Wittgenstein and Derrida [Review]

Similar documents
Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Denis Seron. Review of: K. Mulligan, Wittgenstein et la philosophie austro-allemande (Paris: Vrin, 2012). Dialectica

3 Supplement. Robert Bernasconi

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition:

2 nd Edition : A Short Film Treatment

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Craig on the Experience of Tense

Process Thought and Bridge Building: A Response to Stephen K. White. Kevin Schilbrack

Consciousness might be defined as the perceiver of mental phenomena. We might say that there are no differences between one perceiver and another, as

What Happens When Wittgenstein Asks "What Happens When...?"

At the Frontiers of Reality

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

MODELS CLARIFIED: RESPONDING TO LANGDON GILKEY. by David E. Klemm and William H. Klink

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Heidegger Introduction

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

John Haugeland. Dasein Disclosed: John Haugeland s Heidegger. Edited by Joseph Rouse. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2013.

Law as a Social Fact: A Reply to Professor Martinez

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

Citation Philosophy and Psychology (2009): 1.

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT FALL SEMESTER 2009 COURSE OFFERINGS

Affirmative Judgments: The Sabbath of Deconstruction

International Phenomenological Society

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

Ryle on Systematically Misleading Expresssions

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

The Ten Categories of Being. The Primacy of Substance

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Reality. Abstract. Keywords: reality, meaning, realism, transcendence, context

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

The title of this collection of essays is a question that I expect many professional philosophers have

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

The Supplement of Copula

Nietzsche's Graffito: A Reading of The Antichrist

Aboutness and Justification

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

On Interpretation. Section 1. Aristotle Translated by E. M. Edghill. Part 1

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

BonJour Against Materialism. Just an intellectual bandwagon?

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

How Subjective Fact Ties Language to Reality

PHIL 4242 German Idealism 德意志觀念論 Fall 2016 Professor Gregory S. Moss

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Nagel, Naturalism and Theism. Todd Moody. (Saint Joseph s University, Philadelphia)

The SAT Essay: An Argument-Centered Strategy

Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge Gracia's proposal

Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard

Phenomenology and Metaphysical Realism 1. Robert D. Stolorow. Abstract: This article examines the relationship between totalitarianism and the

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

DESCARTES ONTOLOGICAL PROOF: AN INTERPRETATION AND DEFENSE

Wittgenstein on forms of life: a short introduction

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

The Development of Laws of Formal Logic of Aristotle

THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

PAGE(S) WHERE TAUGHT (If submission is not text, cite appropriate resource(s))

A CRITIQUE OF THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. A Paper. Presented to. Dr. Douglas Blount. Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary. In Partial Fulfillment

PART FOUR: CATHOLIC HERMENEUTICS

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

Edmund Husserl s Transcendental Phenomenology by Wendell Allan A. Marinay

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Humean Supervenience: Lewis (1986, Introduction) 7 October 2010: J. Butterfield

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Well-Being, Disability, and the Mere-Difference Thesis. Jennifer Hawkins Duke University

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

Introduction to Philosophy

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

To Provoke or to Encourage? - Combining Both within the Same Methodology

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Chapter Six. Putnam's Anti-Realism

Intro to Ground. 1. The idea of ground. 2. Relata. are facts): F 1. More-or-less equivalent phrases (where F 1. and F 2. depends upon F 2 F 2

Different kinds of naturalistic explanations of linguistic behaviour

Is the Skeptical Attitude the Attitude of a Skeptic?

Louisiana Law Review. Cheney C. Joseph Jr. Louisiana State University Law Center. Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue Repository Citation

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Reply to Florio and Shapiro

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 5

John D. Caputo s book is one in a new series from Penguin called Philosophy in

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

BENJAMIN R. BARBER. Radical Excess & Post-Modernism Presentation By Benedetta Barnabo Cachola

John Buridan on Essence and Existence

The Qualiafications (or Lack Thereof) of Epiphenomenal Qualia

Retrieving Realism PDF

Every simple idea has a simple impression, which resembles it; and every simple impression a correspondent idea

Realism and instrumentalism

Anaphoric Deflationism: Truth and Reference

Nathan Oaklander IS THERE A DIFFERENCE BETWEEN ABSOLUTE AND RELATIVE SPACE?

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Why Computers are not Intelligent: An Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Knowledge and True Opinion in Plato s Meno

Summary of Sensorama: A Phenomenalist Analysis of Spacetime and Its Contents

UNIVERSITY OF WATERLOO DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY PHILOSOPHY 110A,

Paper #1: Maria tegui & The Problem of the Indian

The New Wittgenstein, ed. Alice Crary and Rupert Read, London and New York, 2000, pp. v + 403, no price.

Review of Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning: The Posterior Analytics by David Bronstein

Kripke s Naming and Necessity. The Causal Picture of Reference

Transcription:

Trinity University Digital Commons @ Trinity English Faculty Research English Department 4-1986 Wittgenstein and Derrida [Review] Michael Fischer Trinity University, mfischer@trinity.edu Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.trinity.edu/eng_faculty Part of the English Language and Literature Commons Repository Citation Fischer, M. (1986). [Review of the book Wittgenstein and Derrida, by H. Staten]. Philosophy and Literature, 10, 93-97. doi: 10.1353/ phl.1986.0019 This Book Review is brought to you for free and open access by the English Department at Digital Commons @ Trinity. It has been accepted for inclusion in English Faculty Research by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Trinity. For more information, please contact jcostanz@trinity.edu.

Critical Discussion Wittgenstein and Derrida, by Henry Staten; xxviii & 182 pp. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1984, $19.95. Discussed by Michael Fischer Wittgenstein and Derrida, the subjects of Henry Staten's important new book, have met before in contemporary literary theory, usually, however, as enemies or at least as philosophers with antithetical approaches to language. In several articles and at greater length in Act and Quality (1981), Charles Altieri, for example, has found in Wittgenstein a powerful challenge to Derridean literary theory, while Christopher Norris in The Deconstructive Turn (1983) has argued that Wittgenstein's writings are infected with the skeptical doubts that they supposedly cure. Unlike these critics, Staten proposes allying Wittgenstein with Derrida, an effort that depends on contesting what I would call, following Staten, the "communitarian" or "therapeutic" reading of Wittgenstein and the "terrorist" or "nihilist" reading of Derrida. While Staten complicates these familiar readings, he does not bring about the realignment that he seeks. Even after his painstaking work, the Derridean notions that he grafts onto Wittgenstein still seem out of place. Staten sees Derrida as a critic of a metaphysical tradition inaugurated by the Greeks and extended by such modern philosophers as Husserl. Much of Staten's introduction ("From Form to Différance"), first chapter ("The Opening of Deconstruction in the Text of Phenomenology"), and concluding chapters (grouped under the heading "The Law of Identity and the Law of Contamination") review Derrida's by now familiar deconstructive critique, sympathetically going over such terms as spacing, trace, iterability, and différance. As an explicator of Derrida, Staten can be 93

94Philosophy and Literature repetitious, especially toward the end of the book. And he can be unfair to some of Derrida's critics, especially John Searle, whose frequently discussed response to "Signature Event Context" seems to Staten not simply "vacuous" but lazy: "But no matter how traditional or well-entrenched die view, it remains that Derrida has worked out a critique and an alternate structure that he claims has a greater range and power, and it is easier to reassert the canonical concepts he criticizes, as Searle has done, in total ignorance of the full range of die conceptual structure Derrida has worked out as its replacement, than it is to master his arguments and his new logic and then to show where they fail" (p. 127). (In a similarly irritated tone, Staten rebukes Searle's essay "The Logical Structure of Fictional Discourse" for its "absurd posturing.") Dividing the world between the hard-working critics who agree with Derrida (thereby demonstrating that they understand him) and the indolent critics of deconstruction who more or less naively reassert what Derrida criticizes has reduced the debate on deconstruction to an often boring shouting match. Finally, in writing about deconstruction, Staten adopts its worst stylistic traits: ungainly verbs ("separate off" instead of separate, "open out" instead of "open," "normed," and "unlids" are only a few examples); labyrinthine sentences ("The iterability of a code ruptures its authority because it makes it essentially permeable to the deformations of context and yet makes it independent of the power of any given context to determine its meaning once and for all, because the sign carries an irreducible structure that will not let itself be absorbed into a present intention that would fix it in relation to an intentionally totalizable present context" [p. 123] is a mild example); and Francophile idioms (e.g., "To think an essential law of contingency, as Derrida does, is to generalize as a 'grammatical rule' the principles of the kind of critique diat Wittgenstein here instantiates" [p. 18]). These shortcomings, however, are the other side of Staten's strengths, in particular his enthusiasm for the ideas he is discussing and his refusal to simplify complex texts. His patient, detailed treatment of Speech and Phenomena, a work often passed over by literary critics, is especially good. Instead of setting up Husserl as a straw man whom Derrida can easily knock down, Staten shows that rigorously working through Husserl's work is a precondition for deconstructing it. His evenhanded commentary persuades me not only diat Derrida is a careful reader of Husserl but that Husserl may have been right in thinking that phenomenology completes die project begun by Greek philosophy. As mentioned earlier, in order to align Derrida widi Wittgenstein, Staten has to overturn the still popular image of Derrida as a freewheeling

Michael Fischer95 anarchist. Staten's commentary accordingly proceeds along the following lines: (1) According to Staten, Derrida questions such supposedly metaphysical notions as identity, completeness, "object-talk," intention, wholeness, seriousness, order, reference, essence, unity, presence, and consciousness. (2) But, while Derrida questions these terms, he is not refuting, destroying, or denying them (as many opponents of deconstruction have charged). (3) Instead, Derrida is merely (or only) modulating, resituating, displacing, suspending, unsettling, or complicating these terms in order to release the presumably exciting new possibilities philosophers since Plato have repressed. In brief, for Staten "it is not a question of giving up idealization [or metaphysics], but of modulating it, of allowing it to open out onto some possibilities that have not been conceivable under the old formulas" (p. 24). (See also pp. 47-48, 152, 155, among many other references tiiat I might cite.) This is a sophisticated reading of Derrida, which is not to say that it is free of problems. I would argue that Derridean critics cannot have it botii ways: the same argument that belitdes the fear of antideconstructionists (that chaos has come again) also undermines the hope of some prodeconstructionists (diat significant change is about to occur). In the scheme that I have just oudined, the dismissive, nothing-to-worry-about tone of step (2) defuses die liberationist, new-age-about-to-dawn rhetoric of step (3): hence the irredeemable vagueness of the possibilities that Staten celebrates.1 I am less interested here in the implications of Staten's approach to Derrida dian I am in die problems it poses for his attempt to group Derrida with Wittgenstein. To bring out Wittgenstein's resemblance to Derrida, Staten has to chip away at die familiar image of Wittgenstein as a dierapist who answers philosophical questions by appealing to shared forms of life or ordinary language-games, where philosophical concerns presumably never arise. Against diis view, Staten points out in his second chapter ("Wittgenstein Deconstructs") that the rules of these games are not inflexible guidelines forever ruling out change, variation, and uncertainty. In Wittgenstein, Staten remarks, we follow these rules like "a blind man feeling his way with his stick... constrained by die accidental [as opposed to the essential or ontological] at every turn" (p. 94). The absence of any firm boundary around our concepts exposes them to endless probing, "since it is impossible to tell in advance where this questioning should stop" (p. 158), where seriousness, for example, turns into nonsense. Staten is right to suggest that Wittgenstein and Derrida thus overlap in challenging the rigidity, or what Staten wants to call die "superhardness,"

96Philosophy and Literature of identity, essence, and the other "metaphysical" terms mentioned earlier. Nevertheless, from this starting point it seems to me that Derrida and Wittgenstein take different paths. Derrida, as Staten astutely reads him, speaks of contaminating or infecting metaphysical categories with the impurities that diey try to exclude. From Derrida's point of view, for instance, "'Repeatability,' as the condition for the existence of all idealities, whether they are the 'senses' or real or ideal objects, turns out to infect the entire domain of presence" (p. 50). (See also pp. 52, 63, and 84 for much the same metaphor.) Similarly, perforating the boundaries of the self allows (or forces) it to be "inimitably torn and carried away into an illimitable spread of new contexts" (p. 147). On the way to selfhood, in this view, we "fall" into a "perverse activity of invention, of fictionalization, Erdichtung" and disintegration that leaves us only with "accidental transformations of related assemblages of inessentials" (pp. 85-86). In diese deflating comments, Derrida (or Staten) is not so much bringing us down to earth as rubbing our noses in it, as in something unsavory. For Wittgenstein, instead of dispersing or scattering the self, the allegedly perverse activity described by Staten constitutes the self. Invention and so on characterize how humans acquire their identity, not how they lose it. I would make much the same response to the other examples taken by Staten from the Investigations. Reading, for instance, is not infected but shaped by "what is not reading" (pp. 83-84). Similarly, when we extend a mathematical series, learn a language, bring words home, or follow a rule, our stumbling describes how we carry on instead of annulling our progress. In each case Wittgenstein uses contingency, variability, and temporality not to sully traditional philosophical categories but to humanize them. Derrida's demystification-with-a-vengeance thus gives way to a probing that reaches bedrock in what we (humans) do (Philosophical Investigations, 217). I do not want to exaggerate die neatness of this resolution, as if Wittgenstein had in mind comfortably setding down and not the hard, frustrating work of digging until, as he says, "the spade is turned." Like Derrida, Wittgenstein is always wary of the possibility of dogmatism, of our confusing getting tired with reaching bedrock. Even so, from Wittgenstein's point of view, digging can arrive at firm ground as well as break it up. Giving grounds like testing, explaining, teaching, and reading thus comes to an end somewhere but that end is what Wittgenstein calls in On Certainty "an ungrounded way of acting" ( 110). As Stanley Cavell has put it in "The Availability of Wittgenstein's Later Philosophy,"

Michael Fischer97 We learn and teach words in certain contexts, and then we are expected, and expect others, to be able to project them into further contexts. Nothing insures that this projection will take place (in particular, not the grasping of universale nor the grasping of books of rules), just as nothing insures that we will make, and understand, the same projections. That on the whole we do is a matter of our sharing routes of interest and feeling, modes of response, senses of humor and of significance and of fulfillment, of what is outrageous, of what is similar to what else, what a rebuke, what forgiveness, of when an utterance is an assertion, when an appeal, when an explanation all the whirl of organism Wittgenstein calls "forms of life." Human speech and activity, sanity and community, rest upon nothing more, but nothing less, than this.2 The "nothing more" in this formulation always provides an opening for skepticism, the "nodiing less" a way of containing, though never eliminating, skeptical doubt. While Staten recognizes some differences between Wittgenstein and Derrida, he minimizes them, only belatedly admitting in his conclusion that "the deconstructive moment of Wittgenstein's writing is not the whole story" (p. 156). I agree with diis concession, tiiough in my view it strains the alliance that Staten has been trying to forge. In calling Wittgenstein's later work "consistently deconstructive" (p. xvi), Staten properly emphasizes Wittgenstein's interrogating the invariable essences and fixed rules that have held traditional philosophy and some of Derrida's critics captive. But Staten loses sight of the constructive lesson that Wittgenstein went on to affirm: "essence is expressed by grammar," not perverted by it (Investigations, 371). University of New Mexico 1. I develop this argument at much greater length in my Does Deconstruction Make Any Difference? (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1985), Chapters 5 and 6. 2.Stanley Cavell, "The Availability of Wittgenstein's Later Philosophy," Must We Mean What We Say? (1969; rpt. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1976), p. 52.