The Ideology of Empiricism. Brent D. Slife and Brent S. Melling. Brigham Young University

Similar documents
ONTOLOGICAL PROBLEMS OF PLURALIST RESEARCH METHODOLOGIES

Testing the Limits of Henriques Proposal: Wittgensteinian Lessons and Hermeneutic Dialogue. Brent Slife, Brigham Young University

Testing the Limits of Henriques Proposal: Wittgensteinian Lessons and Hermeneutic Dialogue

Until recently, the conflict thesis dominated ARE PSYCHOLOGY S MAIN METHODS BIASED AGAINST THE WORLDVIEW OF MANY RELIGIOUS PEOPLE?

Habermas and Critical Thinking

The Kant of Psychology: Joseph Rychlak and. the Bridge to Postmodern Psychology. Brent D. Slife. Brigham Young University

A Review of Norm Geisler's Prolegomena

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

The Prejudice Against Prejudice: A Reply to the Comments. Brent D. Slife, Brigham Young University. Jeffrey S. Reber, University of West Georgia

The Human Science Debate: Positivist, Anti-Positivist, and Postpositivist Inquiry. By Rebecca Joy Norlander. November 20, 2007

Toward a Theistic Method of Science. Brent D. Slife, Brigham Young University

the paradigms have on the structure of research projects. An exploration of epistemology, ontology

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning

Theistic Approaches to Psychology. Brent D Slife and Michael Zhang. Brigham Young University

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Prentice Hall United States History Survey Edition 2013

Prentice Hall U.S. History Modern America 2013

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo

Strange bedfellows or Siamese twins? The search for the sacred in practical theology and psychology of religion

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Published in Analysis 61:1, January Rea on Universalism. Matthew McGrath

Inquiry, Knowledge, and Truth: Pragmatic Conceptions. Pragmatism is a philosophical position characterized by its specific mode of inquiry, and

Chapter Summaries: A Christian View of Men and Things by Clark, Chapter 1

Acknowledging Morality in Methodology

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

MANAGEMENT RESEARCH: A THOUGHT ON VALIDITY OF POSITIVISM

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Introduction: Paradigms, Theism, and the Parity Thesis

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

Philosophy of Ethics Philosophy of Aesthetics. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Logic, Truth & Epistemology. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

A conversation about balance: key principles

Debate Vocabulary 203 terms by mdhamilton25

Cover Page. The handle holds various files of this Leiden University dissertation

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity

Sidgwick on Practical Reason

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Informalizing Formal Logic

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Comments on Lasersohn

SYLLABUS. Department Syllabus. Philosophy of Religion

Virtue Ethics in Practice: The Greenbrier Academy. Brent D. Slife. Brigham Young University

Special Topics on Pastoral Studies and Counseling I: Sociological Perspectives on Pastoral Ministry

Hoong Juan Ru. St Joseph s Institution International. Candidate Number Date: April 25, Theory of Knowledge Essay

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

Christian scholars would all agree that their Christian faith ought to shape how

Alan W. Richardson s Carnap s Construction of the World

Pihlström, Sami Johannes.

Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

1990 Conference: Buddhism and Modern World

CHRISTIANITY AND THE NATURE OF SCIENCE J.P. MORELAND

Brief Remarks on Putnam and Realism in Mathematics * Charles Parsons. Hilary Putnam has through much of his philosophical life meditated on

Introduction. A. The Myths of the Modern Mindset. Prayer

The Inscrutability of Reference and the Scrutability of Truth

Christ-Centered Critical Thinking. Lesson 6: Evaluating Thinking

Intrinsic Properties Defined. Peter Vallentyne, Virginia Commonwealth University. Philosophical Studies 88 (1997):

Concepts of Divine Action for a Theistic Approach to Psychology

EXAM PREP (Semester 2: 2018) Jules Khomo. Linguistic analysis is concerned with the following question:

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY

The stated objective of Gloria Origgi s paper Epistemic Injustice and Epistemic Trust is:

Qualified Realism: From Constructive Empiricism to Metaphysical Realism.

Delusions and Other Irrational Beliefs Lisa Bortolotti OUP, Oxford, 2010

Huemer s Clarkeanism

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

On the Rationality of Metaphysical Commitments in Immature Science

Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008

THE QUESTION OF "UNIVERSALITY VERSUS PARTICULARITY?" IN THE LIGHT OF EPISTEMOLOGICAL KNOWLEDGE OF NORMS

Defending Some Objections to Moti Mizrahi s Arguments for Weak Scientism

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Levinas, Meaning, and Philosophy of Social Science: From Ethical Metaphysics to Ontology and Epistemology

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

ANALOGIES AND METAPHORS

The Character of Space in Kant s First Critique By Justin Murphy October 16, 2006

Diversity in Epistemic Communities: A Response to Clough Maya J. Goldenberg, University of Guelph

Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus

PROSPECTS FOR A JAMESIAN EXPRESSIVISM 1 JEFF KASSER

A Framework for the Good

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

LOCKE STUDIES Vol ISSN: X

Freedom of Religion and Law Schools: Trinity Western University

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

Unrestricted Quantification and Reality: Reply to Kim. Takashi Yagisawa. California State University, Northridge

MDiv Expectations/Competencies ATS Standard

Transcription:

Ideology of Empiricism 1 The Ideology of Empiricism Brent D. Slife and Brent S. Melling Brigham Young University Brent Slife is currently Professor of Psychology at Brigham Young University, where he chairs the doctoral program in Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology and is a member of the doctoral program in Clinical Psychology. Recently honored with the Eliza R. Snow and Karl G. Maeser awards for Outstanding Scholarship, he was also distinguished as "Teacher of the Year" by the university and Most Outstanding Professor by the Psychology Honorary, Psi Chi. As a Fellow of several professional organizations, he has served as the President of the Society of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology and on the editorial boards of six journals. He has authored over 120 articles and books, and enjoys a small private clinical practice of over 25 years. Brent S. Melling is currently a doctoral student in the Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology Program at Brigham Young University. Melling s research interests include issues of religion/psychology integration. Contact Information: Slife and can be reached at slife@byu.edu and at: Dept of Psychology, Brigham Young University, Provo, Utah 84602. Melling can be reached at brentmelling@gmail.com and the same BYU department address.

Ideology of Empiricism 2 The Ideology of Empiricism Brent D. Slife and Brent S. Melling Brigham Young University We congratulate Paul Watson (this issue) on his attempt to navigate the difficult research shoals of postmodernism in psychology. We support his efforts but want to call attention to a deeper issue concerning research and postmodernism the philosophy of science, especially epistemology. We see Watson as rightly focused on the implications of postmodernism for methods, especially questionnaire type methods. His arguments and correctives regarding the biases or ideologies of these supposedly objective methods are helpful and cogent in our view. Our response, however, concerns less the ideologies of methods and more the ideologies of methodologies. We recognize that the terms methods and methodologies are sometimes considered synonymous in psychology. Still, we are making a fairly common distinction between the methods used and the methodologies (studies of methods) or philosophies that guide the use of these methods, including the empirical method itself (Creswell, 2003). Our central concern is to extend, in a sense, the arguments of Watson to the methodological or philosophy of science level. He describes how the subtle influences of ideology can lead to norms of inclusion and exclusion (p. 24), even in scientific research. He demonstrates how certain research methods, considered by many researchers to map domains such as authoritarianism and intolerance in an unbiased fashion, are actually biased against or at least oversimplify Christian sensibilities. As he puts it so graphically, some research methods seem almost designed to ideologically ambush Christians (p. 24).

Ideology of Empiricism 3 Philosophy of science. Our contribution to this discussion is to suggest that these hidden biases may also be operating in methods on the level of the philosophy of science. Watson hints at this other level when he points to the problems in using even rational methods. He is quite right that many postmodernists would deny the neutrality of such methods, citing inherent and implicit biases, depending on culture and context (Clegg & Slife, in press). What Watson does not mention explicitly, but seems to intimate in spots, is that this myth of neutrality can also be leveled at the empiricist. Empiricism is often used as a synonym for the objective or real, as in Watson s own use of empirical realities (p. 29). However, scientific empiricism is a particular epistemology or philosophy that undergirds and implicitly guides the researcher s actions as he or she formulates and conducts scientific investigations. Empiricism, in this sense, is itself an ideology, with its own assumptions about knowledge and its own values about what is important. Indeed, the traditional (British) empiricism of quantitative methods is frequently defined as limiting knowledge and knowing to sensory experience exclusively (Curd & Cover, 1998; Slife & Williams, 1995). This restriction is, of course, the reason that traditional scientific methods have focused on observables almost exclusively. Indeed, it is the wide acceptance of this approach that has led to its lack of recognition as an ideology. For example, some researchers have assumed that this is the only proven method of science, yet there is no empirical evidence for the philosophy of empiricism. Even if we could scientifically compare empiricism with some other epistemology, which epistemology would we use to make the comparison?

Ideology of Empiricism 4 Many researchers also do not view empiricism as a limitation of science. Along with many research methods texts, they consider empiricism to be synonymous with science, and thus assume that observables are all that can be known scientifically. Watson s (this issue) own language could be interpreted to have this implication: empirical proof (p. 6), tested empirically (p. 9), empirical analysis (p. 24), and empirical realities (p. 29). With this interpretation, empiricism is not considered one of the many possible ideologies of science; it is viewed as axiomatic of science. We would argue that this view is false. After all, humans can experience and know all sorts of things that are not observable. Thoughts, feelings, many spiritual experiences, and even meanings and relationships are not strictly sensory experiences and do not fall on our retinas in the sense of vision and observability. The narrative of Genesis, for example, is experienced but not sensorily experienced. The printed words fall on our retinas, to be sure, but the relations among these words their meanings do not. Similarly, the individuals of interpersonal relationships fall on our retinas, but the relationship we form with these individuals the betweenness of these individuals is never observable. Of course, just because these unobservables are experienced and knowable in some sense does not mean that they are systematically or scientifically knowable. Still, many who advocate qualitative methods would claim that these types of meanings and relationships can be studied scientifically, but not with traditional empiricist epistemology (Denzin & Lincoln, 2000; Packer & Addison, 1989; Polkinghorne, 1988; Slife & Gantt, 1999). If this is true, then traditional empiricism is not axiomatic, but is rather a kind of scientific ideology, with other possible philosophies of science available. Indeed, this

Ideology of Empiricism 5 empiricism may contain a type of ideological ambush, to use Watson s colorful phrase, for Christians who believe that there is more to life and knowledge than what can be experienced through the five senses. For example, this form of empiricism could deny the possibility of studying religious unobservables, such as the meanings of the Holy Spirit or the relationships of agape love, even before investigation of these topics is attempted. Operationalization. We acknowledge that many empiricists would claim that they do study unobservables through operationalizations. When some unobservable subject matter is of interest, such as attitudes, feelings, or spiritual experiences, empiricist epistemology requires that the psychological researcher operationalize and thus translate these unobservable constructs into observable procedures or operations. Researchers often assume that these operationalizations are direct manifestations of unobservables, such as the unobservable feelings of love manifesting observable hugs. Still, love can occur without hugs and hugs can occur without love, making their presumed connection (or any such operationalization) in no way necessary. Perhaps more importantly from an empiricist s perspective, we cannot know, in principle, the relation between operationalizations and their constructs because these relationships and the constructs themselves are not observable (Slife, Wiggins, & Graham, 2005). In this sense, the epistemology and its ideological surround still drive what is studied, because the unobservables of interest are never themselves actually studied; only their observable operationalizations are studied. In this sense, we have a discipline of operationalizations, with no empirically knowable connection to the

Ideology of Empiricism 6 constructs of interest. Furthermore, this disciplinary state is not the result of the research itself; it is a result of a pre-investigatory, epistemological bias. Science as ideology. Even in this operationalized sense, empiricism is still an ideology because it contains philosophical biases and selectively attends to only one portion of our experience. Most significantly for our purposes here, these biases and selectivity may undervalue or ignore experiences that are important to the Christian, such as meanings, spiritual experiences, and relationships. In the same sense that Watson advocates the evaluation of assessment instruments, we would advocate the evaluation of philosophies of science. We do not assume that empiricism is bad or wholly unfit for the psychology of religion (or Christianity, for that matter). However, we would argue that that this methodology of method is relatively overlooked and should be evaluated with Christian values and assumptions in mind. For example, the assumptions associated with qualitative research methods (and methodology) may be more compatible with some Christian investigative questions. As mentioned, qualitative research is held to be a scientific way of studying unobservable meanings and relationships (Denzin & Lincoln, 2000; Packer & Addison, 1989; Polkinghorne, 1988). Although qualitative research is itself sometimes characterized as empirical, it typically does not maintain the same assumptions as traditional empiricism (Slife & Gantt, 1999). Moveover, although qualitative researchers rely on a participant s experiences, they do not require nonsensory experiences to be translated and thus operationalized into sensory experiences. We do not mean to advocate qualitative methods here. All methods will have their pros and cons, depending on a host of contextual considerations (Slife, in press).

Ideology of Empiricism 7 Knowing these pros and cons will thus be crucial to correctly interpreting scientific data of all types. As the old saw goes, just because you have only a hammer [the empirical method] doesn t mean that everything important [even in science] is a nail or, we would add, can be operationalized as a nail. When combined with logical positivism, as empiricism often is in psychology, we have a complex combination of ideological values that one of us has delineated in several other publications (e.g., Slife, Wilson, & Judd, 2007; Slife, in press; Slife & Gantt, 1999). Indeed, an upcoming special issue of the journal, Counseling and Values, focuses specifically on methodological values, comparing in many cases traditional quantitative values with qualitative values. Traditional quantitative methods, for example, include many isms or formal systems of values, such as objectivism (assuming that bias is bad ), reductionism (reducing meanings to principles or laws), and materialism (presupposing that matter is what matters in science). However, these methods also include a host of related but less formal values, such as deciding methods before investigation, considering them fixed when conducting studies, and quantifying meanings. Practical implications. These formal and informal method ideologies have very practical implications for the results that we find from these methods. As a pertinent example here, the questionnaire method that Watson discusses is guided and even limited by these values. For instance, questionnaire methods tend to assume that the quantification of meanings is necessary, whereas many qualitative methods assume that representing meanings with numbers is impoverished, if not misleading. In addition, many qualitative researchers would want to study meanings in the participants native or

Ideology of Empiricism 8 lived language. In other words, qualitative researchers would assume that very few participants are skillful at speaking numbers, so asking participants to code complex meanings in numerical form is considered doubly problematic. As Watson (this issue) also notes insightfully with regard to questionnaire methods, method values can be theologies or anti-theologies in disguise (Millbank, 1991, p. 3). For this reason, it is incumbent upon Christian researchers to examine the values of traditional scientific methods to discern their underlying theological assumptions. Do they, for instance, stack up well to the theistic assumptions of Christians? We would suggest in this regard that most empiricist/positivist philosophies of science also include reductive naturalistic assumptions that imply that no understanding of God is required to make sense of the world (Griffin, 2000; Slife & Whoolery, 2006). It is not merely coincidental, in this sense, that God or divine influence is not mentioned in research methods texts. Psychological research is thought to be conceivable and conductable without God or as if God plays no essential role. Again, many psychological researchers may assume that the methodologies of science are neutral to theology that no essential role is a kind of nonpartisanship. However, we would suggest that assuming God is not required for the formulation or conducting of research methods is not the same as, and certainly not neutral to, assuming that God is required for good and complete research activities. Perhaps it is controversial to assert that the latter assumption is at least implicitly presupposed by all Christians. Still, it is surely true that many Christians would presume a strong theism in this sense because they believe that divine influences are involved in the events that affect research.

Ideology of Empiricism 9 If so, then many Christians may not agree with the naturalistic assumptions of the traditional philosophy of science. If this is true, then several practical questions should be asked of psychological research and researchers. For example, are there research designs and/or study topics in which Christian sensibilities are ambushed in the sense implied by Watson? Do these designs, philosophies, or topics require ideological translation, analogous to Watson s strategies, to another type of methodology? In many topics of meaning and spirituality, for instance, we would contend that some qualitative methodologies are more appropriate than some quantitative methodologies. Even if the assumptions of a particular system of methods are acceptable to many Christians, questions of how these values affect the findings would still need to be addressed. Methodological pluralism. This type of methodological sophistication is part of the reason we would advocate what is sometimes called methodological pluralism (Roth, 1987; Slife & Gantt, 1999). We are aware that the term pluralism is often associated with the zeitgeist of postmodernism, especially in its many forms of relativism. However, the form of pluralism that we would favor is simply the notion that all method philosophies should be evaluated for the advantages and disadvantages they bring to a particular investigative question. Harkening back to the hammer metaphor, we would advocate a kind of Jamesian pragmatism that is perhaps best modeled by the successful carpenter. Hammers are helpful and even necessary when pounding nails, but screws are better handled by screwdrivers, and when cutting boards hammers are of almost no use at all.

Ideology of Empiricism 10 Much as the recent APA Task Force on evidence-based practice recognized the need for a diversity of methods (APA, 2006), we would argue that a similar diversity of methodologies is important, particularly when we attempt to discern and investigate the unique subject matters associated with Christianity. We do not wish for our carpentry analogy to mislead anyone; important challenges await those who attempt a methodological pluralism. Nevertheless, ignoring the hidden ideologies that prompt these challenges does not make them go away. We agree with Watson as he concludes, method cannot and should not escape ideology (p. 28). We would only add that his conclusion applies to methodology as well.

Ideology of Empiricism 11 References APA Presidential Task Force on Evidence-Based Practice. (2006). Evidence-based practice in psychology. American Psychologist, 61, 271-285. Bohman, J. (1993). New philosophy of social science. Cambridge: MIT Press. Clegg, J., & Slife, B.D. (in press). Research ethics in the postmodern context. In D. Mertens & P. Ginsberg (Eds.), Handbook of social research ethics. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications. Curd, M., & Cover, J. A. (1998). Philosophy of science: The central issues. New York: W. W. Norton & Company. Creswell, J. (2003). Research Design: Qualitative, Quantitative, and Mixed Methods Approaches. Thousand Oaks, California: Sage Publications. Denzin, N. K., & Lincoln, Y. S. (Eds.). (2000). Handbook of qualitative methods. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications. Griffin, D.R. (2000). Religion and scientific naturalism: Overcoming the conflicts. Albany: SUNY Press. Millbank, J. (1991). Theology and social theory. Oxford: Blackwell. Packer, M. J., & Addison, R. B. (Eds.). (1989). Entering the circle: Hermeneutic investigation in psychology. Albany, NY: SUNY Press. Polkinghorne, D. E. (1988). Narrative knowing and the human sciences. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press. Roth, P. A. (1987). Meaning and method in the social sciences: A case for methodological pluralism. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

Ideology of Empiricism 12 Slife, B.D. (in press). A primer of the values implicit in counseling research. Counseling and Values. Slife, B. D., & Gantt, E. (1999). Methodological pluralism: A framework for psychotherapy research. Journal of Clinical Psychology. 55 (12), 1 13. Slife, B.D., Wilson, J., & Judd, J. (2007). Controversial issues in psychological science. In Slife, B.D. (Ed.) Taking sides: Clashing views on controversial psychological issues. (15th Edition). New York: McGraw-Hill. Slife, B. D., & Whoolery, M. (2006). Are psychology s main methods biased against the worldview of many religious people? Journal of Psychology and Theology, 34 (3), 217 231. Slife, B. D., Wiggins, B. J., & Graham, J. T. (2005). Avoiding an EST monopoly: Toward a pluralism of methods and philosophies. Journal of Contemporary Psychotherapy, 35, 83 97.