Varieties of Goodness. Preliminary Issues for Value Pluralism

Similar documents
Goodness and Commensurability. Good, Bad, Better Worse

Substance as Essence. Substance and Definability

Potentialism about set theory

PHIL 202: IV:

Eden Lin Monism and Pluralism (for the Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Well-Being) January 1, 2015

Can logical consequence be deflated?

On Truth At Jeffrey C. King Rutgers University

Some proposals for understanding narrow content

SCHROEDER ON THE WRONG KIND OF

Moore on External Relations

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports. Stephen Schiffer New York University

On An Alleged Non-Equivalence Between Dispositions And Disjunctive Properties

Varieties of Value Incommensurability and Incomparability: A Defense of a Moderate Position

Entity Grounding and Truthmaking

A Defense of Contingent Logical Truths

Philosophy of Mind. Introduction to the Mind-Body Problem

From Grounding to Truth-Making: Some Thoughts

1. Introduction. Against GMR: The Incredulous Stare (Lewis 1986: 133 5).

Thompson on naive action theory

Williamson s proof of the primeness of mental states

book-length treatments of the subject have been scarce. 1 of Zimmerman s book quite welcome. Zimmerman takes up several of the themes Moore

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

In Defense of the Concept of Intrinsic Value, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 29 (1999):

On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology. In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with

Informational Models in Deontic Logic: A Comment on Ifs and Oughts by Kolodny and MacFarlane

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

Plato s Philosopher Kings. The Sun, Line, and Cave

The Connection between Prudential Goodness and Moral Permissibility, Journal of Social Philosophy 24 (1993):

AQUINAS S METAPHYSICS OF MODALITY: A REPLY TO LEFTOW

A guide to Anscombe s Intention, 1-31

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

PLEASESURE, DESIRE AND OPPOSITENESS

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

Rossian Totalism About Intrinsic Value

R. Keith Sawyer: Social Emergence. Societies as Complex Systems. Cambridge University Press

Imprint A PUZZLE FOR MODAL REALISM. Dan Marshall. volume 16, no. 19 november Lingnan University. Philosophers

Reply to Robert Koons

Saying too Little and Saying too Much. Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul

Stout s teleological theory of action

what makes reasons sufficient?

Saying too Little and Saying too Much Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul

Philosophy 125 Day 12: Overview

Coordination Problems

Comments on Carl Ginet s

In Defence Of Reductionism In Ethics 1. Frank Jackson

CHECKING THE NEIGHBORHOOD: A REPLY TO DIPAOLO AND BEHRENDS ON PROMOTION

There are three aspects of possible worlds on which metaphysicians

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism

Zimmerman, Michael J. Subsidiary Obligation, Philosophical Studies, 50 (1986):

Epistemicism, Parasites and Vague Names * vagueness is based on an untenable metaphysics of content are unsuccessful. Burgess s arguments are

Woodin on The Realm of the Infinite

Popper s Falsificationism. Philosophy of Economics University of Virginia Matthias Brinkmann

The Substance of Ontological Disputes. Richard C. Lamb

AN ACTUAL-SEQUENCE THEORY OF PROMOTION

MAKING A METAPHYSICS FOR NATURE. Alexander Bird, Nature s Metaphysics: Laws and Properties. Oxford: Clarendon, Pp. xiv PB.

McTAGGART'S PARADOX AND SMITH'S TENSED THEORY OF TIME

Philosophy of Mind. Introduction to the Mind-Body Problem

VAGUENESS. Francis Jeffry Pelletier and István Berkeley Department of Philosophy University of Alberta Edmonton, Alberta, Canada

Bob Hale: Necessary Beings

Conceptual idealism without ontological idealism: why idealism is true after all

Ethical non-naturalism

NOT SO PROMISING AFTER ALL: EVALUATOR-RELATIVE TELEOLOGY AND COMMON-SENSE MORALITY

Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 1)

REFERENCE AND MODALITY. An Introduction to Naming and Necessity

What s the Use of an Intrinsic Property? ¹

ON PROMOTING THE DEAD CERTAIN: A REPLY TO BEHRENDS, DIPAOLO AND SHARADIN

Intrinsic Properties Defined. Peter Vallentyne, Virginia Commonwealth University. Philosophical Studies 88 (1997):

MAKING "REASONS" EXPLICIT HOW NORMATIVE IS BRANDOM'S INFERENTIALISM? Daniel Laurier

The unity of the normative

A Refutation of Utilitarianism

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

Postmodal Metaphysics

Primary and Secondary Qualities. John Locke s distinction between primary and secondary qualities of bodies has

How and How Not to Take on Brueckner s Sceptic. Christoph Kelp Institute of Philosophy, KU Leuven

Commentary on Guarini

Made available courtesy of Wiley-Blackwell ***Note: Figures may be missing from this format of the document

Non-Cognitivism, Higher-Order Attitudes, and Stevenson s Do so as well!

Problematic Arguments for Comprehensive Values

Supervenience Arguments and Normative Non-naturalism

10. Presuppositions Introduction The Phenomenon Tests for presuppositions

The Subjective Domain. Nagel s Two Polarities

For the definitive version of this article, see Philosophical Studies. Normative Reasons as Good Bases

Shieva Kleinschmidt [This is a draft I completed while at Rutgers. Please do not cite without permission.] Conditional Desires.

All things considered duties to believe

Faith and Philosophy, April (2006), DE SE KNOWLEDGE AND THE POSSIBILITY OF AN OMNISCIENT BEING Stephan Torre

Hume's Is/Ought Problem. Ruse and Wilson. Moral Philosophy as Applied Science. Naturalistic Fallacy

Quantifiers: Their Semantic Type (Part 3) Heim and Kratzer Chapter 6

derosset, Louis (2013) "What is Weak Ground?," Essays in Philosophy: Vol. 14: Iss. 1, Article

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Transworld Identity or Worldbound Individuals? by Alvin Plantinga (excerpted from The Nature of Necessity, 1974)

Dialogue and UniversalismE Volume 2, Number 2/2011. Coping with Apparently Incomparable Alternatives Pluralism, Parity, and Justified Choice

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

BOOK REVIEWS AND NOTICES

Introduction: Belief vs Degrees of Belief

Truthmaking and Fundamentality. a.r.j. fisher

Naturalness Cian Dorr and John Hawthorne Forthcoming in Oxford Studies in Metaphysics

Transcription:

Varieties of Goodness Preliminary Issues for Value Pluralism

A Plausible Dubious Hypothesis The Comparability Claim (CC): x and y are comparable in respect of value property φ iff: (i) x and y are both φ and φ is applied univocally to x and y; or (ii) (a) x is φ* and y is φ** and there is some further value property ψ superordinate to φ* and φ**, and (b) ψ is applied univocally to φ* and φ**.

Some clarifications Comparable is used here in the sense of being ordinally rankable. After all, everything is comparable to everything else in some respect. A predicate φ is univocal as applied to x and y =df (i) x is φ and y is φ, and (ii) there exists a single, non-disjunctive, essence-specifying account of φ, as applied to x and y. Note, then, that univocity is both predicate-relative and prediction-instance relative. Predicate-relative: x and y can be univocally φ but non-univocally ψ. A statue of Pericles and Pericles can be univocally magnitudes but nonunivocally men. Predication-instance relative: x and y can be both univocally and non-univocally φ. Maria and Marcus can be both univocally and non-univocally flush, because both are blushing, and non-univocally flush, because she has plenty of cash and he is blushing.

Some Explications and Illustrations I The first clause of the definiens: (i) x and y are both φ and φ is applied univocally to x and y Illustrated with a non-value predicate: We can easily say, rightly or wrongly, that Matisse s Nu Bleu IV is bluer than the background of Della Robbia s Madonna and Child We can say not at all or only with difficulty or analogically that Matisse s s Nu Bleu IV is bluer than Camus Illustrated with a value predicate: We can easily say, rightly or wrongly, that supporting one s comrades in a dangerous battle is more honourable than deserting them in the same circumstances. We can say not at all or only with difficulty or analogically that supporting one s comrades in battle is more honourable than being the son of a Marquis or a maid of honour.

Some Explications and Illustrations II The second clause of the definiens: (a) x is φ* and y is φ** and there is some further value property ψ superordinate to φ* and φ**, and (b) ψ is applied univocally to φ* and φ** Illustrated with a non-value predicate: We can easily say, rightly or wrongly, that Rubik s cube is more complex than this puzzle in decision theory, because there are 43 quintillion permutations to the cube, and one needs at least twenty moves employing some 120 algorithms to solve it optimally, whereas the decision theory puzzle requires only six moves to be solved optimally. We can say not at all or only with difficulty or analogically that Rubik s Cube is more complex than the Mandy s situation with her ex. Illustrated with a value predicate: We can easily say, rightly or wrongly, that it is better to be a superb violinist than a mediocre advertising executive, since there is a superordinate value, namely (ceteris paribus) succeeding in one s chosen profession. We can say not at all or only with difficulty or analogically that it is better to be a superb violinist a good bread knife.

Some Preliminary Distinctions Absolute vs. Indexed Goods It is perhaps easiest to characterize the notion absolute goodness negatively: There is nothing which is simply good, or simply goodness itself the good simpliciter. Necessarily if x is good, then either (i) there is some K, where K is some kind or other, such that x is a good K; or (ii) x is good for someone or something. Put slightly more positively: Goodness is a simple, unanalyzable, property, irreducible to any other property or set of properties. (It might or might not be, as Moore thought, a non-natural property as well.)

Moorean Non-naturalism It may be true that all things which are good are also something else, just as it is true that all things which are yellow produce a certain kind of vibration in the light. And it is a fact, that Ethics aims at discovering what are those other properties belonging to all things which are good. But far too many philosophers have thought that when they named those other properties they were actually defining good; that these properties, in fact, were simply not "other," but absolutely and entirely the same with goodness. (Principia Ethica, 10, 3)

Conditional Care Perhaps we accept the following conditional as necessary: (α) Nec. (if x is the absolute good, then for some (possible) y, it is good for y to associate with x) From (α) it does not follow that there is no absolute goodness. It merely follows that if there is some absolute goodness, that necessarily, drawing near it would be good for some (possible) something or other So, possibly, (α) could be true even though indexed goods do not exhaust all goods.

Indexed and Non-indexed Goods If there is absolute goodness, than it is a (the) non-indexed good. By contrast, x is an indexed good x is good only if x is somehow sortal dependent or sortal relative, as indexed to some kind K or some interest-bearer: x might be good for seedlings but not good for human babies (e.g. having manure rich in nitrogen spread upon them) x might, in a more extended way, be good for some artefact, where the artefact is not an intrinsic interest bearer even though it is bad for some organism or other artefacts (e.g. a modest amount of humidity is good for a grand piano but bad for certain desert plants or potato crisps). x might be good as a K, but not good as a K* x might be a good baker but not a good diesel mechanic Here K may be, but need not be, a functional kind. So, x is a good knife i.e. a knife that performs the function of knives well. A good knife cuts well; it is not made a bad knife in view of the fact that is a poor screwdriver or no kind of seaworthy vessel.

Restating CC The Comparability Claim (CC): x and y are comparable in respect of value property φ iff: (i) x and y are both φ and φ is applied univocally to x and y; or (ii) (a) x is φ* and y is φ** and there is some further value property ψ superordinate to φ* and φ**, and (b) ψ is applied univocally to φ* and φ**.

Incommensurability and Incomparability for Value-bearers Incommensurability: x and y are incommensurable with respect to value property φ iff only if there exists no common cardinal measure providing a value scale along which x and y can be measured in respect of being-φ. Incomparability x and y are incomparable with respect to value property φ iff x and y cannot be put into ordinal rankings with respect to φ.

Incommensurability and Incomparability for Values Incommensurability: φ and ψ are incommensurable value properties iff there exists no superordinate value property ω providing a common cardinal value in terms of which φ and ψ can be measured in respect of being-ω. Incomparability φ and ψ are incomparable value properties iff there exists no superordinate value property ω providing a common value in terms of which φ and ψ can be ordinary ranked.

CC as a Plausible Hypothesis 1. Nec., any two values (or value-bearers) are comparable only if there is some univocal covering value, in terms of which they are to be compared. [Nothing is better than anything else simpliciter; there is always some φ in terms of which one thing is better than another.] 2. If (1), then CC. 3. So, CC.

CC as a Dubious Hypothesis Accept for now the Trichotomy Thesis, viz. that if x and y are comparable in respect of being φ, then x is either: (i) more-φ than y (better than y); (ii) less-φ than y (worse than y); or (iii) as-φ as y (equal to y in respect of being φ). Two Arguments: An Argument from the Diversity of Values An Argument from Small Improvements

The Diversity of Values An (alleged) observation: values belong to irreducibly distinct types or genres. So, e.g., the value of a good novel is not all like the value of keeping a promise, which in turn is not at all like the value of a freshly baked loaf of bread. This is Value Pluralism (VP) 1. If CC, then, on the assumption of TT, every value (or valuebearer) can be judged better, worse, or the same as one another. 2. If VP, then, again on the assumption of TT, not CC. 3. VP. 4. So, not CC.

Small Improvements Suppose two exemplary value bearers in different genres (e.g. Beethoven and Shakespeare, or Jussi Bjoerling and the Learned Hand) are equally great. 1. If CC, then if TT, then if we enhance the value of one state of affairs by even a little, then the one whose value is enhanced must come to be judged to be better than the other. 2. That s implausible. 3. So, either: not TT or not CC. 4. TT. 5. So, not CC.