Handout 1: Arguments -- the basics because, since, given that, for because Given that Since for Because

Similar documents
24.09x Guide to Logic and Argumentation

Skim the Article to Find its Conclusion and Get a Sense of its Structure

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

Lecture 3 Arguments Jim Pryor What is an Argument? Jim Pryor Vocabulary Describing Arguments

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

PHILOSOPHY 102 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC PRACTICE EXAM 1. W# Section (10 or 11) 4. T F The statements that compose a disjunction are called conjuncts.

CRITICAL THINKING. Formal v Informal Fallacies

Practice Test Three Fall True or False True = A, False = B

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

Relevance. Premises are relevant to the conclusion when the truth of the premises provide some evidence that the conclusion is true

Practice Test Three Spring True or False True = A, False = B

Criticizing Arguments

Study Guides. Chapter 1 - Basic Training

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

FROM INQUIRY TO ACADEMIC WRITING CHAPTER 8 FROM ETHOS TO LOGOS: APPEALING TO YOUR READERS

CHAPTER THREE Philosophical Argument

What is an argument? PHIL 110. Is this an argument? Is this an argument? What about this? And what about this?

MCQ IN TRADITIONAL LOGIC. 1. Logic is the science of A) Thought. B) Beauty. C) Mind. D) Goodness

A Brief Introduction to Key Terms

A R G U M E N T S I N A C T I O N

1. To arrive at the truth we have to reason correctly. 2. Logic is the study of correct reasoning. B. DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE ARGUMENTS

Logic -type questions

Arguments. 1. using good premises (ones you have good reason to believe are both true and relevant to the issue at hand),

What is a logical argument? What is deductive reasoning? Fundamentals of Academic Writing

I. What is an Argument?

The antecendent always a expresses a sufficient condition for the consequent

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

Recall. Validity: If the premises are true the conclusion must be true. Soundness. Valid; and. Premises are true

Tutorial A03: Patterns of Valid Arguments By: Jonathan Chan

Logic Book Part 1! by Skylar Ruloff!

Directions: For Problems 1-10, determine whether the given statement is either True (A) or False (B).

In view of the fact that IN CLASS LOGIC EXERCISES

Introduction to Logic

ARGUMENTS. Arguments. arguments

Chapter 1. What is Philosophy? Thinking Philosophically About Life

PHIL2642 CRITICAL THINKING USYD NOTES PART 1: LECTURE NOTES

PLEASE DO NOT WRITE ON THIS QUIZ

Philosophical Arguments

SHORT ANSWER. Write the word or phrase that best completes each statement or answers the question.

Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic

Introduction to Logic

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

Introduction to Philosophy

Lecture 4 Good and Bad Arguments Jim Pryor Some Good and Bad Forms of Arguments

T. Parent. I shall explain these steps in turn. Let s consider the following passage to illustrate the process:

Topic III: Sexual Morality

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

PHI 244. Environmental Ethics. Introduction. Argument Worksheet. Argument Worksheet. Welcome to PHI 244, Environmental Ethics. About Stephen.

A short introduction to formal logic

Answers to Practice Problems 7.3

Overview of Today s Lecture

Academic argument does not mean conflict or competition; an argument is a set of reasons which support, or lead to, a conclusion.

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Session 10 INDUCTIVE REASONONING IN THE SCIENCES & EVERYDAY LIFE( PART 1)

Chapter 8 - Sentential Truth Tables and Argument Forms

Philosophical Methods Revised: August, 2018

Informalizing Formal Logic

Unit. Categorical Syllogism. What is a syllogism? Types of Syllogism

Part II: How to Evaluate Deductive Arguments

Reading Comprehension Fallacies in Reading

I'd Like to Have an Argument, Please.

Matthews Key for Informal Logic Exercises 1. Use these answers to grade and correct your homework assignment. A perfect score would be 100.

b) The meaning of "child" would need to be taken in the sense of age, as most people would find the idea of a young child going to jail as wrong.

Those who doubt the writing is from the autistic children themselves, lack compassion, and should stay the hell out of our lives!

Friday April 22, 2011 Schedule for the Day

Fallacies are deceptive errors of thinking.

5: Preliminaries to the Argument

Chapter 9- Sentential Proofs

2/21/2014. FOUR WAYS OF KNOWING (Justifiable True Belief) 1. Sensory input; 2. Authoritative knowledge; 3. Logic and reason; 4. Faith and intuition

Argumentation. 2. What should we consider when making (or testing) an argument?

Philosophy 12 Study Guide #4 Ch. 2, Sections IV.iii VI

HOW TO ANALYZE AN ARGUMENT

1 Chapter 6 (Part 2): Assessing Truth Claims

Thinking and Reasoning

The Philosopher s World Cup

Logical (formal) fallacies

Helpful Hints for doing Philosophy Papers (Spring 2000)

Logic. A Primer with Addendum

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

C. Problem set #1 due today, now, on the desk. B. More of an art than a science the key things are: 4.

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Artificial Intelligence: Valid Arguments and Proof Systems. Prof. Deepak Khemani. Department of Computer Science and Engineering

Chapter 1 Why Study Logic? Answers and Comments

Appendix: The Logic Behind the Inferential Test

Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe.

Video: How does understanding whether or not an argument is inductive or deductive help me?

Genuine dichotomies expressed using either/or statements are always true:

Conditionals II: no truth conditions?

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

ELEMENTS OF LOGIC. 1.1 What is Logic? Arguments and Propositions

Also, in Argument #1 (Lecture 11, Slide 11), the inference from steps 2 and 3 to 4 is stated as:

Norva Y S Lo Produced by Norva Y S Lo Edited by Andrew Brennan. Fallacies of Presumption, Ambiguity, and Part-Whole Relations

LOGIC. Inductive Reasoning. Wednesday, April 20, 16

Common Logical Fallacies

Fallacies. What this handout is about. Arguments. What are fallacies?

HANDBOOK. IV. Argument Construction Determine the Ultimate Conclusion Construct the Chain of Reasoning Communicate the Argument 13

Logic: A Brief Introduction. Ronald L. Hall, Stetson University

Test Item File. Full file at

LOGIC ANTHONY KAPOLKA FYF 101-9/3/2010

PHI Introduction Lecture 4. An Overview of the Two Branches of Logic

Transcription:

Handout 1: Arguments -- the basics It is useful to think of an argument as a list of sentences.[1] The last sentence is the conclusion, and the other sentences are the premises. Thus: (1) No professors are ignorant. All ignorant people are vain. No professors are vain. and: (2) All lions are fierce. Some lions do not drink coffee. Some creatures that drink coffee are not fierce. are both arguments. (These two examples are taken from Lewis Carroll, who was an amateur logician, as well as the author of Alice in Wonderland.) The readings will usually not contain arguments in this nice form. Rather, you will have to extract premises and conclusions from much more complex and lengthy passages of text. In doing this, it is helpful to look out for certain key words which often serve as indicators of ("flags" for) premises or conclusions. Some common premise-indicators are because, since, given that, for. These words usually come right before a premise. Examples of the use of such "flags" for premises: (3) Danish pastries should be renamed, because the Danish cartoonists committed blasphemy. (4) Given that euthanasia is a common medical practice, we might as well make it legal. (5) Since marijuana is a dangerous recreational drug, it should not be prescribed by doctors. (6) We must engage in affirmative action, for America is still a racist society. (7) Because gay marriage is a hotly contested issue in this country, nobody should force his opinion about it on anyone else. Some common conclusion-indicators are thus, therefore, hence, it follows that, so, consequently. These words usually come right before the conclusion of the argument. Examples of the use of such "flags" for conclusions: (8) Either Clinton lied about sex, or about whether he was alone with Monica, or about the meaning of 'alone'; so he lied about something. (9) Affirmative action violates the rights of white males to a fair shake;hence it is unjust. (10) It is always wrong to kill a human being, and a fetus is undoubtedly a human being. It follows that abortion is always wrong. (11) Scooter Libby is a man of impeccable integrity and would never lie. Consequently, he has been wrongly accused. (12) Tony Soprano is seeing a psychiatrist and so is not playing with a full deck. Thus, he won't make a good mob boss and should therefore be taken out. It is also helpful to use these premise- and conclusion-indicators in your own writing, to make the structure of your arguments clearer. Don't use them lightly, however: make sure they really are "flagging" either a premise or a conclusion of your argument, as appropriate. Anyone reading your paper is entitled to think that sentences preceded by because, etc., are premises, and that

sentences preceded by therefore, etc., are conclusions. Make sure they are, or you are misleading the reader. Definitions: Evaluating arguments (1) A conclusion is entailed by some premises just in case it is not possible for all the premises to be true and the conclusion false. Put another way, the conclusion follows from the premises just in case, necessarily, if the premises are all true, the conclusion is true. (2) An argument is valid just in case its conclusion is entailed by its premises. (An argument that is not valid is invalid.) Note that there are perfect good arguments (in the sense that believing that the premises are true gives you good reason to believe that the conclusion is true) that are nonetheless invalid. For example: (3) Past Congresses have always contained many adulterers. The current Congress contains some adulterers. However, the arguments that we will encounter in this course will be any good only if they are valid. So, the first thing you should ask yourself in evaluating an argument from the readings -- or one of your own -- is whether it is valid. Is it possible for the conclusion to be false and the premises true? Exercise: determine, for each of the two arguments from Lewis Carroll, and for each of the following arguments, whether it is valid or invalid. If the argument is invalid, explain why. (4) Clinton's troubles were caused either by a right-wing conspiracy, or by his own animal urges. They were caused by his animal urges. There was no right-wing conspiracy. (5) If Jessica Simpson is a space alien, then I'll eat my hat. Jessica Simpson is a space alien. I'll eat my hat. (6) All politicians enjoy cheating on their spouses. Some male politicians enjoy cheating on their spouses. (7) Abortion is morally wrong. Abortion is not a constitutional right. Abortion ought to be against the law. Sometimes an argument which is invalid as written can easily be "fixed up" so that it is valid and in line with what the proponent of the argument intended. The most common reason for this kind of "corrigible" invalidity is missing premises. Sometimes a writer does not state all of his or her premises explicitly, and this renders his or her argument invalid. In such cases we can make the argument valid by supplying an appropriate premise, supposing that the writer intended it to be a premise all along. You should become adept at filling in missing premises so that you can see the structure of an argument more clearly. Exercise: supply the missing premises to arguments (6) and (7) above, and to the following arguments: (8) If your mob connections are revealed, you'll lose your reputation as a man of integrity.

Your nomination to head up the department of homeland security will collapse. (9) Abortion involves terminating the existence of some organic matter. Abortion is always morally wrong. Note that sometimes a premise is left out because it is taken to be obvious, as in argument (6) above. However, sometimes the missing premise is contentious, as in (7) above. Sometimes, in fact, it is the most contentious premise of the argument, as in (9) above. Definition: (10) A deductive argument is sound just in case it is valid and all its premises are true. (An argument that is not sound is unsound.) Argument (5) above is an example of a valid argument which is unsound. Note the following fact, which is a consequence of the definitions of soundness and validity: (11) The conclusion of a sound argument is true. This fact has practical import. It means that if you read an article and disagree with the conclusion, the onus is on you to show why the argument is unsound. For (by (11)) if it were sound, the conclusion would be true. Therefore, if (according to you) the conclusion is false, the argument must be unsound. This means that either the conclusion does not actually follow from the premises -- in other words, there is a problem with the author's reasoning or logic -- or at least one of the premises is false. In this subject, it is never enough simply to say that you disagree with someone's position, or that his or her position is mistaken. If it is mistaken, there must be something wrong with the argument, and you need to say what it is. Soundness is thus the most important criterion in evaluating both arguments from the readings and your own arguments. After having identified the conclusion for which a writer is arguing, and the premises which he or she advances in support of that conclusion, you should attempt to determine whether the argument, thus reconstructed, is sound. And in making arguments of your own, you should always try to give a valid argument the premises of which are true, or at least defensible. Argument-forms and common flaws Here are some examples of valid forms of argument. Modus ponens. The general form of a modus ponens argument is given in (1). Two examples follow. (1) If P then Q P Q (2) If the NSA is listening to your phone conversations, then you are a terrorist. The NSA is listening to your phone conversations. You are a terrorist. (3) If affirmative action is an effective way of achieving greater equality, then it ought to be practiced. Affirmative action is an effective way of achieving greater equality.

Affirmative action ought to be practiced. Modus tollens. The general form of a modus tollens argument is given in (4). Two examples follow. (4) If P then Q. Not-Q. Not-P. (5) If Bush decides to attack Iran then Chirac will support him. Chirac will not support him. Bush will not decide to attack Iran. (6) If abortion in the ninth month of pregnancy is acceptable, then infanticide is acceptable. Infanticide is not acceptable. Abortion in the ninth month of pregnancy is not acceptable. Disjunctive syllogism. The general form of a disjunctive syllogism is given in (7a) and (7b). Two examples follow. (7a) (Either) P or Q Not-P Q (7b) (Either) P or Q Not-Q. P (8) Either Scooter is a liar, or else very forgetful. Scooter is not a liar. Scooter is very forgetful. (9) Either Carrie spends all her money on shoes or Samantha does. Samantha does not spend all her money on shoes. Carrie does. Categorical syllogism. Two general types of categorical syllogism are given in (10a) and (10b). Two examples follow. (10a) All Fs are G x is (an) F x is G (10b) All Fs are G. All Gs are H All Fs are H

(11) All theories are unsupported hypotheses. Evolution is a theory. Evolution is an unsupported hypothesis. (12) Abortion involves terminating the existence of organic matter. It is always morally wrong to terminate the existence of organic matter. Abortion is always morally wrong. Arguments can have various kinds of flaws: for example, invalidity, false premises, dialectical ineffectiveness. NB: these are quite different, and should not be confused -- false premises and failure to persuade an opponent are not logical flaws. Exercise: give an example of a dialectically ineffective argument (i.e. an argument that your imagined opponent will find unpersuasive) that is also sound. Some of these flaws have common labels, as follows. The fallacy of equivocation: using key terms in different senses in different parts of the argument. Begging the question (also known as a circular argument): assuming what you are trying to prove. We will seldom see really obvious cases of begging the question in the readings. What we may see is a weak form of begging the question, namely putting forward as a premise something so close to the conclusion that no one would believe the premise who didn't already believe the conclusion. This is an ineffective mode of argument, precisely because it does not persuade. Proving too much: an argument is said to prove too much if it appeals to a principle which has consequences that the formulator of the argument would not accept, or which are clearly erroneous. Example: no politician should be taken seriously if he used to smoke pot. Ad hominem arguments: an ad hominem argument involves a personal attack on one's opponent rather than a reasoned objection to his or her position or argument. Appeals to authority: in philosophy, there are no authorities. It is never acceptable to support a position simply by pointing out that someone we've read holds it. Descartes is on the philosophy All-Star team, but that doesn't mean that dualism is true. Appealing to supposed authorities in this way is the mirror image of an ad hominem argument. Straw man arguments: representing your opponent's position or argument unfairly so that it is easier to shoot down. In such cases, all you have shot down is a "straw man," not your actual opponent. [1] More exactly, sentences that are either true or false. Thus 'Shut the door!', and 'Is the door shut?', although perfectly acceptable sentences, cannot form part of an argument as explained here.