ECONOMETRIC METHODOLOGY AND THE STATUS OF ECONOMICS. Cormac O Dea. Junior Sophister

Similar documents
A Scientific Realism-Based Probabilistic Approach to Popper's Problem of Confirmation

Methodological criticism vs. ideology and hypocrisy Lawrence A. Boland, FRSC Simon Fraser University There was a time when any university-educated

Sydenham College of Commerce & Economics. * Dr. Sunil S. Shete. * Associate Professor

Falsification or Confirmation: From Logic to Psychology

The poverty of mathematical and existential truth: examples from fisheries science C. J. Corkett

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Revista Economică 66:3 (2014) THE USE OF INDUCTIVE, DEDUCTIVE OR ABDUCTIVE RESONING IN ECONOMICS

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Falsification of Popper and Lakatos (Falsifikace podle Poppera a Lakatose)

Module 1: Science as Culture Demarcation, Autonomy and Cognitive Authority of Science

Science is Judgment, Not Only Calculation: A Reply to Aris Spanos

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

Scientific errors should be controlled, not prevented. Daniel Eindhoven University of Technology

PHILOSOPHIES OF SCIENTIFIC TESTING

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

On the futility of criticizing the neoclassical maximization hypothesis

Hoong Juan Ru. St Joseph s Institution International. Candidate Number Date: April 25, Theory of Knowledge Essay

If I were to give an award for the single best idea anyone has ever had, I d give it to... Darwin

Mementos from Excursion 2 Tour II: Falsification, Pseudoscience, Induction (first installment, Nov. 17, 2018) 1

SAMPLE ESSAY 1: PHILOSOPHY & SOCIAL SCIENCE (1 ST YEAR)

Popper s Falsificationism. Philosophy of Economics University of Virginia Matthias Brinkmann

Inductive Inference, Rationality and Pragmatism: Peirce and Ajdukiewicz

Statistical Inference Without Frequentist Justifications

A Critique of Friedman s Critics Lawrence A. Boland

Philosophy of Economics versus Methodology of Economics

Is the Skeptical Attitude the Attitude of a Skeptic?

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence

Why Creation Science must be taught in schools

Statistics, Politics, and Policy

Objective Evidence and Absence: Comment on Sober

METHODENSTREIT WHY CARL MENGER WAS, AND IS, RIGHT

Lecture 1. The Science of Economics

Comparison between Rene Descartes and Francis Bacon s Scientific Method. Course. Date

Class 6 - Scientific Method

Introduction to Political Science

145 Philosophy of Science

THE HYPOTHETICAL-DEDUCTIVE METHOD OR THE INFERENCE TO THE BEST EXPLANATION: THE CASE OF THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION BY NATURAL SELECTION

What Is Science? Mel Conway, Ph.D.

LTJ 27 2 [Start of recorded material] Interviewer: From the University of Leicester in the United Kingdom. This is Glenn Fulcher with the very first

Betting on God: Pascal, Probability Theory and Theology. nevertheless made surprising contributions to the field of religious philosophy.

The Nature of Science: Methods for Seeking Natural Patterns in the Universe Using Rationalism and Empiricism Mike Viney

Introduction and Background

Ilija Barukčić Causality. New Statistical Methods. ISBN X Discussion with the reader.

Experimental Design. Introduction

Positive Economics as Optimistic Conventionalism

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

Demarcation of Science

A Warning about So-Called Rationalists

CHRISTIANITY AND THE NATURE OF SCIENCE J.P. MORELAND

Copan, P. and P. Moser, eds., The Rationality of Theism, London: Routledge, 2003, pp.xi+292

foundationalism and coherentism are responses to it. I will then prove that, although

"Are Eyebrows Going to Be Talked of in Connection with the Eye of God?" Wittgenstein and Certainty in the Debate between Science and Religion

Business Research: Principles and Processes MGMT6791 Workshop 1A: The Nature of Research & Scientific Method

1/5. The Critique of Theology

Philosophy Of Science On The Moral Neutrality Of Scientific Acceptance

Scientific Method and Research Ethics

Review of Views Into the Chinese Room

Lecture 9. A summary of scientific methods Realism and Anti-realism

Gary Ebbs, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry, Cambridge. University Press, 2017, 278pp., $99.99 (hbk), ISBN

FINAL EXAM REVIEW SHEET. objectivity intersubjectivity ways the peer review system is supposed to improve objectivity

Does law have to be effective in order for it to be valid?

Two Ways of Thinking

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

Florida State University Libraries

Sheldrake's "Hypothesis"

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

imply constrained maximization. are realistic assumptions. are assumptions that may yield testable implications. A and C above.

Epistemology for Naturalists and Non-Naturalists: What s the Difference?

INTRODUCTION TO HYPOTHESIS TESTING. Unit 4A - Statistical Inference Part 1

Philosophy of Economics and Politics

MISSOURI S FRAMEWORK FOR CURRICULAR DEVELOPMENT IN MATH TOPIC I: PROBLEM SOLVING

1s IT possible for a society to distinguish between its own myths and nonmyths?

Teaching the Metatheoretics of Qualitative Methodology. David Waldner Department of Politics University of Virginia. May 14, 2003

The evolution of the meaning of SCIENCE. SCIENCE came from the latin word SCIENTIA which means knowledge.

Unless indicated otherwise, required texts on the syllabus will be available at the Yale University Bookstore.

Philosophy and Methods of the Social Sciences

Scientific Realism and Empiricism

Haberdashers Aske s Boys School

Let s explore a controversial topic DHMO. (aka Dihydrogen monoxide)

From the Greek Oikos = House Ology = study of

Scientific Dimensions of the Debate. 1. Natural and Artificial Selection: the Analogy (17-20)

Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology* Oxford University Press, 2009

Lectures and laboratories activities on the nature of Physics and concepts and models in optic: 1. Scientific sentences

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

MARK KAPLAN AND LAWRENCE SKLAR. Received 2 February, 1976) Surely an aim of science is the discovery of the truth. Truth may not be the

Science, Rationality and the Human Mind. by Garry Jacobs

Chapter 2 Science as a Way of Knowing: Critical Thinking about the Environment

the paradigms have on the structure of research projects. An exploration of epistemology, ontology

1/9. The First Analogy

Baha i Proofs for the Existence of God

The Crisis of Expertise? Continuities and Discontinuities.

Introduction to Deductive and Inductive Thinking 2017

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

A Brief Essay on Essays

Introduction to Statistical Hypothesis Testing Prof. Arun K Tangirala Department of Chemical Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Transcription:

Student Economic Review, Vol. 19, 2005 ECONOMETRIC METHODOLOGY AND THE STATUS OF ECONOMICS Cormac O Dea Junior Sophister The question of whether econometrics justifies conferring the epithet of science on economics is a controversial one. Though the physical sciences are not free from imperfections, Cormac O Dea contends that the problems with econometric methodology are too great to justify scientific status. He concludes by questioning the need felt by some economists to be referred to as scientists. Introduction In examining the nature of econometrics and evaluating its impact on the scientific status of economics, two approaches can be taken. We could consider a scientific realm of knowledge completely and definitively demarcated from all non-scientific knowledge. A second approach involves considering the very real flaws with econometric methodology and comparing them to similar, and again, real flaws in the physical sciences. Such an approach implicitly accepts science as a spectrum of knowledge and allows a ranking of disciplines in terms of their scientific nature. This essay will contend that econometric methodology has added a degree of testability to the economic theory, and by allying economics with mathematics and statistics, rendered the discipline more scientific. However, if we are forced to make an absolute statement, then we must conclude that the inability of econometrics to conclusively and reliably falsify economic theories seriously undermines any claim to scientific status. The Imperfection of the Physical Sciences Sceptics point to the inability (or severely restricted ability) of the social scientist to conduct controlled experiments. Friedman points to the inability of the astronomer to conduct same (1953). Assuming a particular distribution of the error term could be deemed to provide a fatal blow to the econometrician s quest 37

ECONOMETRIC METHODOLOGY AND THE STATUS OF ECONOMICS for scientific status. However, Friedman notes the usefulness of the law of falling bodies in physics, which assumes that the body is falling in a vacuum (ibid). That this assumption is unrealistic and only provides an approximation to reality doesn t undermine the law s usefulness or its scientific status. With regard to the contention that there can be no scientific study of a subject matter of which the student is a part, Boulding reminds us that the Heisenberg Uncertainty Principle is by no means restricted to the social sciences (1969). Another frequent charge is that scientific study of the economic environment is impossible given the constant flux of the subject matter. Boulding notes that the subject matter of the physical sciences is not exactly static, in particular that evolutionary process do not seem to render biology unscientific in the popular consciousness (ibid). It has been contended that the possibility of data mining undermines a claim on scientific status. Such a charge implies that abuses of data and deception are impossible in the physical sciences. Hendry predicts that the future status of econometrics will depend on the spirit with which the subject is tackled (1980: 403). It would seem grossly unfair to assume that the spirit of all physical scientists is beyond reproach while there exists apparently an army of economists and econometricians bent on deception! The above paragraph documents some of the frequent arguments used to contend that economics is not scientific. It has not been an attempt to make a claim to the contrary. It simply points out that many of the flaws that exist with econometric methodology exist to a lesser degree in disciplines whose scientific status is not in question. Though it may be possible to find a counterpart in the physical sciences to each flaw in econometric methodology, those flaws should not be underestimated. Their total effect renders econometric tests inconsistent and non-reproducible, which undermines their claim to scientific status. The Greater Imperfection of Econometric Methodology If econometric methodology is to give scientific rigour to economic theory, it must be capable of falsifying the hypotheses of economic theory. Such hypotheses normally contain a ceteris paribus assumption. The counterpart in econometrics to such an assumption is the disturbance term. All effects, other than those explicitly explained in the model, are included in this term. Assuming that this term follows a particular distribution, as econometric methodology does, it is an attempt to control statistically what we cannot control experimentally. The economic interactions of human beings are governed by an infinite number of forces. Schumpeter claimed that economics was the most quantitative of all sciences as it was made numerical by life itself (Hendry 1980: 389). However 38

CORMAC O DEA many of these forces governing economic behavior are neither numerical nor measurable. They are not even what might be considered economic. The inability of econometrics and the unwillingness of economists to consider such forces flies in the face of its claim to be scientific. In grouping all these forces into one term, the distribution of which is assumed to be known, econometricians take a massive leap of faith. Econometric tests of economic theory are valid only under the exact conditions of the test. Such conditions can never be known exactly, let alone reproduced. This is problematic, given the role of hypothesis testing in econometrics. The interpretation of failing to reject a hypothesis at a 95% level of significance is that in repeated sampling, we would expect to be correct 19 out of each 20 times. However, given the complexity of the forces governing economic behaviour, and our inability to conduct controlled experiments, each experiment is unique, and to talk of repeated sampling is flawed. It is not the probabilistic nature of econometric results which undermines scientific economics. Statistical inference plays a major role in modern quantum physics (Blaug 1980: 31). However a reliance on statistical inference, combined with an inability to reproduce supposedly critical experiments, is a major problem. Random effects are possible in the physical sciences but are all the more present in the social science. It would be tempting to attribute this to an intrinsic randomness in human behaviour. However, such an assertion would be unsafe. An effect that today is attributed to erratic human behaviour could be explained in the future by a variable not yet understood. Popper defines a scientifically significant physical effect as that which can be regularly reproduced by anyone who carries out the appropriate experiment in the way prescribed (Popper 2002: 23-24). Using this criterion, which seems eminently reasonable if theories are to be discredited on the basis of empirical results, econometric results cannot be described as scientifically significant. The Duhem-Quine problem with hypothesis testing has a particular relevance to econometrics, given the infinite number of ancillary hypotheses buried in the assumption about the error term and the specification of the functional form of the model. A rejection (or an incorrect decision not to reject) of a hypothesis concerning an estimated parameter could well be due to any number of flaws with the buried assumptions rather than the falsity of the hypothesis actually under examination. This results from an attempt to control statistically what ideally would be controlled experimentally and undermines the power of econometrics to test economic theory. 39

ECONOMETRIC METHODOLOGY AND THE STATUS OF ECONOMICS A Question of Mindset An ability to use the laws of statistics and mathematics to test and potentially reject hypotheses from theory is a necessary but insufficient condition to justify economics as a science. Economists have to be willing to reject hypotheses should they fail to stand up to econometric testing. Consider Koutsoyiannis: It should be noted that the statistical criteria are secondary only to the a priori theoretical criteria. The estimation of the parameters should be rejected in general if they happen to have the wrong sign (or size) even though the correlation coefficient is high, or the standard errors suggest that the estimates are statistically significant (1977: 26). Such an approach seems to imply that econometrics can t and won t be used to put economic theory to the test. Koutsoyannis sees economic theory as the falsifier of econometric results. The role of econometrics in this regard is simply to provide estimates of parameters in economic models. These models, according to Koutsoyannis, are clearly beyond reproach, at least from econometric testing. The same author exhibits a cavalier attitude to statistical procedure when ignoring the problem of a loss of degrees of freedom every time a regression is run on the same data set using a different functional form. He states: Some loose interpretation of statistical rules is at times essential if econometrics is to be helpful in testing economic theory and in measuring economic relationships (ibid: 25). Once again we cannot dismiss the notion of econometrics testing theory on the basis of one practitioner, but it would seem that Koutsoyannis is not alone. Spanos admits that no economic theory was ever abandoned because it was rejected by some econometric test nor was a clear-cut decision between competing theories made in lieu of such a test (Keuzenkamp 2000: 247). Conclusion Karl Popper is very clear in making a distinction between scientific and meaningful (2002: 18). To state that econometrics does not give scientific status to economic theory is not to say that it is meaningless or useless to policy. The constitution of the econometric society defines the aims of the discipline as the 40

CORMAC O DEA advancement of economic theory in its relation to statistics and mathematics (Frisch 1933). It goes on to describe itself as a scientific organization (ibid). The former definition of econometrics is valid and achievable without the epithet of science. This essay has pointed out that many of the faults with econometric methodology exist in the physical sciences, albeit to a lesser degree. If we are allowed to view science as a spectrum, we can argue that econometrics does grant a certain degree of scientific rigour to economic theory. If we are forced to come up with a yes or no answer, which requires us to draw a definite line between the sciences and the non-sciences, I would argue that econometric methodology does not do enough to justify using economic science to describe what used to be known as the political economy. The debate about the scientific status of econometrics is largely irrelevant and represents a certain professional insecurity in those who desperately seek it. Roy F. Harrod points out that speculation upon methodology offer the greatest opportunity for internecine strife and a victory even if it could be established, is thought to yield no manifest cause to the cause itself (Blaug 1980). Conferring the word science on the discipline would not contribute anything to the development of either economic theory or econometric methodology. Bibliography Blaug, M. (2000) The Methodology of Economics, or, How Economists Explain. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Boulding, K. E. (1969) Economics as a Moral Science. American Economic Review, Vol. 59, pp. 1-13. Brown, W.S. (1991) Introducing Econometrics. St. Paul (Minn): West. Daley, Steven (2004) Being Economical With the Truth. Student Economic Review, Vol. 18, pp. 3-8. Friedman, M. (1953) The Methodology of Positive Economics. University of Chicago Press <http://members.shaw.ca/compilerpress1/anno %20Friedman%20 Positive.htm>. Frisch, Ragnar (1933) Editors Note. Econometrica, Vol. 1, pp. 1-4. 41

ECONOMETRIC METHODOLOGY AND THE STATUS OF ECONOMICS Gujarati, D.N. (1995) Basic Econometrics. New York: McGraw-Hill. Hendry, D. (1980) Econometrics-Alchemy or Science. Economica, Vol. 47, November, pp. 387-406. Keuzenkamp, H. (2000) Probability, Econometrics and Truth: The Methodology of Econometrics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Koutsoyannis, A. (1977) Theory of Econometrics: an introductory exposition of econometric methods. London: Macmillan. Maddala, G.S. (2001) Introduction to Econometrics. Chichester: Wiley. McCloskey, D. (1983) The Rhetoric of Economics. Journal of Economic Literature 21, June. Patinkin, D. (1976) Keynes and Econometrics. Econometrica 44, November. Pesaran, M. and Smith R. (1992) The Interaction between Theory and Observation in Economics. Economic and Social Review, Vol. 24, pp.1-24. Popper, K. (2002) The Logic of Scientific Discovery. London: Routledge. 42