ORIGINS OF MODERN PHILOSOPHY The Problem of Induction

Similar documents
The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

Business Research: Principles and Processes MGMT6791 Workshop 1A: The Nature of Research & Scientific Method

Falsification or Confirmation: From Logic to Psychology

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Treatise I,iii,14: Hume offers an account of all five causes: matter, form, efficient, exemplary, and final cause.

Hume s An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding

Learning from Mistakes Karl Popper and Thomas Kuhn

complete state of affairs and an infinite set of events in one go. Imagine the following scenarios:

Lecture 25 Hume on Causation

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

What does it mean if we assume the world is in principle intelligible?

HUL 841: Philosophy of Science IInd Semester,

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

WHAT IS HUME S FORK? Certainty does not exist in science.

1/6. The Second Analogy (2)

Of Cause and Effect David Hume

Logic: inductive. Draft: April 29, Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of premises P1,

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

Inductive Inference, Rationality and Pragmatism: Peirce and Ajdukiewicz

1/7. Metaphysics. Course Leader: Dr. Gary Banham. Room Tel. Ext.: 3036

POLI 342: MODERN WESTERN POLITICAL THOUGHT

Introduction to Deductive and Inductive Thinking 2017

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

A Warning about So-Called Rationalists

David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature ( ), Book I, Part III.

Sydenham College of Commerce & Economics. * Dr. Sunil S. Shete. * Associate Professor

YFIA205 Basics of Research Methodology in Social Sciences Lecture 1. Science, Knowledge and Theory. Jyväskylä 3.11.

Scientific Method and Research Ethics

Class 6 - Scientific Method

LOCKE STUDIES Vol ISSN: X

VI. CEITICAL NOTICES.

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

PHILOSOPHICAL RAMIFICATIONS: THEORY, EXPERIMENT, & EMPIRICAL TRUTH

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Evolution: The Darwinian Revolutions BIOEE 2070 / HIST 2870 / STS 2871

PHILOSOPHIES OF SCIENTIFIC TESTING

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of

Analogy and Pursuitworthiness

Demarcation of Science

Oxford Scholarship Online: The Cement of the Universe

Introductory Essay University of Pittsburgh Press. All rights reserved.

Ilija Barukčić Causality. New Statistical Methods. ISBN X Discussion with the reader.

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2

Hume, skepticism, and the search for foundations

The British Empiricism

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Certainty, Necessity, and Knowledge in Hume s Treatise

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

! Jumping ahead 2000 years:! Consider the theory of the self.! What am I? What certain knowledge do I have?! Key figure: René Descartes.

APEH ch 14.notebook October 23, 2012

Do we have knowledge of the external world?

Hoong Juan Ru. St Joseph s Institution International. Candidate Number Date: April 25, Theory of Knowledge Essay

HUME S IDEA OF NECESSARY CONNECTION A POSITIVE VIEW AGAINST THE TRADITIONAL MISUNDERSTANDING

Chapter 16 George Berkeley s Immaterialism and Subjective Idealism

The Unbearable Lightness of Theory of Knowledge:

Hume. Hume the Empiricist. Judgments about the World. Impressions as Content of the Mind. The Problem of Induction & Knowledge of the External World

APEH Chapter 6.notebook October 19, 2015

IDHEF Chapter 2 Why Should Anyone Believe Anything At All?

Hume s Missing Shade of Blue as a Possible Key. to Certainty in Geometry

1/8. Introduction to Kant: The Project of Critique

Metaphysics. Gary Banham

Physics and Metaphysics

1/8. Descartes 3: Proofs of the Existence of God

Notes on Bertrand Russell s The Problems of Philosophy (Hackett 1990 reprint of the 1912 Oxford edition, Chapters XII, XIII, XIV, )

Science, Rationality and the Human Mind. by Garry Jacobs

WEEK 1: WHAT IS KNOWLEDGE?

someone who was willing to question even what seemed to be the most basic ideas in a

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

A Quick Review of the Scientific Method Transcript

Hume s Methodology and the Science of Human Nature

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

A Studying of Limitation of Epistemology as Basis of Toleration with Special Reference to John Locke

Theory of Knowledge. 5. That which can be asserted without evidence can be dismissed without evidence. (Christopher Hitchens). Do you agree?

A Brief History of Scientific Thoughts Lecture 5. Palash Sarkar

Two Ways of Thinking

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

Hume, Causation and Subject Naturalism. as opposed to that of an object naturalist. Object naturalism involves the ontological

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence

Critical Thinking 5.7 Validity in inductive, conductive, and abductive arguments

Every simple idea has a simple impression, which resembles it; and every simple impression a correspondent idea

Are Miracles Identifiable?

Critical Thinking: Present, Past and Future 5 April, 2015

Syllabus. Primary Sources, 2 edition. Hackett, Various supplementary handouts, available in class and on the course website.

Lecture 4: Transcendental idealism and transcendental arguments

Introduction to Philosophy

Kant s Misrepresentations of Hume s Philosophy of Mathematics in the Prolegomena

Lecture 9. A summary of scientific methods Realism and Anti-realism


Lecture 6. Realism and Anti-realism Kuhn s Philosophy of Science

Syllabus. Primary Sources, 2 edition. Hackett, Various supplementary handouts, available in class and on the course website.

The Nature of Science: Methods for Seeking Natural Patterns in the Universe Using Rationalism and Empiricism Mike Viney

THE RELATION BETWEEN THE GENERAL MAXIM OF CAUSALITY AND THE PRINCIPLE OF UNIFORMITY IN HUME S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE

Transcription:

ORIGINS OF MODERN PHILOSOPHY The Problem of Induction Peter Prevos 23 May 2005 1 Introduction Inductive inferences play an important role on our every day and scientific thinking. Francis Bacon (1561 1626) argued that we are able to derive universal principles from a finite number of examples, by means of induction. 1 A well known example of a generalising induction is: Millions of swans have been observed and all of them were white, therefore by induction the statement all swans are white is true. Scientific inductions amplify particular observations to universal laws to make predictions about future behaviour of physical systems. The problem of induction is what justification can there be for making such an inference? Can we actually make a universal claim based on a finite number of observations? David Hume (1711 1776) is usually credited to be the first to ask this question and analyse the problem of induction. Hume comes to the conclusion that there is no rational justification for inductive references and that Bacon was wrong in assuming that we can derive universal principles from observation of the particular. Many philosophers have attempted to solve this problem, but there is still no consensus on how to solve the issue, or whether it is actually solvable. We are still in the same position Hume put us in. 2 Karl Popper (1902 1994) accepts the validity This paper has been written for the Monash University course Origins of Modern Philosophy B, amended with comments by Aubrey Townsend. 1 Jürgen Klein, Francis Bacon, in: Edward N. Zalta, editor, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, (2004) http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2004/entries/francis-bacon/. 2 Olaf Dietrich, A constructivist approach to the problem of induction, Evolution and Cognition 1 (1995):2 http://www.vub.ac.be/clea/people/dietrich/induction.html Accessed: 9 May 2005; John Earman and Wesley C. Salmon, The confirmation of scientific hypotheses, in: Merrilee H. Salmon, editor, Introduction to the philosophy of science, (Prentice Hall, 1992), p. 182. 1

of the Humean critique of induction, but believes that science does not depend on induction at all. If Popper is correct, the induction problem seems to evaporate. In this essay, the sceptical arguments regarding the validity of inductive inferences by David Hume and the solution proposed by Karl Popper will be investigated. It will be argued that, although Popper s solution has significant practical implications, Hume s problem remains unsolved and a totally different approach is needed to account for the success of inductive reasoning. 2 Hume s argument for inductive scepticism Hume outlines his argument for inductive scepticism in both the Treatise of Human Nature and the Enquiries Concerning the Human Understanding. 3 also summarises his position in an abstract of the Treatise he published. 4 Hume Hume s analysis of induction is closely related to his ideas on causation, for all reasonings concerning matter of fact seem to be founded on the relation of Cause and Effect. 5 Hume argues that when we see one billiard ball hitting another, what we perceive is that they strike and the ball, which was formerly at rest, now is in motion. From this perception, it is evident that the two balls touched each other before the motion of the second ball commenced. Contiguity in time and place are thus a requisite circumstance for the operation of all causes. It is also evident to Hume that the two motions follow each other in time (priority) and Hume also believes that there is a constant conjunction between cause and effect in that similar circumstances always produce similar effects. Hume notes that tis commonly suppos d, that there is a necessary connexion betwixt the cause and effect, and that the cause possesses something, which we call a power, or force, or energy. 6 Hume can, however, not see anything beyond contiguity, priority and constant conjunction between cause and effect. The actual connection between cause and effect is an occult quality and Hume remarks that nature has kept us at a great distance from all her secrets 7 The powers by which bodies operate are 3 David Hume; John P. Wright, Robert Stecker, and Gary Fuller, editors, A treatise of human nature, (London: Everyman, 2003); David Hume; L.A. Selby-Bigge, editor, An enquiry concerning the human understanding, and an enquiry concering the principles of morals, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1894). 4 David Hume, An abstract of a book published; entitled a Treatise of Human Nature &c, (London, 1740) http://www.gale.com/eighteenthcentury/ Accessed: 13 may 2005. 5 Hume (1894), p. 26, Book I, Section IV, 22. 6 Hume (1740), p. 22. 7 Hume (1894), pp. 32 33, Book I, Section IV, 28. 2

entirely unknown as we perceive only their sensible qualities. 8 Hume wants to find out what this inference from cause to effect is founded upon. The stakes are high, as Hume considers the inference from cause to effect to be the cornerstone of all our knowledge about the world, except for mathematics. 9 Hume notes that, although the premise of a predictive inductive inference is true, the conclusion can nevertheless be false. Although we have always perceived the same cause and effect, their connection is not a necessary truth: the mind can always conceive any effect to follow from any cause, and indeed any event to follow upon another: whatever we conceive is possible, at least in a metaphysical sense. 10 The conclusion that all swans are white was, until Dutch explorer Willem de Vlamingh in 1697 was the first European to see a black swan in Australia, considered a fact. 11 De Vlamingh thus falsified the previously considered universal truth that all swans are white. Hume concludes from the fact that inductions can produce false conclusions from true premises that induction can not be a rational inference. The claim that induction is not a rational inference depends, according to Aubrey Townsend, on two steps. The first is to conclude that induction is not demonstrative, or deductive. In the second stage he also needs an argument to show that if induction is not demonstrative but probable, then still it is not a rational inference, because it rests on a presumption that can only be justified by a circular use of inductive reasoning. 12 Hume, in line with Cartesian thinking, believes that rational reasoning is by definition error-free and inductive inferences can therefore not be rational. The only way we can make inferences from the impression to the idea (induction) is, according to Hume, by relying on experience of the constant conjunction of the objects in question. Hume writes: even after we have experience of the operations of cause and effect, our conclusions from that experience are not founded on reasoning, or any process of the understanding. 13 The core of Hume s argument is the claim that all probable arguments presuppose that the future resembles the past (the Uniformity Principle) and that the Uniformity Principle is a matter of fact. That the future resembles the past is, however, not something we derive from reason but from experience alone. Hume argues that because it is no contradiction that the course of nature may change, any object 8 Hume (1740), p. 16. 9 Ibid., p. 13. 10 Ibid., p. 14. 11 VOC Historical Society,Perth, Voyage to the South Land, http://www.voc.iinet.net.au/ vlamingh.html Accessed: 10 May 2005. 12 E-mail from Aubrey Townsend, June 2005. 13 Hume (1894), p. 32, Book I, Section IV, 28. 3

may be causing different effects in the future and all previous inductions will fail. 14 Prior to 1697, everybody who had ever seen a white swan assumed, following the Uniformity Principle, that all future swans would also be white. This implies that the results of an inductive argument is probable, but never certain, as pointed out earlier. This again leads to the circularity objection, because the Uniformity Principle, as a justification of induction itself is based on an induction. Hume thus concludes that not reason, but custom alone, leads us to conclude that induction is a valid inference. To justify induction and to show that it is rational, Hume needs to be able to show that though on particular occasions induction will take us from truth to falsehood, as in the case with the swans, yet in the long run, induction will get us nearer to the truth. That is what Descartes attempted to do with the argument based on a proof of God s existence and veracity. Hume wanted to show that any such program will fail. 3 Reactions to Hume s argument Hume s problem of induction strikes at the very foundation of empirical science. Following Hume, all inductive reasoning should be accompanied with a disclaimer, warning that every connection with reality is based on pure coincidence. 15 Bertrand Russell thought that Hume s philosophy represents the bankruptcy of eighteenthcentury reasonableness and if there is no solution to Hume s problem, there is no intellectual difference between sanity and insanity. 16 Several arguments have been developed in response to the problem posed by Hume. 3.1 Deductivism Hume s argument depends on the claim that all inductive inferences presuppose the Uniformity Principle and that this principle can not be derived from reason, but only from observation. The question to be asked is whether all inductive reasoning indeed depends on the Uniformity Principle. David Stove argues that inductive arguments depend on the Uniformity Principle because the addition makes inductive 14 Hume (1894), p. 35, Book I, Section IV, 30. 15 Thanks to Ian Watson for this suggestion. 16 Bertrand Russell, History of western philosophy, 2nd edition. (London: Routledge, 1961), pp. 645 646. 4

arguments deductively valid. 17 If Stove is right, then all inductive arguments are actually deductive arguments with a hidden premise. A characteristic difference between inductive and deductive arguments is that, if the premises are correct, the outcome of a deductive argument will always be correct as well. This is not the case in inductive reasonings, as Hume pointed out. If the addition of the Uniformity Principle would render an inductive argument deductively valid, then the Uniformity Principle must be false, because the principle would be shown to be false by every inductive failure. Stove s lines of reasoning renders the Uniformity Principle false, something which most people would not be willing to accept. 3.2 The success of science Another reply to Hume is by pointing out the success of the application of inductive reasoning in science. The fact that I am writing this essay on a computer can be considered proof that the rules of physics, on which the technology enabling the existence of this computer are based, are in fact true. These rules of physics are, in turn, based on ampliative reasoning through inductive inferences. From this follows that inference is a valid way of concluding the universal from the particular. Other modes of obtaining knowledge, such as divination, do not have such a reliable track record and are thus inferior to the empirical sciences. The problem with this justification is that it uses the scientific method to justify the scientific method. To predict that the scientific method will continue to be successful in the future because it has been successful in the past is a circular argument. 18 4 Popper s Critical Rationalism Karl Popper characterises the scientific method not as a process of observation and inductive reasoning, but as a process of conjectures and refutations. 19 Popper describes a scientist as:... a man dressed in black, who in a black room looks for a black hat, which may not be there... he tentatively tries for the black hat. 20 There is, according to Popper, no such thing as a logical method of having new 17 Davide Stove, Hume, probability and induction, in: V.C. Chappell, editor, Hume: A collection of essays, (1966). Cited in Aubrey Townsend, editor, Origins of modern philosophy B, (Melbourne: Monash University, 1998), p. 136. 18 Earman and Salmon (1992), p. 178. 19 Karl R. Popper, Conjectures and refutations, 5th edition. (London: Routledge, 1989). 20 Open Universiteit, De menselijke kennis en haar vijanden (Human knowledge and its enemies), (VHS, 1988). 5

ideas and discovery of scientific theories always contains an irrational element. 21 Albert Einstein refers to this irrational element as an intuition, based on empathy (Einfühlung) with experience. 22 This in contrast to Isaac Newton, who insisted that he does not invent theories (hypothesis non fingo) and that intuition plays no role in science. 23 It is interesting to note that according to his assistant John Conduitt, Newton discovered a critical aspect of the theory of gravity not from meticulous observations of planetary motion, but from an apple he saw falling from a tree. 24 Popper s philosophy of science is, however, not a form of irrationalism, but critical rationalism. Popper argues that every theory should be subjected to a rigorous critical testing regime, aimed at attempting to falsify that theory. Critical rationalism is closely related to Popper s view on the problem of induction. His solution to the problem is, in short, that science actually does not use induction as a means to obtain new knowledge. As scientific theories are based on conjectures, scientists can only make deductions from the conjectured theories and test whether the predictions are valid by looking for possible refutations. Popper believes that Hume s refutation of inductive inference from a logical point of view is clear and conclusive, but he is dissatisfied with Hume s psychological explanation of induction in terms of custom and habit. Hume believes in the psychological power of induction; not as a logically valid procedure, but as a procedure which animals and people make use of. 25 The answers given by Hume to the logical and psychological problems of induction lead to the conclusion that inductive inferences are irrational. All knowledge, according to the Humean view, is mere irrational habit or custom and is rationally totally indefensible. Popper is not satisfied with this sceptical conclusion and believes that he has a solution to Hume s psychological problem. He reformulates Hume s problem by widening the scope from instances to laws and by including counterinstances (refutations). Hume s modified problem of induction now reads: Are we rationally justified in reasoning from instances, or from counterinstances, of which we have had experience to the truth or falsity of the corresponding laws or to instances of which we have had no experience? 21 Karl Popper, The problem of induction, in: M. Curd and J.A. Covers, editors, Philosophy of science: the central issues, (New York: W.W. Norton, 1998), pp. 429 430. 22 Albert Einstein, Mijn kijk op het leven (My view of the world), (Amsterdam: Corona, 1990), p. 143. 23 Ibid., p. 173. 24 John Conduitt, Memoir of Newton, http://www.newtonproject.ic.ak.uk/texts/ keynes129-a_n.html Accessed: 20 May 2005. 25 Popper (1989), p. 42. 6

Popper s answer to the problem is, as implied by Hume, that we are not justified in reasoning from an instance to the truth of the corresponding law. We are, however, justified in reasoning from a counterinstance to the falsity of the corresponding universal law. The acceptance of one counterinstance (the discovery of black swan) immediately falsifies the law (all swans are white). Induction may be logically invalid, but refutation or falsification is a logically valid way of arguing from a single counterinstance to the refutation of a corresponding law. Logic forces us to reject even the most successful law the moment we accept one single counterinstance. The result of Popper s argument is that all universal laws or theories forever remain conjectures until refuted by discovery of a counterinstance. 5 The Uniformity Principle Popper seems to have found a way out of the sceptical problems posed by Hume. The solution he proposes is, however, not what most philosophers would have hoped for, as his re-interpretation of Hume s problem of induction leads to the view that all knowledge is a temporary approximation. Although Hume s reasoning has left philosophy with a huge conundrum, he does not seem to be convinced himself of his conclusion that causation is a category of the mind: Thought may well depend on causes for its operation, but not causes on thought. This is to reverse the order of nature, and make that secondary, which is really primary. 26 Popper s reformulation of Hume s problem is an attempt to rescue a point of reference for scientific knowledge from the ashes of Hume s argument. Both Hume and Popper are both strong believers that the Uniformity Principle is actually true, although no justification, other than experience, can be given. It is a nearly generally agreed view that the problem of induction can and has to be solved only within the framework of an ontological reality and acceptance of the Uniformity Principle. 27 Acceptance of the Uniformity Principle is problematic and in recent times the principle has come under attack from philosophers and physicists. Ilya Prigogine regards the Uniformity Principle confirmed by the success of the theories of physics, but also as the most solid obstacle to understanding and justifying the nature of human freedom, creativity and responsibility. 28 He argues 26 Hume (2003), p. 107, Book I, Part III, Section XIV. 27 Dietrich (1995). 28 Ilya Prigogine, The end of certainty, (New York: The Free Press, 1997), p. 14. 7

that we need to go beyond the determinism of the Uniformity Principle and find a way to embrace indeterminism in physics. The Uniformity Principle allows prediction of future events, based on patterns from the past. The same principle also allows to postdict past events by looking at the current situation. The laws of physics, as they are based on the Uniformity Principle, also allow prediction and postdiction of events. In physics, the direction of time does not seem to matter. In everyday life, however time certainly seems to have a direction; we can t unstir a cup of tea to separate the milk from the tea and we always get older, but never any younger, and so forth. Nature involves both time-reversible and time-irreversible processes, but irreversible processes are the rule and the reversible the exception. 29 If Prigogine is right and time-irreversible processes are the rule, then the Uniformity Principle is not only uncertain, but actually wrong and can only be interpreted as a category of the mind. 6 The Success of Technology There does not seem to be any satisfactory solution to the difficulties Hume raised. Popper s theory is only a partial solution, as it presupposes the Uniformity Principle, which in turn can not be justified. Are we left with the world as an unpredictable chaos? Are we forced to admit that, in the words of punk singer Johnny Rotten: There is no solution to the problems, so enjoy the chaos? The apparent success of technology, however, seems to disprove the sceptical conclusions of Hume and Prigogine s call for indeterminism. We are surrounded by technology that validates the laws of physics which are all based on deterministic models of reality derived by inductive reasoning. We are left with a reality without logical justification. If there is no logical justification for scientific inferences we are forced to accept instrumentalist theories. In my work as a professional engineer I often say that there is nothing more practical than a good theory. Instrumentalism is, in this context, the view that concepts and theories are merely useful instruments whose worth is measured not by whether the concepts and theories correctly depict reality, but how effective they are in explaining and predicting phenomena. 30 Instrumentalism is not an answer to the logic problem of induction, as argued is section 3.2. Instrumentalism is a pragmatic theory that bypasses the metaphysical 29 Prigogine (1997), p. 18. 30 C. Widdershoven-Heerding, editor, Wetenschapsleer (Philosophy of science), (Heerlen, the Netherlands: Open Universiteit, 1995), p. 147. 8

problems of inductive reasoning. To the instrumentalist, inductive reasoning is a powerful tool to attempt to understand the reality we are presented with. References Conduitt, John, Memoir of Newton, http://www.newtonproject.ic.ak.uk/ texts/keynes129-a_n.html Accessed: 20 May 2005. Dietrich, Olaf, A constructivist approach to the problem of induction, Evolution and Cognition 1 (1995):2 http://www.vub.ac.be/clea/people/ dietrich/induction.html Accessed: 9 May 2005. Earman, John and Salmon, Wesley C., The confirmation of scientific hypotheses, in: Salmon, Merrilee H., editor, Introduction to the philosophy of science, (Prentice Hall, 1992), pp. 55 66, printed in Townsend (1998), p. 176 183. Einstein, Albert, Mijn kijk op het leven (My view of the world), (Amsterdam: Corona, 1990). Hume, David, An abstract of a book published; entitled a Treatise of Human Nature &c, (London, 1740) http://www.gale.com/eighteenthcentury/ Accessed: 13 may 2005, Eighteenth Century Collections Online, Document No. CW3318060774. Hume, David; Selby-Bigge, L.A., editor, An enquiry concerning the human understanding, and an enquiry concering the principles of morals, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1894). Hume, David; Wright, John P., Stecker, Robert, and Fuller, Gary, editors, A treatise of human nature, (London: Everyman, 2003). Klein, Jürgen, Francis Bacon, in: Zalta, Edward N., editor, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, (2004) http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/ fall2004/entries/francis-bacon/. Open Universiteit, De menselijke kennis en haar vijanden (Human knowledge and its enemies), (VHS, 1988), Interview with Karl Popper. Popper, Karl, The problem of induction, in: Curd, M. and Covers, J.A., editors, Philosophy of science: the central issues, (New York: W.W. Norton, 1998), pp. 426 432, Originally published in: The logic of scientific discovery. Popper, Karl R., Conjectures and refutations, 5th edition. (London: Routledge, 1989). Prigogine, Ilya, The end of certainty, (New York: The Free Press, 1997). 9

Russell, Bertrand, History of western philosophy, 2nd edition. (London: Routledge, 1961). Stove, Davide, Hume, probability and induction, in: Chappell, V.C., editor, Hume: A collection of essays, (1966). Townsend, Aubrey, editor, Origins of modern philosophy B, (Melbourne: Monash University, 1998). VOC Historical Society,Perth, Voyage to the South Land, http://www.voc. iinet.net.au/vlamingh.html Accessed: 10 May 2005. Widdershoven-Heerding, C., editor, Wetenschapsleer (Philosophy of science), (Heerlen, the Netherlands: Open Universiteit, 1995). 10