Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification?

Similar documents
FOUNDATIONALISM AND ARBITRARINESS

Finite Reasons without Foundations

Epistemic Circularity and Common Sense: A Reply to Reed

Skepticism and Internalism

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

I guess I m just a good-old-fashioned internalist. A prominent position in philosophy of religion today is that religious experience can

Against Phenomenal Conservatism

THREE ARGUMENTS AGAINST FOUNDATIONALISM: ARBITRARINESS, EPISTEMIC REGRESS, AND EXISTENTIAL SUPPORT

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

foundationalism and coherentism are responses to it. I will then prove that, although

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Is There Immediate Justification?

I assume some of our justification is immediate. (Plausible examples: That is experienced, I am aware of something, 2 > 0, There is light ahead.

Infinitism Is the Solution to the

Acquaintance and assurance

Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason

ABSTRACT: In this paper, I argue that Phenomenal Conservatism (PC) is not superior to

Three Arguments Against Foundationalism: Arbitrariness, Epistemic Regress, and Existential Support

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

Internalism and Properly Basic Belief. Matthew Davidson, CSUSB Gordon Barnes, SUNY-Brockport

PHENOMENAL CONSERVATISM, JUSTIFICATION, AND SELF-DEFEAT

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

INTRODUCTION: EPISTEMIC COHERENTISM

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

DEFENDING KLEIN ON CLOSURE AND SKEPTICISM

ACQUAINTANCE AND THE PROBLEM OF THE SPECKLED HEN

SCHAFFER S DEMON NATHAN BALLANTYNE AND IAN EVANS

THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Externalism and Skepticism

Phenomenal Conservatism and the Internalist Intuition

Against Coherence: Truth, Probability, and Justification. Erik J. Olsson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xiii, 232.

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

5 A Modal Version of the

Philosophical reflection about what we call knowledge has a natural starting point in the

Arbitrary Foundations? On Klein s Objection to Foundationalism

Pollock and Sturgeon on defeaters

Epistemic Consequentialism, Truth Fairies and Worse Fairies

COMMONSENSE NATURALISM * Michael Bergmann

Phenomenal Conservatism and the Demand for Metajustification *

PHIL 3140: Epistemology

CARTESIANISM, NEO-REIDIANISM, AND THE A PRIORI: REPLY TO PUST

McDowell and the New Evil Genius

The modal status of materialism

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

RATIONALITY AND THEISTIC BELIEF, by Mark S. McLeod. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, Pp. xiv and 260. $37.50 (cloth).

The Many Problems of Memory Knowledge (Short Version)

Small Stakes Give You the Blues: The Skeptical Costs of Pragmatic Encroachment

Moore s paradoxes, Evans s principle and self-knowledge

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Epistemological Externalism and the Project of Traditional Epistemology. Contemporary philosophers still haven't come to terms with the project of

Review of Steven D. Hales Book: Relativism and the Foundations of Philosophy

PHILOSOPHY EPISTEMOLOGY ESSAY TOPICS AND INSTRUCTIONS

Knowledge and its Limits, by Timothy Williamson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xi

What Should We Believe?

Goldman on Knowledge as True Belief. Alvin Goldman (2002a, 183) distinguishes the following four putative uses or senses of

AGENT CAUSATION AND RESPONSIBILITY: A REPLY TO FLINT

Shieva Kleinschmidt [This is a draft I completed while at Rutgers. Please do not cite without permission.] Conditional Desires.

Foundations and Coherence Michael Huemer

Content Externalism and the Internalism/ Externalism Debate in Justification Theory

Basic Knowledge and the Problem of Easy Knowledge (Rough Draft-notes incomplete not for quotation) Stewart Cohen

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

Reliabilism: Holistic or Simple?

Philosophy of Religion 21: (1987).,, 9 Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht - Printed in the Nethenanas

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

What should I believe? Only what I have evidence for.

Phil Notes #9: The Infinite Regress Problem

STEWART COHEN AND THE CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives

Inferential Evidence. Jeff Dunn. The Evidence Question: When, and under what conditions does an agent. have proposition E as evidence (at t)?

Markie, Speckles, and Classical Foundationalism

Objections to the two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind

What God Could Have Made

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

STUBBORN SYSTEMS: TWO NEW MULTIPLE COHERENT SYSTEMS OBJECTIONS FOR COHERENTIST MORAL REALISM. A Thesis ROSS T. COLEBROOK

The Paradox of the Question

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Do we have knowledge of the external world?

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya

The cosmological argument (continued)

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

CAN EMPIRICAL KNOWLEDGE HAVE A FOUNDATION?

4AANB007 - Epistemology I Syllabus Academic year 2014/15

Achieving epistemic descent

Nozick and Scepticism (Weekly supervision essay; written February 16 th 2005)

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility

Warrant: The Current Debate

Common Sense: A Contemporary Defense By Noah Lemos Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. xvi

CURRICULUM VITAE MICHAEL BERGMANN (May 2018) Department of Philosophy (765) N. University St.

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

A Priori Skepticism and the KK Thesis

SELLARS AND SOCRATES: AN INVESTIGATION OF THE SELLARS PROBLEM FOR A SOCRATIC EPISTEMOLOGY

Phenomenal Conservatism and Skeptical Theism

Transcription:

Philos Stud (2007) 134:19 24 DOI 10.1007/s11098-006-9016-5 ORIGINAL PAPER Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification? Michael Bergmann Published online: 7 March 2007 Ó Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2007 Abstract This paper is a response to Peter Klein s Human Knowledge and the Infinite Progress of Reasoning (also in this issue of this journal). After briefly discussing what Klein says about the requirement, for doxastic justification, that a belief be formed in the right way, I ll make the following three points: Klein s solution to the regress problem isn t an infinitist solution, Klein s position on doxastic justification faces a troubling dilemma, and Klein s objection to foundationalism fails. Keywords infinitism Æ foundationalism Peter Klein deserves the gratitude and respect of the philosophical community for making us work so hard to defend our dismissal of infinitism a view that many thought was obviously false. He still hasn t managed to shake my conviction that infinitism is a mistake though he has certainly demonstrated that it isn t an easy matter to refute a canny defender of it. In this paper, I will argue not only that his latest attempt to defend infinitism fails to defend the conclusion he arrives at but also that the conclusion he arrives at isn t infinitism. I confess that I ve never been much interested in propositional justification. Insofar as I ve been interested in epistemic justification, it s doxastic justification that I care about. There s wide agreement between externalists and internalists and between skeptics and nonskeptics that knowledge requires doxastically justified belief. There s less agreement about whether propositional justification is required or at least about whether it s worth mentioning in an analysis of knowledge. Moreover, as Klein himself points out (in the Section Infinitism is the only alternative that can solve the regress problem of his 2006), the regress problem is concerned not with propositional justification but with doxastic justification. Of course, this doesn t show that one shouldn t be interested in propositional justification. I mention these considerations only to explain why I care about doxastic justification and why I ll be ignoring propositional justification in these comments. M. Bergmann (&) Purdue University, BRNG Hall, West Lafayette, IN 47906, USA e-mail: bergmann@purdue.edu

20 Philos Stud (2007) 134:19 24 In what follows, I ll focus first on what Klein says about the requirement, for doxastic justification, that a belief be formed in the right way. Then I ll make the following three points: (a) Klein s solution to the regress problem isn t an infinitist solution; (b) Klein s position on doxastic justification faces a troubling dilemma; and (c) Klein s objection to foundationalism fails. Doxastic justification and the basing requirement Klein says in the Section Propositional and doxastic justification of his 2006 that a person s belief is doxastically justified only if it is held in an epistemically responsible manner that is, only if the belief is formed in the right way or held for the right reasons. I have two complaints related to this point. The first has to do with what Klein avoids saying: he seems to resist saying that the belief must be properly based and he clearly resists saying that it must be caused in the right way. But I don t see any good reason for him to resist either claim. Klein admits that a belief s doxastic justification has to do with the manner in which it is held or formed. And he says that it must be held for the right reasons. I take it then that he is requiring, for a belief B s doxastic justification, that B be held because of some adequate reason the person has for it. But this is just to agree that it must be properly based on some adequate reason the person has for it. Is there a causal element to this basing? This isn t the place for a full-fledged discussion of that point. But, for the record, I ll just note that I have yet to see an example of a belief that is plausibly thought to be justified in virtue of being based on something, X, even though X isn t a causal contributor to the belief. 1 My second complaint in connection with Klein s the Section Propositional and doxastic justification discussion of the basing requirement on doxastic justification is that he later seems to contradict that discussion. In the Section Propositional and doxastic justification, he makes it clear that a belief is doxastically justified only if it is formed or held in the right way for the right reasons. Yet later, in the Section Further clarification and defense of infinitism, he speaks of what:... lies at the heart of the infinitist s requirement for doxastic justification, namely that we be able to produce reasons for our beliefs. The issue is not what causes our beliefs; but rather whether we can cite a reason for our beliefs. 2 The point here seems to be that doxastic justification requires not that our beliefs be caused in the right way but that we be able to cite a reason for our beliefs. In what sense must we be able to do this? Klein concludes that infinitists can reasonably say that having easy (physical) access to an ordinary encyclopedia containing adequate evidence for p, is sufficient for being able to cite a reason for believing p. But this is a 1 A priori beliefs in necessary mathematical truths don t provide obvious examples of the sort I say I can t find. It is sometimes pointed out that mathematical beliefs are about the abstract realm of numbers and that things in that realm are causally inert, so that a priori mathematical beliefs can t be causally based on them. But according to what I take to be the usual understanding of belief grounds (the things on which beliefs are based), they are other mental states of the subject. So an a priori mathematical belief is based on, for example, a mental state such as the seeming obviousness of its content, not on any abstract item in the realm of numbers. And this seeming obviousness is itself a mental state that can enter into causal relations. 2 See the Section Further clarification and defense of infinitism, question (iii) of Klein (2006).

Philos Stud (2007) 134:19 24 21 far cry from what he initially said about doxastic justification. For clearly, the fact that that person has an encyclopedia in the next room containing adequate evidence for p, is consistent with that person forming or holding her belief that p in an epistemically irresponsible manner, in the wrong way and for the wrong reasons. 3 Contrary to what Klein says, therefore, when it comes to doxastic justification, the issue is not whether there are easily available reasons we could cite; the issue is what our beliefs are in fact based on. Klein s solution to the regress problem Let s turn now to an important problem related to doxastic justification: the epistemic regress problem. Consider the following reductio version of the regress argument for the foundationalist thesis that our beliefs can be noninferentially (doxastically) justified: 1. A belief of ours can be justified only if it is inferentially justified. [assume for reductio] 2. A belief of ours can be inferentially justified only if the belief from which it is inferred is a justified belief. 3. Therefore, either our beliefs can be justified via circular reasoning or they can be justified via infinite chains of reasoning or it isn t possible for our beliefs to be justified. [from 1 and 2] 4. Our beliefs can t be justified via circular reasoning. 5. Our beliefs can t be justified via infinite chains of reasoning. 6. It is possible for our beliefs to be justified. 7. Therefore, 3 is false. [from 4, 5, and 6] 8. 3 is both true and false. [from 3 and 7] 9. Therefore, 1 is false (i.e., our beliefs can noninferentially justified). [by reductio, from 1 to 8] The fact that this argument is valid and has only four premises makes it clear that its foundationalist conclusion can be rejected in the following four ways: (i) The Unjustified Foundations View: our beliefs can be inferentially justified even if the beliefs from which they are inferred are unjustified (so premise 2 is false). (ii) Linear coherentism: our beliefs can be justified via circular reasoning (so premise 4 is false). 4 (iii) Infinitism: our beliefs can be justified via an infinite chain of reasoning (so premise 5 is false). (iv) Radical Skepticism: it s impossible for our beliefs to be justified (so premise 6 is false) 3 Klein also requires that the subject is such that she would check the encyclopedia for this evidence were doing so required in the context. But the satisfaction of that further condition (i.e., being such that she would do such checking) is even when combined with the satisfaction of the easy access requirement also consistent with the person forming or holding her belief that p in an epistemically irresponsible manner, in the wrong way and for the wrong reasons. 4 This differs from the holistic coherentist position which accepts the foundationalist thesis. According to holistic coherentists, a belief can be (doxastically) justified in virtue of being a member of a coherent set of beliefs, even if it isn t inferred from or based on any of those other beliefs. See Plantinga s (1993, ch. 4) for further discussion of how coherentists who reject circular reasoning are a species of foundationalists.

22 Philos Stud (2007) 134:19 24 Given that Klein recognizes that the regress problem has to do with doxastic justification and that his stated purpose (in the opening sentence of his 2006) is to explain how infinitism solves this problem, one would expect him to endorse option (iii), which denies premise 5. But what we in fact find is that his solution to the regress problem is to endorse option (i), which rejects premise 2. 5 According to Klein, the infinitist thinks that S s belief that p is doxastically justified if and only if S has engaged in tracing the reasons in virtue of which the proposition p is justified far enough forward to satisfy the contextually determined requirements. 6 As I understand Klein s view here, he is saying there is or could be some context C in which a person S holds a belief, B1, and she bases B1 on (holds it because of, infers it from) her further belief, B2. Her belief B2 is based on her belief B3 and so on down to B10, her belief on which she bases her belief B9. In context C, by tracing her reasons for B1 this far, S has done enough to satisfy the contextually determined requirements for B1 s doxastic justification. 7 In order to reject the foundationalist solution to the regress problem, Klein must endorse the following view: K1: For a belief B to be doxastically justified, it must be based on some other belief. From this we may conclude that since B10 in the scenario described above isn t based on some other belief, belief B10 isn t justified. Now suppose Klein combined K1 with: K2: A belief can be doxastically justified by being based on some other belief only if that other belief is itself doxastically justified. From this it would follow that B9 in the above scenario isn t justified, since B9 is inferred from B10, which isn t justified. But then B8 wouldn t be justified either, and so on right down to B1. Since that clearly conflicts with Klein s description of the scenario, he must reject K2. And to reject K2 is to deny premise 2 from the regress argument given earlier. It s to endorse the unjustified foundations view. Hence, Klein s solution to the regress problem is not an infinitist solution. A dilemma for Klein Klein must either accept or reject K2. Suppose he rejects it, as he seems to in his 2006. Then he endorses the unjustified foundations view. One problem with embracing this horn of the dilemma is that, as I just noted above, it doesn t provide the infinitist solution to the regress problem that Klein promised to explain. But he could just take that promise back and acknowledge that his solution to the regress problem appeals to the unjustified foundations view. However, this isn t the most 5 In fact, his position is a contextualist version of the unjustified foundations view. This contextualism isn t the recently discussed variety defended by Lewis (1996) and DeRose (1992). Rather, it s more like the old-fashioned sort of contextualism defended by Annis (1978). 6 See the beginning of the Section Further clarification and defense of infinitism of Klein (2006). 7 Obviously I m assuming that tracing out one s reasons involves basing one s beliefs on the further beliefs offered as reasons. But this seems eminently plausible given that this tracing out of reasons is supposed to contribute to doxastic justification, something that Klein thinks of as depending on one s holding the belief in question for the right reasons.

Philos Stud (2007) 134:19 24 23 serious problem with rejecting K2. The most serious problem is that it commits him to the view that a belief can be justified even if the reason one has for it (i.e., the belief it is based on or inferred from) is an unjustified belief! One of Klein s main complaints about foundationalism is that it makes justification inappropriately easy to obtain by saying that beliefs can be justified without reasons i.e., without being based on other beliefs. Klein thinks that, in order to be doxastically justified, all beliefs need to be based on reasons in the form of other beliefs. Given the spirit of his complaints against foundationalism, one would expect him to require these reasons to be good reasons. But apparently even bad reasons will do, since the reason can be an unjustified belief. 8 The suggestion that a belief can be doxastically justified via inference from an unjustified belief seems both highly implausible and contrary to the spirit of Klein s complaint that foundationalism makes justification too easy to come by. If, on the other hand, Klein accepts K2 along with K1, then he is committed to requiring for doxastic justification an infinite number of actual beliefs, each of which is based on another in a nonrepeating series. But it seems completely clear that none of us has an infinite number of actual beliefs, each of which is based on another in such a series. (As a response to this concern, Klein s claim that we have an infinite number of reasons available to us is beside the point.) I assume that the reason Klein doesn t accept K2 in his 2006 (even though doing so would be more in accord with his claim to be an infinitist about doxastic justification) is that he agrees with me that this would make him obviously committed to global skepticism. In defense of foundationalism Klein makes it clear that he thinks one important consideration in support of infinitism is that its most plausible competitor, foundationalism, is mistaken. I want to turn next, therefore, to his objection to foundationalism about doxastic justification. Klein asks us to imagine a conversation between Sally the Skeptic and Fred the Foundationalist. Fred begins by asserting p and Sally asks his reason for thinking p is true. Fred gives his reason r and Sally asks what his reason is for thinking r is true. This continues on until Fred mentions his belief b which is a basic reason, one which is not based on another belief. A foundationalist will think Fred needn t give or even have another belief on which b is based, for Fred s belief b can be justified noninferentially, in virtue of having some property F on which noninferential justification supervenes. 9 Here is Klein s response (from the Section Infinitism is the only alternative that can solve the regress problem of his 2006): Sally (or Fred s inner voice) can grant that b has F. But she now asks Fred to consider this question: Are propositions with F likely to be true? Fred has only three responses available if he is to remain acting as a responsible epistemic agent seeking to retain only those beliefs worthy of being retained. He could, of course, 8 In correspondence, Klein has said that not only does B s doxastic inferential justification not require the justification of the belief on which B is based, it also doesn t require that the person holding B have propositional justification for B s content (which can be had, according to Klein, only if that person has available an infinite number of nonrepeating reasons for B s content). Thus, he thinks S s belief B can be doxastically justified despite the fact that (a) S s belief B is based on an unjustified belief and (b) S lacks propositional justification for B s content. 9 For my views on how Fred should continue this discussion, see Bergmann (2004).

24 Philos Stud (2007) 134:19 24 get bored or see what s coming and flee reminiscent of some of the characters in a Platonic dialogue. The context is such that if Fred is interested in holding doxastically justified beliefs, these are his possible responses: 1. Propositions with F are not likely to be true. 2. It s just as likely that propositions with F are true as it is that they are not true. 3. Propositions with F are likely to be true. Notice that Klein is here making the following claim: K3: If Fred sees what is coming and refrains from making any of those three responses, he is holding unexamined beliefs and is not an epistemically responsible agent. K3 is a crucial component in Klein s response. If K3 is mistaken, then this objection to foundationalism doesn t go through. And K3 is mistaken. The foundationalist may be aware of Klein s claim that unexamined beliefs aren t worth having. However, as Klein notes, the foundationalist can see what s coming. For either the allegedly required examination could be satisfied by basing b on an unjustified belief or the allegedly required examination takes K2 for granted. But examination of one s beliefs that involves inference from an unjustified belief is clearly useless. And requiring examination that takes K2 for granted leads immediately to global skepticism, which makes such a requirement seem implausible. So Fred the foundationalist will reject Klein s examination requirement and refrain from asserting or believing any of 1 3. In doing so, he is not being an epistemically irresponsible agent. He s simply rejecting a highly implausible examination requirement. Thus K3 is false and Klein s objection to foundationalism doesn t go through. 10 References Annis, D. (1978). A contextualist theory of epistemic justification. American Philosophical Quarterly, 15, 213 219. Bergmann, M. (2004). What s NOT wrong with foundationalism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 68, 161 165. DeRose, K. (1992). Contextualism and knowledge attributions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 52, 913 929. Klein, P. (2006). Human Knowledge and the Infinite Progress of Reasoning. Philosophical Studies DOI: 10.1007/s11098-006-9012-9. Lewis, D. (1996). Elusive knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74, 549 567. Plantinga, A. (1993). Warrant: The current debate. New York: Oxford University Press. 10 Thanks to Jeffrey Brower and Michael Rea for comments on an earlier draft and to Peter Klein for many helpful conversations concerning his views.