeness of the series of dependencies underlying the existence of any given physical state, logically implies at least one self-existent, and therefore nonphysical, state of being.4 Moreover, as J.P. Moreland and William Lane Craig observe: there are two types of causal explanation... explanations in terms of laws and initial conditions and personal explanations in terms of agents and their volitions. A first state of the universe cannot have [an explanation in terms of laws and initial conditions] since there [are no laws or initial conditions] before it, and therefore it can be accounted for only in terms of personal explanation.5 And this, of course, is an important part of what we mean by God. 2) A Leibnizian Cosmological Argument The Leibnitzian cosmological argument builds upon the principle of sufficient reason : 1) Everything that exists has an explanation of its existence, either in the necessity of its own nature or in an external cause 2) The universe exists 3) Therefore the universe has an explanation of its existence 4) If the universe has an explanation of its existence, that explanation is God 5) Therefore, the explanation of the universe s existence is God Since the universe obviously exists, non-theists must deny premises 1 or 4 to rationally avoid God s existence. Many philosophers think Premise 1 the principle of sufficient reason - is selfevident: Imagine finding a translucent ball on the forest floor whilst hiking. You d naturally wonder how it came to be there. If a fellow hiker said, It just exists inexplicably. Don t worry about it! you d wouldn t take him seriously. Suppose we increase the size of the ball so it s as big the planet. That doesn t remove the need for explanation. Suppose it were the size of the universe. Same problem. 2

Premise 4 If the universe has an explanation of its existence, that explanation is God - is synonymous with the standard atheistic claim that if God doesn t exist, then the universe has no explanation of its existence. The only other alternative to theism is to claim the universe has an explanation in the necessity of its own nature. But this is a very radical step and I can t think of any contemporary atheist who takes it. After all, it s coherent to imagine a universe made from a wholly different collection of quarks than the collection that actually exists; but such a universe would be a different universe, so universes clearly don t exist necessarily. Suppose I ask you to loan me a certain book, but you say: I don t have a copy right now, but I ll ask my friend to lend me his copy and then I ll lend it to you. Suppose your friend says the same thing to you, and so on. Two things are clear. First, if the process of asking to borrow the book goes on ad infinitum, I ll never get the book. Second, if I get the book, the process that led to me getting it can t have gone on ad infinitum. Somewhere down the line of requests to borrow the book, someone had the book without having to borrow it. Likewise, argues Richard Purtill, consider any contingent reality: the same two principles apply. If the process of everything getting its existence from something else went on to infinity, then the thing in question would never [have] existence. And if the thing has... existence then the process hasn t gone on to infinity. There was something that had existence without having to receive it from something else 6 A necessary being explaining all physical reality can t itself be a physical reality. The only remaining possibilities are an abstract object or an immaterial mind. But abstract objects are causally impotent. Therefore, the explanation of the physical universe is a necessarily existent, transcendent mind. 3) The Fine-Tuning Design Argument In The Grand Design Stephen Hawking acknowledges that: the initial state of the universe had to be set up in a very special and highly improbable way if the universe were only slightly different, beings like us could not exist. What are we to make of this fine-tuning? Is it evidence that the universe, after all, was designed..?7 Well, if it looks like a dog, that s a good reason to think that it is a dog. Moreover, the combination of a highly improbable event with a very special pattern, seen in cosmic fine-tuning, is an example of specified complexity best explained by intelligent design. That is: 1) If something exhibits specified complexity then it s probably the product of design 2) The fine tuning of the universe exhibits specified complexity 3) Therefore, the fine tuning of the universe is probably the product of design A long string of random letters is complex (unlikely) but it isn t specified (it doesn t conform to any independently given pattern). A short string of letters could be 3

specified - like this but wouldn t be sufficiently complex to outstrip the ability of chance to explain the match. Neither complexity without specificity, nor specificity without complexity compels us to infer design. However, if you saw a play by Shakespeare written out in scrabble tiles, you d infer design. A play is both specified and sufficiently complex to merit a design inference on the grounds that in all cases where we know the causal origin of specified complexity, experience has shown that intelligent design played a causal role. 8 Likewise with cosmic fine-tuning. Given enough time, typewriters, and monkeys one might get the works of Shakespeare by chance; so why does no one explain Shakespeare s works using the many monkeys hypothesis? In the absence of independent evidence for the existence of enough time, typewriters and monkeys, the design explanation is clearly preferable. Likewise, even granting that if there were multiple universes then one could obtain the fine-tuning of our universe by chance, in the absence of independent evidence for the existence of multiple universes the design explanation is clearly preferable. In point of fact, the multi-verse hypothesis is empirically disconfirmed by the observation of fine tuning on a universal scale rather than on the much more probable local scale. Besides, as Robin Collins observes: even if [a] many-universe generator exists, it along with the background laws and principles could be said to be [a fine tuned] system with just the right combination of laws and fields for the production of life-permitting universes the existence of such a system suggests design.9 4) A Moral Argument 1) If any objective moral value exists, then god exists 2) At least one objective moral value exists 3) Therefore, god exists It s important not to confuse this argument with the false claim that we must believe in God in order to know or to do the right thing. What does it mean to say that moral values are objective? Suppose one person thinks the sun goes around the earth, and another thinks the opposite. In this case, we know the earth goes around the sun. Those who believe otherwise, however sincerely, are wrong. Moreover, coming to know that the earth goes around the sun is a matter of discovering truth, not inventing it. Moral objectivism says that ethics is about discovering moral truths, truths that exist even if we fail to discern them. According to moral objectivism there are genuine moral disagreements; and the observation that people sometimes hold different moral opinions just shows that our moral beliefs can be either correct or incorrect according to the moral facts of the matter. To tackle our second premise first, are there any objective moral facts? Those who point to the reality of evil as the basis for an argument against God certainly think so; for nothing can be objectively evil if there are no objective values. 4

John Cottingham reports that the increasing consensus among philosophers today is that some kind of objectivism of value is correct... 10 For example, atheist Peter Cave defends moral objectivism by appealing to his intuitions: whatever sceptical arguments may be brought against our belief that killing the innocent is morally wrong, we are more certain that the killing is morally wrong than that the argument is sound... Torturing an innocent child for the sheer fun of it is morally wrong. 11 The properly basic intuition that torturing innocent children for fun is wrong isn t undermined by the existence of the psychopath who enjoys torturing children. By the principle of credulity, torturing an innocent child for fun clearly isn t merely something that stops the child functioning normally (an empirical observation), or merely something we dislike because of our evolutionary history, or merely something our society has decided to discourage. Rather, torturing an innocent child for fun is objectively wrong. So at least one thing is objectively wrong. Therefore, moral subjectivism is false. Some moral intuitions are specific (e.g. It s evil to torture small children for fun) and some are general (e.g. it s always right to choose the lesser of two evils). Of course, our moral intuitions can be mistaken, but this very admission of fallibility presupposes moral objectivism; for if moral subjectivism were true, no moral claims could be mistaken! As atheist Russ Shafer-Landau argues: subjectivism s picture of ethics as a wholly conventional enterprise entails a kind of moral infallibility for individuals or societies... This sort of infallibility is hard to swallow. 12 Finally, if moral objectivism were false it couldn t be true that we objectively ought to consider arguments against objectivism, or that we ought to consider them fairly, so the second premise of the moral argument seems secure! Turning to the first premise, many atheists acknowledge that if god doesn t exist, then objective moral values don t exist. For example, Jean-Paul Sartre wrote that it is: extremely embarrassing that God does not exist, for there disappears with Him all possibility of finding values in an intelligible heaven. There can no longer be any good a priori, since there is no infinite and perfect consciousness to think it.13 An objective moral value is a transcendent ideal that prescribes and obligates behaviour; but an ideal implies a mind, a prescription requires a prescriber and an obligation is contingent upon a person. As H.P. Owen argues: On the one hand [objective moral] claims transcend every human person... On the other hand it is contradictory to assert that impersonal claims are entitled to the allegiance of our wills. The only solution to this paradox is to suppose that the order of [objective moral] claims... is in fact rooted in the personality of God.14 5

5) An Ontological Argument As the greatest possible being God is by definition a necessary being. A necessary being is by definition a being that must exist if its existence is possible. Hence we can argue: 1) If it is possible that God exists, then God exists 2) It is possible that God exists 3) Therefore, God exists A great-making property is any property that a) endows its bearer with some measure of objective value and which b) admits of a logical maximum. A sock isn t more valuable than you because it s smellier than you; and however smelly a sock we imagine, it s always possible to imagine a smellier one. Smelliness isn t a greatmaking property. On the other hand, power is a great-making property, one that has a logical maximum in the quality of being omnipotent. Likewise, necessary being is the maximal instantiation of a great-making property. Even if Kant was right to argue that saying something exists doesn t add to our knowledge of its properties, to say that something exists necessarily certainly does add to our knowledge of its properties. Hence most philosophers agree that if God s existence is even possible, then, as a necessary being, He must exist. Unlike the tooth fairy God couldn t just happen not to exist despite His existence being possible. To deny the existence of the tooth fairy, one needn t claim that its existence is impossible. However, to deny the existence of God one must make the metaphysically stronger claim that His existence is impossible. But the claim that God exists clearly isn t on a par with the claim that there exists a round square! Many atheists acknowledge that the idea of God is coherent. Indeed, atheist Richard Carrier warns that arguments for thinking otherwise are: not valid, since any definition of god (or his properties) that is illogical can just be revised to be logical. So in effect, Arguments from Incoherence aren t really arguments for atheism, but for the reform of theology.15 Moreover, humans exhibit non-maximal degrees of great making properties (such as power, knowledge and goodness), and this supports the hypothesis that maximal degrees of great-making properties can co-exist over the hypothesis that they cannot. Finally, by confirming various aspects of the theistic hypothesis, the other theistic arguments provide independent grounds for thinking that the crucial second premise of the ontological argument is more plausible than its denial. The ontological argument thus ties together the thrust of our cumulative case for God. 6

Recommended Resources Web Sites Bethinking www.bethinking.org/ Last Seminary www.lastseminary.com/ Christian Philosophers Paul Copan www.paulcopan.com/ William Lane Craig www.reasonablefaith.org Video Craig, William Lane. Leibniz s Cosmological Argument www.reasonablefaith.org/site/news2?page=newsarticle&id=9174 - Can we be Good Without God? (SOAS, 2011) http://youtu.be/jzlenrjfdbc - The Ontological Argument http://youtu.be/dr36hid62wm Lennox, John. A Matter of Gravity: God, the Universe and Stephen Hawking http://youtu.be/222ihlzlujq Audio Kreeft, Peter. A Refutation of Moral Relativism www.peterkreeft.com/audio/05_relativism.htm Peter S. Williams Podcast Channel www.damaris.org/cm/podcasts/category/peterswilliams Papers Sadowsky, James A. Can there be an endless regress of causes? www.anthonyflood.com/sadowskyendlessregress.htm Williams, Peter S. A Universe From Someone: Against Lawrence Krauss' A Universe From Nothing: Why There is Something Rather than Nothing' www.bethinking.org/science-christianity/advanced/auniverse-from-someone-against-lawrence-krauss.htm - The Design Inference from Specified Complexity Defended by Scholars Outside the Intelligent Design Movement A Critical Review, Philosophia Christi, Volume 9, Number 2, 2007, p. 407-428 http://epsociety.org/library/articles.asp?pid=54 - Can Moral Objectivism Do Without God? www.bethinking.org/right-wrong/advanced/can-moralobjectivism-do-without-god.htm Books Beckwith, Francis J. et al (ed. s), To Everyone An Answer: A Case For The Christian Worldview (IVP, 2004) Copan, Paul & Paul K. Moser (ed. s), The Rationality of Theism (Routledge, 2003) Craig, William Lane, On Guard (David C. Cook, 2010) - (ed.), Philosophy Of Religion: A Reader and Guide (Edinburgh, 2002) Craig, William Lane & J.P. Moreland (ed. s), The Blackwell Companion To Natural Theology (WileyBlackwell, 2009) - Naturalism: A Critical Analysis (Routledge, 2001) Moreland, J.P. Scaling the Secular City (Baker, 1987) Nagasawa, Yujin. The Existence of God: A Philosophical Introduction (Routledge, 2011) Sennett, James F. & Douglas Groothuis (ed. s), In Defence of Natural Theology: A Post-Humean Assessment (IVP, 2005) Willard, Dallas. Knowing Christ Today: Why We Can Trust Spiritual Knowledge (HarperOne, 2009) Williams, Peter S. A Sceptic s Guide to Atheism (Paternoster, 2009) - C.S. Lewis vs. the New Atheists (Paternoster, 2013) 7

1 Alexander Vilenkin quoted by Lisa Grossman, Death of the eternal cosmos, New Scientist, 14th January 2012, p.7. cf. Alexander Vile kin, Did the Universe Have a Beginning? http://youtu.be/nxcqelhkj7a 2 In the beginning, New Scientist, 14th January 2012, p. 3. 3 Paul Davies, The Birth of the Cosmos, in God, Cosmos, Nature and Creativity (Jill Gready (ed.), Scottish Academic Press, 1995), p. 8-9. 4 Dallas Willard, The Three-Stage Argument for the Existence of God in Contemporary Perspectives on Religious Epistemology (ed. Douglas Geivett & Brendan Sweetman; Oxford University Press, 1992). 5 J.P. Moreland & William Lane Craig, Philosophical Foundatrions for a Christian Worldview (IVP), p. 479-480. 6 Richard Purtill quoted by Charles Taliaferro, Contemporary Philosophy of Religion (Blackwells, 2001), p. 358-359. 7 Stephen Hawking & Leonard Milodinov, The Grand Design (Bantam, 2010), p. 130 & 144. 8 Stephen C. Meyer, Teleological Evolution: The Difference it Doesn t Make, www.arn.org/docs/meyer/sm_teleologicalevolution.htm 9 Robin Collins, Design and the Many Worlds Hypothesis, http://home.messiah.edu/~rcollins/finetune/craig7.htm 10 John Cottingham, Philosophers are finding fresh meanings in Truth, Goodness and Beauty, The Times (June 17, 2006). 11 Peter Cave, Humanism (OneWorld, 2009), p. 146. 12 Russ Shafer-Landau, Whatever Happened to Good and Evil? (OUP), p. 16-17. 13 Jean-Paul Sartre, Existentialism Is a Humanism (Yale University Press, 2007), p. 28, www.marxists.org/reference/archive/sartre/works/exist/sartre.htm 14 H.P. Owen, Why morality implies the existence of God, edited extract from The Moral Argument for Christian Theism (George Allen & Unwin, 1965), in Brian Davies (ed.), Philosophy of Religion: a guide and anthology (OUP, 2000), p. 648. 15 Richard Carrier, Sense & Goodness Without God (Author House, 2005), p. 276. 8