A Generalization of Hume s Thesis

Similar documents
G. H. von Wright Deontic Logic

Supplementary Section 6S.7

prohibition, moral commitment and other normative matters. Although often described as a branch

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014

Philosophia Scientiæ Travaux d'histoire et de philosophie des sciences (Anti-)Realisms: The Metaphysical Issue. Publisher Editions Kimé

An alternative understanding of interpretations: Incompatibility Semantics

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Chapter 6. Fate. (F) Fatalism is the belief that whatever happens is unavoidable. (55)

Paradox of Deniability

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

A Liar Paradox. Richard G. Heck, Jr. Brown University

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

Necessity and Truth Makers

A Judgmental Formulation of Modal Logic

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

Aquinas' Third Way Modalized

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome

Ethical Consistency and the Logic of Ought

1. Lukasiewicz s Logic

Figure 1 Figure 2 U S S. non-p P P

Lecturer: Xavier Parent. Imperative logic and its problems. by Joerg Hansen. Imperative logic and its problems 1 / 16

TRUTH-MAKERS AND CONVENTION T

GROUNDING AND LOGICAL BASING PERMISSIONS

MCQ IN TRADITIONAL LOGIC. 1. Logic is the science of A) Thought. B) Beauty. C) Mind. D) Goodness

Knowledge, Time, and the Problem of Logical Omniscience

Informalizing Formal Logic

TOWARDS A PHILOSOPHICAL UNDERSTANDING OF THE LOGICS OF FORMAL INCONSISTENCY

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility

ILLOCUTIONARY ORIGINS OF FAMILIAR LOGICAL OPERATORS

Deontic Logic. G. H. von Wright. Mind, New Series, Vol. 60, No (Jan., 1951), pp

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE OVERVIEW FREGE JONNY MCINTOSH 1. FREGE'S CONCEPTION OF LOGIC

Durham Research Online

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

A Model of Decidable Introspective Reasoning with Quantifying-In

Review of "The Tarskian Turn: Deflationism and Axiomatic Truth"

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Quantifiers: Their Semantic Type (Part 3) Heim and Kratzer Chapter 6

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

Varieties of Apriority

16. Universal derivation

Quantificational logic and empty names

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

Supervaluationism and Fara s argument concerning higher-order vagueness

Conditionals II: no truth conditions?

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

Logic for Robotics: Defeasible Reasoning and Non-monotonicity

Situations in Which Disjunctive Syllogism Can Lead from True Premises to a False Conclusion

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

On the Aristotelian Square of Opposition

Is and Ought Distinction in Legal Philosophy

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester

CHAPTER 2 THE LARGER LOGICAL LANDSCAPE NOVEMBER 2017

Predicate logic. Miguel Palomino Dpto. Sistemas Informáticos y Computación (UCM) Madrid Spain

CURRICULUM VITAE. Matthew W. McKeon

Requirements. John Broome. Corpus Christi College, University of Oxford.

Reasoning, Argumentation and Persuasion

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

Contrary to Duty Obligations A Study in Legal Ontology

How Gödelian Ontological Arguments Fail

Powerful Arguments: Logical Argument Mapping

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

WITTGENSTEIN ON EPISTEMOLOGICAL STATUS OF LOGIC 1

Review of Philosophical Logic: An Introduction to Advanced Topics *

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

Semantics and the Justification of Deductive Inference

A Defense of the Kripkean Account of Logical Truth in First-Order Modal Logic

Natural Law Controversy: Three Basic Logical Issues, The;Note

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY FALL 2014 COURSE DESCRIPTIONS

Nozick and Scepticism (Weekly supervision essay; written February 16 th 2005)

The normativity of content and the Frege point

Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference

A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports. Stephen Schiffer New York University

2.3. Failed proofs and counterexamples

Necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pp. i-ix, 379. ISBN $35.00.

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016

INTERMEDIATE LOGIC Glossary of key terms

Maudlin s Truth and Paradox Hartry Field

University of St Andrews, Reino Unido. Resumen. Abstract

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

A Solution to the Gettier Problem Keota Fields. the three traditional conditions for knowledge, have been discussed extensively in the

FIRST PUBLIC EXAMINATION. Preliminary Examination in Philosophy, Politics and Economics INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY LONG VACATION 2013

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning

On Priest on nonmonotonic and inductive logic

NON-COGNITIVISM AND THE PROBLEM OF MORAL-BASED EPISTEMIC REASONS: A SYMPATHETIC REPLY TO CIAN DORR

BENEDIKT PAUL GÖCKE. Ruhr-Universität Bochum

Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

Hume s Is/Ought Problem. Ruse and Wilson. Moral Philosophy as Applied Science. Naturalistic Fallacy

Transcription:

Philosophia Scientiæ Travaux d'histoire et de philosophie des sciences 10-1 2006 Jerzy Kalinowski : logique et normativité A Generalization of Hume s Thesis Jan Woleński Publisher Editions Kimé Electronic version URL: http:// philosophiascientiae.revues.org/494 DOI: 10.4000/philosophiascientiae.494 ISSN: 1775-4283 Printed version Date of publication: 1 avril 2006 Number of pages: 109-115 ISBN: 2-84174-392-6 ISSN: 1281-2463 Electronic reference Jan Woleński, «A Generalization of Hume s Thesis», Philosophia Scientiæ [Online], 10-1 2006, Online since 10 June 2011, connection on 05 October 2016. URL : http://philosophiascientiae.revues.org/494 ; DOI : 10.4000/philosophiascientiae.494 The text is a facsimile of the print edition. Tous droits réservés

A Generalization of Hume s Thesis 1 Jan Woleński Université de Krakow (Pologne) More specifically, I will consider the Hume thesis concerning the is/ought relation. This reservation is essential, because we have also another thesis stated by Hume, namely the principle (roughly speaking) that sets with the same cardinality have the same number of elements. Hume s thesis about the is/ought relation is expressed in the following way : 1 An extended version of this paper is forthcoming in [Woleński 2006] under the same title. Philosophia Scientiæ, 10 (1), 2006, 109 115.

110 Jan Woleński I cannot forbear adding to those reasonings an observation, which ma, perhaps be found of some importance. In every system of morality, which I have hitherto met with, I have always remark d that the author proceeds for some time in the ordinary way of reasoning, and establishes the being of a God, or makes observations concerning human affairs ; when of a sudden I am surpris d to find, that instead of usual copulations of propositions, is, and not, I meet with no proposition that is not connected with an ought, or ought not. This change is imperceptible ; but is, however, of the last consequence. For as this ought, or ought not, expresses some new relation or affirmation, ts necessary that it shou d be observed and explain d ; and at the same time that a reason should be given, for what seems altogether inconceivable, how this new relation can be a deduction from others, which are entirely different from it. [Hume 1951, 469] Perhaps it is important to note that the quoted fragment says nothing about the relation between norms as specific linguistic utterances and declarative sentences. In particular, Hume did not characterize oughtsentences as norms or imperatives. He only contrasted two kinds of copulations, relations or affirmations, one expressed by is and is not and another, which is expressed by ought and ought not. What Hume does in his statement, consists in pointing out that ought-sentences are not deducible ( seems altogether inconceivable how this new relation can be deduced from others, which are entirely different from it ). A similar question was considered by Poincaré in his essay about morality and science. 2 According to Poincaré, a correct logical inference with an imperative as its conclusion requires an imperative premise. 3 However, this metalogical rule is defined for a language in which occurs imperatives and declarative sentences, not only the latter. Thus, there is an essential difference between Hume and Poincaré in their approaches to the is/ought problem. I will take Hume s pattern. My aim is to generalize the Hume s thesis for a broad class of modal sentences, that is the variety which includes at least deontic, epistemic and interrogative modalities. I start with deontic modalities for which the Hume thesis was originally formulated. As usually, by deontic sentences I understand instantiations of the following schematic formulas (A is an arbitrary non-deotnic sentential expression) : OA it is obligatory that A; FA is prohi- 2 See [Poincaré 1910], chapter 8. 3 This principle was implicitly adopted by Aristotle in his treatment of normative syllogisms as reconstructed [Kalinowski 1953, 163 173].

A Genralization of Hume s Thesis 111 bited (forbidden that A); PA it is permitted that A. I assume the standard deontic logic, which validates the following equivalences (as definitions) : FA O A; OA O A; PA O A; OA P A; PA FA; FA PA. These dependencies generate the wellknown logical square (or square of oppositions) (D) for deontic sentences (it is isomorphic with the logical square for alethic modal sentences) (see Fig. 1 5 on page 111). Fig. 1 (D) The interpretation : α OA, β FA, γ PA, δ P A. We have the following facts (the symbol indicates that the formula occurring after it is a logical theorem) : (1) (α β) (obligation and prohibition are contraries) ; (2) (α γ) (obligation entails permission) ; (3) (β δ) (prohibition entails permission not) ; (4) (α δ) (obligation and permission not are contradictories) ; (5) (β γ) (prohibition and permission are contradictories) ; (6) (γ δ) (permission and permission not are complementaries).

112 Jan Woleński The Hume thesis cannot be formulated within (D), because it concerns the relation between A and OA. More precisely, the Hume s thesis asserts (*) (A OA). We should consider another diagram, namely (D1) (see Fig. 2). Fig. 2 (D1) The point κ is for A, the point λ for A, the point ν for α β (that is, OA FA; normative determination, symbolically DA) and µ for γ δ (that is, PA.P A; normative indifference ; symbolically IA). We have new theorems, namely α ν (obligation entails determination); β ν (prohibition entail determination); µ γ (indifference entails permission); µ δ (indifference entails permission not). However, (D1) does not suggest anything about validity of (*). Moreover, we have also questions concerning the status of (a) α κ, that is, OA A; (b) κ γ, that is, A PA; (c) γ κ, that is, PA A, and similarly, for β, λ and δ ; (d) κ ν ; (e) ν κ, (e) κ µ ; (f) µ κ, and similarly, for λ and µ. These formulas are not proper for deontic logic, although alethic counterparts of (a) and (b) are valid. In order to investigate the problem, one must appeal to semantics.

A Genralization of Hume s Thesis 113 The best tools are provided by possible world semantics. Not entering too deeply into formal details, let as assume that we have the ordered triple (Kripke frame) S =< K, W, R >, where K is a non-empty set of items called possible worlds, W is a distinguished element of K, usually interpreted as the real world, and R is a binary relation defined on K (the accessibility or alternativeness relation). S is a deontic frame if and only if R is not reflexive, that is, it is not generally true that WRW. In particular, we assume that not W RW. This assumption immediately excludes (a) as not a tautology of deontic logic. Now we define : OA is true in W if and only if A is true in every world W such that WRW. Intuitively, the sentence it is obligatory that A is true in the real world W if and only if A in true in every world W being a deontic alternative to W, that is, in the world which all obligations valid in the real world are satisfied. Accordingly, the sentence PA is true in W* if and only if there is a world W such that WRW* and A is true in W. 4 These intuitive constraints exclude (*), (b) (f) as deontic tautologies. 5 In the light of this analysis the Hume thesis can be generalized to the statement (the letter N denotes one of the symbols O, F, P, P ; moreover, if N is F or P, then A is to be replaced by A outside of the given deontic operator) : (GHT)(a) A NA; (b) NA A. I will call (GHTa) as the simple Hume thesis, and (GHTb) as the converse Hume thesis. The particular cases of both are summarized by the following list : (7) (A OA) (the simple Hume thesis for obligation) ; (8) ( A F A) (the simple Hume thesis for prohibition) ; (9) (OA A) (the converse Hume thesis for obligation) ; (10) (F A A) (the converse Hume thesis for 4 The truth-conditions for FA, P A, DA and IA follow immediately from the definitions for OA and PA. 5 Some instances of (b) and (c) are valid. If A is a tautology, A PA, PA A and OA A are universally true. Moreover, if something is obligatory and A is a tautology, then A OA is also valid. However, (*), (a) (c) are not universally valid.

114 Jan Woleński prohibition) ; (11) (A P A) (the simple Hume thesis for permission) ; (12) ( A P A) (the simple Hume thesis for permission not) ; (13) (P A A) (the converse Hume thesis for permission) ; (14) (P A A) (the converse Hume thesis for permission not) ; (15) (A DA) (the first simple Hume thesis for determination) ; (16) ( A DA) (the second simple Hume thesis for determination) ; (17) (DA A) (the first converse Hume thesis for determination) ; (18) (DA A) (the second converse Hume thesis for determination) ; (19) (A IA) (the first simple Hume thesis for indifference) ; (20) ( A IA) (the second simple Hume thesis for indifference) ; (21) (IA A) (the first converse Hume thesis for indifference) ; (22) (IA A) (the second converse Hume thesis for indifference). It is possible to go further. If we assume normal modal logic, (a) holds for necessity, but (b) for possibility. The converse of (a) is valid only for very special modal logics, but (c) invalid everywhere. However, alethic modal logic is an exception as far as the matter concerns (a) and (b). Most modal contexts behaves like deontic sentences and satisfies (GTM). Thus, the sentence A does not entail I believe (ask, suppose, assert, etc.) that A. The converse dependence holds neither. There are some dubious case. For example, according to the classical definition of knowledge, the sentence I know that A entails A. On Frege s account of assertion, its logical force demands that I assert A entails A. I am inclined to think that these account are not correct. The logical entailment from I know that A to A cannot be justified by definition only. It requires a

115 semantic basis. Of course, it is possible to give it, but the principle if I know that A, then A is possible seems to be more plausible. Frege s account of assertion is open to a similar criticism. If these remarks are right, (GHT) is a very general principle, which is fairly important for many philosophical issues. Let me mention only that this thesis very strongly challenges naturalism in epistemology. Références Hume, D. 1951 Treatise of Human Nature, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 469, 1951. Kalinowski, J. (G.) 1953 Théorie des propositions normatives, Studia Logica I, 163 173, 1953. Poincaré, H. 1910 Dernières Pensées, Paris : Flammarion, chapitre 8, 1910. Woleński, Jan 2006 A Generalization of Hume s Thesis, in T. Childers (ed.), The Logica Yearbook 2006. The Proceedings of the 18th Symposium, Filosofia, Praha 2006.