Nihilismus p. 1 v. 1

Similar documents
James Sire, The Universe Next Door: A Basic Worldview Catalog Zero Point: Nihilism

Existentialism. And the Absurd

EXISTENTIALISM. Wednesday, April 20, 16

Existentialism Definition - What is Existentialism philosophy?

Becoming More Authentic: The Positive Side of Existentialism

Introduction to Ethics Part 2: History of Ethics. SMSU Spring 2005 Professor Douglas F. Olena

VERIFICATION AND METAPHYSICS

Philosophy of Ethics Philosophy of Aesthetics. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

VOL. 1 ISSUE 12 MAY 2015 ISSN An International, Peer-Reviewed, Open Access, Monthly, Online Journal of English Language and Literature

What Is Existentialism? COPYRIGHTED MATERIAL. Chapter 1. In This Chapter

CHAPTER I INTRODUCTION. A. Research Background. being as opposed to society as a one organism (Macquarrie, 1973). Existentialism mainly finds

Fathers and Sons Reflective Statement and Written Assignment. Hermione Weasley. Candidate Language A: English HL.

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

Definition: The denial of the possibility of knowledge, philosophy, and value in anything.

You will be assigned a primary source reading that will address the following question from a particular perspective. What is the meaning of life?

Tu Quoque, Archbishop

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

R. M. Hare (1919 ) SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG. Definition of moral judgments. Prescriptivism

Christian scholars would all agree that their Christian faith ought to shape how

Ludwig Feuerbach The Essence of Christianity (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 10/23/13 9:10 AM. Section III: How do I know? Reading III.

The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World. In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages, Kripke expands upon a conclusion

Atheism From the University to Society. Edwin Chong. April 2, 2006

Class 23 - April 20 Plato, What is Right Conduct?

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

BIBLICAL INTEGRATION IN SCIENCE AND MATH. September 29m 2016

CHAPTER ONE What is Philosophy? What s In It For Me?

MAEG-01 June - Examination 2017 MA (Prev.) English Examination English Language Usage and Communication Skills Paper - MAEG-01

Communicating Christ in a Multicultural World

Journal Of Contemporary Trends In Business And Information Technology (JCTBIT) Vol.5, pp.1-6, December Existentialist s Model of Professionalism

Naturalism and is Opponents

EXAM PREP (Semester 2: 2018) Jules Khomo. Linguistic analysis is concerned with the following question:

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

LA Mission College Mark Pursley Fall 2016 Note:

JEAN-PAUL SATRE AND THE RESURGENCE OF EXISTENTIALISM

Subject: Biblical World Views #1 Title: Think Like Jesus Texts: Genesis 1:1; Hebrews 11:6, etc.

EXISTENTIALISM EXISTENTIALISM - METAPHYSICS EXISTENTIALISM - METAPHYSICS

DOES ETHICS NEED GOD?

Altruism. A selfless concern for other people purely for their own sake. Altruism is usually contrasted with selfishness or egoism in ethics.

I. THE PHILOSOPHY OF DIALOGUE A. Philosophy in General

Understanding the burning question of the 1940s and beyond

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

Morality Without God Rev. Amy Russell Unitarian Universalist Community Church of Glen Allen Sunday, February 7, 2016

Introduction to Kierkegaard and Existentialism

What is Atheism? How is Atheism Defined?: Who Are Atheists? What Do Atheists Believe?:

Running Head: ETHICAL BEHAVIOUR 1 ETHICAL BEHAVIOUR. Name: Institutional Affiliation: Date:

Nietzsche s Philosophy as Background to an Examination of Tolkien s The Lord of the Rings

V3301 Twentieth-Century Philosophy PHIL V TR 2:40pm-3:55pm- 516 Hamilton Hall - Fall Professor D. Sidorsky

Emotivism and its critics

Paradox and the Calling of the Christian Scholar

MORAL RELATIVISM. By: George Bassilios St Antonius Coptic Orthodox Church, San Francisco Bay Area

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

Topic no. 2: Immanuel Kant

Reply to Brooke Alan Trisel James Tartaglia *

Principles and Situations

Philosophy & Religion

By: Yusra Hashmi, Britney Laber, Shelby Nelson, Kirsten Ronning, and Julie Thamby

Russell: On Denoting

COPLESTON: Quite so, but I regard the metaphysical argument as probative, but there we differ.

Self-Fulfillment. Part 4 of 4 by Eddie Correia Presented to Unitarian Universalist Fellowship of the Rappahannock June 17, 2018

DALLAS BAPTIST UNIVERSITY THE ILLOGIC OF FAITH: FEAR AND TREMBLING IN LIGHT OF MODERNISM SUBMITTED TO THE GENTLE READER FOR SPRING CONFERENCE

Skepticism is True. Abraham Meidan

CHRISTIAN RESEARCH JOURNAL PHILOSOPHERS SERIES

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

Introduction to Existentialism

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 1

Morality, Suffering and Violence. Ross Arnold, Fall 2015 Lakeside institute of Theology

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

Philosophy Courses-1

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

MORAL LAW. Introduction:Most basic questions: - Epistemology- This area asks How do I. - Metaphysics- This area asks, What is real?

JESUS FIRST QUESTION KEY POINTS IN THIS LESSON YOU WILL STUDY THESE QUESTIONS:

out in his Three Dialogues and Principles of Human Knowledge, gives an argument specifically

Emotivism. Meta-ethical approaches

READING MY FAVORITE ATHEISTS: Ivan, Raskolnikov, and Kirilov

Comparative Philosophical Analysis on Man s Existential Purpose: Camus vs. Marcel

LA Mission College Mark Pursley Spring 2018 Note:

Kant and his Successors

Introduction to Philosophy

VIEWING PERSPECTIVES

Department of Philosophy. Module descriptions 2017/18. Level C (i.e. normally 1 st Yr.) Modules

A-LEVEL Religious Studies

Philosophical Review.

Reading Euthyphro Plato as a literary artist

Spirituality of Suffering Sermon by Blanca Rodriguez August 28, 2016 All Souls Church, NYC

Listening Guide. Worldview Basics. A Comparison of Major Worldviews. WE102 Lesson 02 of 05

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Reason 3: The Moral Argument

CONTENTS PREFACE

Ethical Theory for Catholic Professionals

What Should We Believe?

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

The Power of Myth A Conversation Between Joseph Campbell and Bill Moyers

Sometimes doing what is Right has No Right Answer: On Hilary Putnam s Pragmatism with Existential Choices

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

Philosophy Catalog. REQUIREMENTS FOR A MAJOR IN PHILOSOPHY: 9 courses (36 credits)

Outcomes Assessment of Oral Presentations in a Philosophy Course

CHECKING THE NEIGHBORHOOD: A REPLY TO DIPAOLO AND BEHRENDS ON PROMOTION

Transcription:

NIHILISM. The term "nihilism" appears to have been coined in Russia sometime in the second quarter of the nineteenth century. It was not, however, widely used until after the appearance of I van Turgenev's highly successful novel Fathers and Sons in the early 1860s. The central character, Bazarov, a young man under the influence of the "most advanced ideas" of his time, bore proudly what most other people of the same period called the bitter name of nihilist. Unlike such real-life counterparts as Dmitri Pisarev, Nikolai Dobrolyubov, and Nikolai Chernyshevski, who also bore the label, Bazarov's interests were largely apolitical; however, he shared with these historical personalities disdain for tradition and authority, great faith in reason, commitment to a materialist philosophy like that of Ludwig Buchner, and an ardent desire to see radical changes in contemporary society. An extreme statement by Pisarev of the nihilist position as it developed in the late 1850s and 1860s in Russia is frequently quoted: "Here is the ultimatum of our camp: what can be smashed should be smashed; what will stand the blow is good; what will fly into smithereens is rubbish; at any rate, hit out right and left-there will and can be no harm from it" (quoted in Avrahm Yarmolinsky, Road to Revolution, p. 120). Bazarov echoes this idea, though a bit feebly, when he accepts a description of nihilism as a matter of "just cursing." Use of the term spread rapidly throughout Europe and the Americas. As it did, the term lost most of its anarchistic and revolutionary flavor, ceasing to evoke the image of a political program or even an intellectual movement. It did not, however, gain in precision or clarity. On the one hand, the term is widely used to denote the doctrine that moral norms or standards cannot be justified by rational argument. On the other hand, it is widely used to denote a mood of despair over the emptiness or triviality of human existence. This double meaning appears to derive from the fact that the term was often employed in the nineteenth century by the religiously oriented as a club against atheists, atheists being regarded as ipso facto nihilists in both senses. The atheist, it was held, would not feel bound by moral norms; consequently, he would tend to be callous or selfish, even criminal. At the same time he would lose the sense that life has meaning and therefore tend toward despair and suicide. Atheism. There are many literary prototypes of the atheist- nihilist. The most famous are I van in Dostoyevsky's Brothers Karamazov and Kirilov in Dostoyevsky's The 051031 Nihilismus p. 1 v. 1

Possessed. It was into Ivan's mouth that Dostoyevsky put the words, "If God does not exist, everything is permitted." And Dostoyevsky made it clear that it was Ivan's atheism which led him to acquiesce to his father's murder. Kirilov was made to argue that if God does not exist, the most meaningful reality in life is individual freedom and that the supreme expression of individual freedom is suicide. Nietzsche was the' first great philosopher-and still the only one-to make extensive use of the term "nihilism." He was also one of the first atheists to dispute the existence of a necessary link between atheism and nihilism. He recognized, however, that as a matter of historical fact, atheism was ushering in an age of nihilism. "One interpretation of existence has been overthrown," Nietzsche said,..but since it was held to be the interpretation, it seems as though there were no meaning in existence at all, as though everything were in vain" (Complete Works, Edinburgh and London, 1901-1911, Vol. XIV, p. 480). Albert Camus later dealt with this historical fact at some length in The Rebel (1951). The tendency to associate nihilism with atheism continues to the present. It is to be found, for instance, in a work by Helmut Thielicke entitled Nihilism, which first appeared in 1950. During the course of the twentieth century, however, the image of the nihilist has changed, with a corresponding change in the analysis of nihilism's causes and consequences. Professor Hermann Wein of the University of Gottingen writes, for instance, that the members of the younger generation today tend to think of the nihilist not as a cynical or despairing atheist but as a robotlike conformist. For them nihilism is caused not so much by atheism as by industrialization and social pressures, and its typical consequences are not selfishness or suicide but indifference, ironical detachment, or sheer bafflement. The literary prototypes are not the romantic heroes of Dostoyevsky but the more prosaic and impersonal heroes of Robert Musil's Man Without Qualities (first volumes published 1931-1933) or Kafka's The Trial (1925). Moral skepticism. If by nihilism one means a disbelief in the possibility of justifying moral judgments in some rational way and if philosophers reflect the intellectual climate of the times in which they live, then our age is truly nihilistic. At no period in Western history, with the possible exception of the Hellenistic age, have so many philosophers regarded moral statements as somehow arbitrary. For many Continental philosophers, especially the atheistic existentialists, moral values are products of free 051031 Nihilismus p. 2 v. 2

choice-that is, of uncaused, unmotivated, and nonrational decisions. The most notable statement of this view is in Being and Nothingness (1943) by Jean-Paul Sartre. In England and America, on the other hand, most philosophers tend to the view known as emotivism, according to which moral statements are ultimately and essentially products of pure social conditioning or brute feeling. The most noted, though not the most extreme, representatives of this position are A. J. Ayer and Charles Stevenson. It is impossible to state here with reasonable detail and accuracy the positions so summarily described in the last paragraph, much less to discuss their logical merits. For an understanding of nihilism, however, it is important to note how these positions relate to the ideas of those to whom nihilism of this kind is anathema. As already indicated, the most vociferous antinihilists were originally theologians, like Dostoyevsky, who feared that disbelief in God would lead to selfishness and crime. If, they argued, there is no divine lawgiver, each man will tend to become a law unto himself. If God does not exist to choose for the individual, the individual will assume the former prerogative of God and choose for himself. For these antinihilists the principal enemy today would be Sartre. The later antinihilists, however, tend to save their fire for the emotivists, whom they accuse of sanctioning moral indifference and mindless conformity. If all moral codes are essentially matters of feeling and social pressure, then no one would be better or worse than another. The wise man, like the Sophists of Plato's day, would simply adjust as best he could to the code of the society in which he happened to be living. John Dewey's fervid insistence upon critical individual intelligence as the prime agent of social and moral reconstruction places him squarely in the second group of antinihilists. Whether belief in atheistic existentialism or emotivism does in fact have the kinds of consequences suggested above is not at issue here. The point is simply that antinihilists of the' older variety do not regard conventional morality, especially in its otherregarding aspects, as adequately justified unless it has a cosmic or divine sanction, whereas more contemporary antinihilists do not regard any moral code as adequately 'justified unless there is some standard or touchstone more universal than pure feeling or social pressure to which it may be shown to conform. The pertinent question here is whether the antinihilists have a good case for these views. It would appear that the demand for justification of conventional moral rules by 051031 Nihilismus p. 3 v. 3

appeal to a divine or cosmic power cannot be logically admitted without abandoning widespread and deeply felt notions about the nature of moral justification. If the higher power which presumably legitimizes our moral code is by definition good and just, an appeal to that power would involve us in a vicious circle. How would we know that that power was good and just unless there were some purely human ideas about the good and the just to which we felt entitled independently of that power's sanction? If, on the other hand, the presumed higher power is not by definition good or just, if, for instance, it were defined merely as a creator and sustainer of life, by what right could we appeal to it to legitimize our moral views? Might or power, even the power to create and sustain life, is not to be confused with right or legitimacy. The demand that moral codes be justified by more universal standards than pure feeling or social dictate is, on the contrary, much more consonant with widespread, intuitive notions about the nature of moral justification. If social pressure is taken as the touchstone of morality, we once again court a confusion between might and right; if feeling is taken as the touchstone, we must apparently abandon not only the notion of a universal morality, feelings being notoriously fluctuating and individual, but also the notion that one of the functions of morality is to refine, direct, and control individual feelings. It may, of course, be the case that there is no universal morality and that whatever power morality possesses must derive from individual feeling and social conditioning alone. It would be surprising, however, if even the emotivists did not experience a certain chagrin that the truth in ethical theory should be so contrary to human hopes. Meaninglessness of life. Passing to the second meaning of the term "nihilism," we find that the pertinent questions are less logical or technically philosophical than psychological or sociological. There are two questions here, corresponding to the two forms of antinihilism. Is it true that a loss of faith in God or cosmic purposes produces a sense of despair over the emptiness and triviality of life, consequently stimulating selfishness and callousness? Is it true that industrialization and conformist social pressures have trivialized life in a similar way, causing us to adopt an attitude of ironic detachment? A negative answer to these questions would appear to fly in the face of most contemporary social criticism and analysis as well as the testimony of most contemporary literature. 051031 Nihilismus p. 4 v. 4

It is doubtful, however, whether a simple yes would be a proper response to the first question. When it is assumed that man needs a sense of divine or cosmic purpose in order to lead a rich and morally wholesome life, one is generalizing far beyond the evidence. The most that the evidence can be made to support is that relatively large numbers of men in certain societies at certain times have felt this need. No one who has read, for instance, Tolstoy's account of his religious crisis in middle age could doubt the depth of his despair or the reality of his need for a vital relationship to an eternal being. One can reasonably doubt, however, whether that need and despair spring from universal and firmly rooted human aspirations. Some psychologists regard Tolstoy's conversion crisis as a symptom of involutional melancholia, and there are many who believe it to be a consequence of Tolstoy's social position as a member of Russia's decaying aristocracy. Bertrand Russell went through a similar crisis earlier in life. He not only survived that crisis without reverting to faith in God or cosmic purpose; he also survived it, as his essay "A Free Man's Worship" (1902) attests, by deliberately espousing a world outlook which emphasizes the finitude and cosmic isolation of mankind. And.no one who is familiar with the facts of his life would dare to suggest that the later Russell was less morally earnest than the young believer or less wholeheartedly and happily engaged in the process of living. Those who attribute the nihilistic malaise of our time to industrialization and conformity are less vulnerable to the charge of overgeneralization. This is not because they limit their analysis to a given historical epoch, for they, too, are making an implicit generalization about universal human needs. Their point is that all men need, if they are to be whole and healthy, the sense that they can by a unique and personal effort contribute to the social process and that society will appreciate and reward this individual effort. This generalization is less vulnerable than the first simply because there is more evidence for it. Novels and biographies, ethnographic reports and individual clinical histories, not to mention common-sense attitudes of most men in all societies at all historical periods, tend to support it. And the issue raised by nihilism in this sense of the term is one of the great unresolved political and social problems of the twentieth century. Whether philosophers in their professional capacity are competent to contribute to its solution is a question we shall not attempt to answer here. 051031 Nihilismus p. 5 v. 5