Does God exist? The argument from evil

Similar documents
Does God exist? The argument from evil

The free will defense

The Problem of Evil. Prof. Eden Lin The Ohio State University

Proofs of Non-existence

The problem of evil & the free will defense

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

What should I believe? Only what I have evidence for.

What we want to know is: why might one adopt this fatalistic attitude in response to reflection on the existence of truths about the future?

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments

Am I free? Freedom vs. Fate

David E. Alexander and Daniel Johnson, eds. Calvinism and the Problem of Evil.

The Ontological Argument. An A Priori Route to God s Existence?

Am I free? Free will vs. determinism

A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM

Puzzles for Divine Omnipotence & Divine Freedom

Well, how are we supposed to know that Jesus performed miracles on earth? Pretty clearly, the answer is: on the basis of testimony.

Free will and foreknowledge

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 3

Introduction to Philosophy

Anselm of Canterbury, Proslogion, chapters 2-5 & replies

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

In Defense of The Wide-Scope Instrumental Principle. Simon Rippon

Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification?

The Ontological Argument

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

HANDBOOK. IV. Argument Construction Determine the Ultimate Conclusion Construct the Chain of Reasoning Communicate the Argument 13

Anselm s Equivocation. By David Johnson. In an interview for The Atheism Tapes, from the BBC, philosopher Colin McGinn briefly

10 CERTAINTY G.E. MOORE: SELECTED WRITINGS

A CRITIQUE OF THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. A Paper. Presented to. Dr. Douglas Blount. Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary. In Partial Fulfillment

The belief in the existence of an omniscient, omnipotent and benevolent God is inconsistent with the existence of human suffering. Discuss.

Lecture 4 Good and Bad Arguments Jim Pryor Some Good and Bad Forms of Arguments

What God Could Have Made

Swinburne: The Problem of Evil

Material objects: composition & constitution

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

REASONS AND ENTAILMENT

C. Exam #1 comments on difficult spots; if you have questions about this, please let me know. D. Discussion of extra credit opportunities

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

New Chapter: Philosophy of Religion

An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine. Foreknowledge and Free Will. Alex Cavender. Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

Today we begin our discussion of the existence of God.

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Religious Education and the Floodgates of Impartiality

Paradox of Deniability

An Evaluation of Skeptical Theism

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

The cosmological argument (continued)

Lawrence Brian Lombard a a Wayne State University. To link to this article:

TWO NO, THREE DOGMAS OF PHILOSOPHICAL THEOLOGY

Today we turn to the work of one of the most important, and also most difficult, philosophers: Immanuel Kant.

Introductory Matters

Puzzles of attitude ascriptions

Today s Lecture. Preliminary comments on the Problem of Evil J.L Mackie

Does God exist? The argument from miracles

SWINBURNE ON THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA. CAN SUPERVENIENCE SAVE HIM?

Evil and Omnipotence

Aquinas' Third Way Modalized

Objections to the two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind

THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

Tutorial A03: Patterns of Valid Arguments By: Jonathan Chan

A Liar Paradox. Richard G. Heck, Jr. Brown University

THE ROAD TO HELL by Alastair Norcross 1. Introduction: The Doctrine of the Double Effect.

Replies to Hasker and Zimmerman. Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, I.

Lecture 2.1 INTRO TO LOGIC/ ARGUMENTS. Recognize an argument when you see one (in media, articles, people s claims).

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

James Rachels. Ethical Egoism

Lucky to Know? the nature and extent of human knowledge and rational belief. We ordinarily take ourselves to

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

responding to suffering

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

The St. Petersburg paradox & the two envelope paradox

Today we turn to the work of one of the most important, and also most difficult, of philosophers: Immanuel Kant.

The Rejection of Skepticism

Creation & necessity

Trinity & contradiction

The Ontological Argument

INTERMEDIATE LOGIC Glossary of key terms

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

Why There s Nothing You Can Say to Change My Mind: The Principle of Non-Contradiction in Aristotle s Metaphysics

Pain, Suffering, and a Benevolent God. Topic: The Problem of Good and Evil

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

Mr Vibrating: Yes I did. Man: You didn t Mr Vibrating: I did! Man: You didn t! Mr Vibrating: I m telling you I did! Man: You did not!!

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

God, Evil, and the Contemplation of Infinitely Many Options

PHLA10F 2. PHLA10F What is Philosophy?

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

The Argument from Evil. Why doesn t God do something?

Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

The view that all of our actions are done in self-interest is called psychological egoism.

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

Maudlin s Truth and Paradox Hartry Field

Divine command theory

Transcription:

Does God exist? The argument from evil

One of the oldest, and most important, arguments against the existence of God tries to show that the idea that God is all-powerful and all-good contradicts a very obvious fact about the world: the fact that it contains evil. The reading for today is a powerful version of that argument, which is due to the Australian 20th century philosopher John Mackie.

What we need to understand, first, is why Mackie thinks that these three claims are contradictory. The three claims are: God is omnipotent. God is wholly good. Some evil exists. Now, it is certainly not obvious that these three claims are contradictory. Mackie thinks that we can show them to be contradictory with the help of two further premises: If something is omnipotent, it can do anything. If something is wholly good, it always eliminates as much evil as it can.

God is omnipotent. God is wholly good. Some evil exists. If something is omnipotent, it can do anything. If something is wholly good, it always eliminates as much evil as it can. Now our question is: why does Mackie think that these five claims are contradictory? To answer this, we can begin by thinking about the claims that God is omnipotent and that God is wholly good. If you think about it, what these claims say can be split into two parts. They first say that God exists and, second, say that if God exists, then God is a certain way. So we can replace these two claims with the following three:

God is omnipotent. God is wholly good. Some evil exists. If something is omnipotent, it can do anything. If something is wholly good, it always eliminates as much evil as it can. So we can replace these two claims with the following three: God exists. If God exists, then God is omnipotent. If God exists, then God is wholly good.

God exists. If God exists, then God can do anything. If God exists, then God eliminates as much evil as God can. If something is omnipotent, it can do anything. If God exists, then God is omnipotent. If God exists, then God is wholly good. If something is wholly good, it always eliminates as much evil as it can. If God exists, then God eliminates all evil. Some evil exists. If God exists, then there is no evil. There is no evil. We now have six claims which, as Mackie says, will all look quite plausible to someone who believes in God. What remains is to show that they lead to contradiction.

1. God exists. 2. If God exists, then God is omnipotent. 3. If something is omnipotent, it can do anything. 4. If God exists, then God can do anything. (2,3) 5. If God exists, then God is wholly good. 6. If something is wholly good, it always eliminates as much evil as it can. 7. If God exists, then God eliminates as much evil as God can. (5,6) 8. If God exists, then God eliminates all evil. (4,7) 9. If God exists, then there is no evil. (8) 10. There is no evil. (1,9) 11. Some evil exists. C. There is no evil and some evil exists. (10,11) This is a form of argument called reductio ad absurdum - reduction to absurdity. Unlike every other argument discussed to this point, it is a kind of argument designed to have a false conclusion. Why might one give an argument with a false conclusion? What can be learned from an argument of this sort?

1. God exists. 2. If God exists, then God is omnipotent. 3. If something is omnipotent, it can do anything. 4. If God exists, then God can do anything. (2,3) 5. If God exists, then God is wholly good. 6. If something is wholly good, it always eliminates as much evil as it can. 7. If God exists, then God eliminates as much evil as God can. (5,6) 8. If God exists, then God eliminates all evil. (4,7) 9. If God exists, then there is no evil. (8) 10. There is no evil. (1,9) 11. Some evil exists. C. There is no evil and some evil exists. (10,11) Given that the argument is valid and that it has a false conclusion, we know that one of the six independent premises must be false. Mackie s aim is to convince you that premise (1) is the false premise.

1. God exists. 2. If God exists, then God is omnipotent. 3. If something is omnipotent, it can do anything. 4. If God exists, then God can do anything. (2,3) 5. If God exists, then God is wholly good. 6. If something is wholly good, it always eliminates as much evil as it can. 7. If God exists, then God eliminates as much evil as God can. (5,6) 8. If God exists, then God eliminates all evil. (4,7) 9. If God exists, then there is no evil. (8) 10. There is no evil. (1,9) 11. Some evil exists. C. There is no evil and some evil exists. (10,11) It would be difficult for any sort of traditional believer in God to reject premises (1), (2), or (5). So it looks like the believer in God must reject one of premises (3), (6), or (11). It seems difficult to solve Mackie s problem by denying (3) or (11). It seems very obvious that there is evil in the world; and the reason why there is evil can t be that God is powerless to stop it from happening.

6. If something is wholly good, it always eliminates as much evil as it can. So attention naturally focuses on premise (6). Can you think of any reason why a person - say, a parent - might not eliminate an evil without thereby doing anything wrong? Can this help us to understand why a wholly good being might not eliminate as much evil as it can?

6. If something is wholly good, it always eliminates as much evil as it can. It seems plausible that a wholly good being might not eliminate some evil E when the following two conditions are met: (1) there is some good G such that G outweighs E, and (2) the being cannot being about G without also permitting E This falsifies premise (6) of Mackie s original argument. Can you think of a way that Mackie might revise his argument to get around this problem?

Can you think of a way that Mackie might revise his argument to get around this problem? Let s call any evil for which there is no greater good such that God could not have brought about the good without permitting the evil an unredeemed evil. Then Mackie might try to replace premise (6) in his original argument with the following: 6*. If something is wholly good, it always eliminates as much unredeemed evil as it can. This premise looks hard to deny. Let s see how it might fit into Mackie s argument.

1. God exists. 2. If God exists, then God is omnipotent. 3. If something is omnipotent, it can do anything. 4. If God exists, then God can do anything. (2,3) 5. If God exists, then God is wholly good. 6*. If something is wholly good, it always eliminates as much unredeemed evil as it can. 7*. If God exists, then God eliminates as much unredeemed evil as God can. (5,6*) 8*. If God exists, then God eliminates all unredeemed evil. (4,7*) 9*. If God exists, then there is no unredeemed evil. (8*) 10*. There is no unredeemed evil. (1,9*) 11. Some evil exists. C. There is no unredeemed evil and some evil exists. (10*,11) This argument simply replaces (6) with (6*), and makes the corresponding changes to steps of the argument which are supposed to follow from (6*). Is this still an effective reductio argument? To make the argument imply a contradiction, we need to change premise (11).

1. God exists. 2. If God exists, then God is omnipotent. 3. If something is omnipotent, it can do anything. 4. If God exists, then God can do anything. (2,3) 5. If God exists, then God is wholly good. 6*. If something is wholly good, it always eliminates as much unredeemed evil as it can. 7*. If God exists, then God eliminates as much unredeemed evil as God can. (5,6*) 8*. If God exists, then God eliminates all unredeemed evil. (4,7*) 9*. If God exists, then there is no unredeemed evil. (8*) 10*. There is no unredeemed evil. (1,9*) 11*. Some unredeemed evil exists. C. There is no unredeemed evil and some unredeemed evil exists. (10*, 11*) To make the argument imply a contradiction, we need to change premise (11). Just as in the case of Mackie s original argument it seems that the religious believer must reject one of (3), (6), or (11), so it seems that in the case of the revised argument the religious believer must reject one of (3), (6*), and (11*). Which seems like the most promising choice?

11*. Some unredeemed evil exists. If one denies this, then what one is saying is that, for every evil we encounter in the world, there is some good G such that (1) G outweighs the evil, and (2) God could not have brought about G without permitting the evil. Both aspects of this definition of unredeemed evil raise problems for this denial.

If one denies this, then what one is saying is that, for every evil we encounter in the world, there is some good G such that (1) G outweighs the evil, and (2) God could not have brought about G without permitting the evil. On part (1): Consider some particularly horrific evil like the Holocaust, or the shooting in Newtown. It is not at all implausible to say that, horrible as these events were, some good thing came out of them. But isn t it massively implausible to say that goods came out of them which outweighed the evil they involved? Wouldn t that imply, ludicrously, that if, say, Hitler foresaw whatever the good consequences of the Holocaust might be, he would have been justified in setting it in motion? On part (2): Many of the cases where human agents are justified in permitting evil to occur for the sake of some later good only make sense against the background of our limited powers. For example: a dentist is surely justified in causing pain in order to fix some dental condition; but this wouldn t be true of an omnipotent dentist, whom we would justifiably resent! Consider the pain of some animal killed by a predator. One might be inclined to say that God is justified in permitting this because it leads to the survival of the predator. But once we keep in mind God s omnipotence, this looks pretty implausible. Could it really be true that the only way that an omnipotent being can sustain the life of a lion is by having it kill some other animal?

So while it is not at all implausible to say that God often brings good out of evil, it is not at all clear that this thought by itself provides an effective response to our revised version of Mackie s argument. Next time, we ll ask whether the idea that freedom of the will is a great good might fare better as a response to that argument.